The Good, the Bad, and the Grouch A Comparison of Characterization in Menander and Ancient Philosophers. By Matthew W. McDonald

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "The Good, the Bad, and the Grouch A Comparison of Characterization in Menander and Ancient Philosophers. By Matthew W. McDonald"

Transcription

1 The Good, the Bad, and the Grouch A Comparison of Characterization in Menander and Ancient Philosophers By Matthew W. McDonald

2 ἁλωτα γίνετ ἐπιμελείᾳ καὶ πόνῳ ἅπαντ All is attainable through care and work -Sostratos, Dyskolos Thanks to my father and mother, Dr. William Owens, Dr. Ruth Palmer, Dean Webster, Cary Frith, and all the faculty and staff members of the Department of Classics and World Religions and of the Honors Tutorial College ii

3 Table of Contents: Forward: My History with the Texts iv Chapter 1: Introduction The Background of Menander 1 The Study of Characterization 7 Characterization in Philosophy 16 Chapter 2: Character through Solitude and Friendship: An Analysis of the Dyskolos The Dyskolos in History and Scholarship 30 The Characters of Knemon, Kallippides, Sostratos, and Gorgias 40 Chapter 3: Character through Father and Son: An Analysis of the Samia The Samia in History and Scholarship 61 The Characters of Moschion and Demeas 69 Chapter 4: Conclusion 100 Bibliography 106 iii

4 Forward: My History with the Texts I was first introduced to Menander in the tenth grade, when I played Sostratos in my school s production of the Dyskolos. It is difficult to explain why exactly I became so fond of that play, I think most of my classmates found it boring; it was by no means gut-bustingly hilarious, nor was the plot particularly interesting. Yet, the characters had a certain undeniable charm; the lover was endearingly naïve; the country-boy was unexpectedly profound; the slaves were deviously clever; and the titular grumpy old man embodied the sympathetic villain. The essence of the play was in these characters. It was also while in high school that I was introduced to Plato and Aristotle. While I might not have always agreed with their discussions of ethics and virtues, I was fascinated by their arguments and the idea that these subjective topics could be explored in a logical and precise manner. One thing that I particularly found interesting was the emphasis they had on behavior and emotions in relation to morality; character also was the essence of their topics. iv

5 Chapter 1: Introduction The Background of Menander Menander enjoyed a successful career. Not only did he produce a significant number of works during his thirty year career, having written over an estimated one hundred plays, but he received at least eight victories at dramatic festivals. 1 Menander was not only a prolific exponent of [New Comedy] but he was also, according to ancient authors its star. 2 In addition to being popular during his own time, his plays were adapted for Roman audiences by playwrights like Plautus and Terence. 3 While the mere fact that Menander was able to write places him among the elite minority, his plays were performed at public festivals before an audience of the broad Athenian populace, consisting of men from various social classes and possibly women and slaves. 4 Unlike his dramatic predecessors, however, Menander was not limited to Athenian audiences. His plays were not performed only once at a festival, but went on tour in Greek and Hellenistic city-states. 5 This new professionalism 1 Sebastiana Nervegna, Menander in Antiquity, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013), Susan Lape, Reproducing Athens, (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2004), 9 3 Ibid. 4 Eric Csapo, Performing Comedy in the Fifth through Early Third Centuries, in The Oxford Handbook of Greek and Roman Comedy, ed. Michael Fontaine and Adele C. Scafuro, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014), 53 5 Michael J. Walton and Peter D. Arnott, Menander and the Making of Comedy, (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1996), 34 1

6 enlarged the scope of the theatre and brought it to wider audiences. 6 Menander was the star of Greek theater when everybody was watching. Early in the modern era, Menander was not particularly esteemed in comparison to other classical authors. It was Euripides who fought this death struggle of tragedy; the later art is known as the New Attic Comedy. In it the degenerate form of tragedy lived on as a monument of the most painful and violent death of tragedy proper, wrote Friedrich Nietzsche in The Birth of Tragedy. 7 When only fragments of Menander remained, scholars were quick to dismiss it as trivial literature. In comparison to the Old Comedy of Aristophanes, which was known for its quick-wit, inventive language, and controversial political commentary, scholars viewed New Comedy as a degraded genre. The jokes are subtler, the language is milder, and the topics cover mundane elements of domestic life, rather than contemporary events. 8 New Comedy may in certain respects be described as the Old tamed down, but in products of genius, tameness is not generally considered a merit, wrote A.W. Schlegel in Lectures on Dramatic Literature and Art. 9 Until the 1950 s, the works of Menander were known through fragments of lines, quotes from ancient sources, and Roman adaptations. However, after more substantial remnants of his plays were found, critical opinion changed. A more comprehensive assessment of these plays shows that they often involve the same story 6 Walton and Arnott, Menander and the Making of Comedy, 35 7 Quoted by Sander M. Goldberg, The Making of Menander s Comedy (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1980), v 8 Walton and Arnott, Menander and the Making of Comedy, Quoted by Goldberg, The Making of Menander s Comedy, v 2

7 of a young man who overcomes obstacles to get the girl he loves. 10 While this formulaic plot leaves little room for diversity in terms of plot and character, modern scholars have found value investigating how Menander either repeats specific dramatic conventions or how he varies them. Ian Ruffell makes a point at noting that Menander regularly adapts the stock characters of Middle Comedy into his own works, but individualizes them according to his own style. 11 Likewise, Netta Zagagi remarks that valuing artistic merit based on originality is a modern tendency and that this quality was never particularly valued by ancient audiences, on the contrary, variations on a given theme were far more likely to stimulate the imagination. 12 The reliance and repetition of tropes certainly was not lost on the ancient audience either. Plutarch preserves an ancient anecdote in which a friend asks Menander, The Dionysian Festival is near, have you written your comedy? To which Menander reportedly replied, By the gods, I have written the comedy; for the plot is in order; but I just need to fit the lines to it. (Plut. Mor. 347e). The use of stock characters, in particular, is recognized to be an important component of Menander s plays. 13 In essence a stock character is a dramatic stereotype; characters of the same age, class, and occupation, thus, find themselves in similar circumstances and behave in similar ways. The very presentation of stock characters suggests familiarity to the audience. It is well known from vase paintings 10 Lape, Reproducing Athens, Ian Ruffell, Character types, in The Cambridge Companion to Greek Comedy, ed. Martin Revermann, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2014), Netta Zagagi, The Comedy of Menander, (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 1995), R.L. Hunter, The New Comedy of Greece & Rome, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985), 59 3

8 and the writings of Julius Pollux that actors wore masks while performing Greek comedy. Each mask was designed to be used with a specific type of character. So while each character looked unique within the context of the play, he would resemble all other characters of the same stock type. 14 Stock characters would also be discernable by the way they spoke; for instance, the cook calls himself the cuisinier and makes puns about chopping. 15 Stock characters are central in the discussion of repetition and variation of dramatic conventions, because the presence of a stock character anticipates certain dramatic expectations, which the playwright can either follow or alter. The scholarship about stock types in Menander enhances the discussion of the author s characterization in terms of dramatic theory, but keeps the conversation entirely within the context of his plays. Several scholars have expanded this discussion through reference to Aristotle s works on ethics and rhetoric. David Konstan has discussed how Glykera s pardon of Polemon fails to satisfy Aristotle s definition of forgiveness. As Konstan argues, Polemon s apology to Glykera does not address his moral flaw nor does he demonstrate a change in character. In turn, Glykera does not return to Polemon because of this apology. Rather, the reconciliation of the couple is due to the revelation that Glykera, who had been serving as a courtesan, is actually a citizen. Glykera the courtesan, was not under the legal and social restrictions that bound citizen women; Glykera, the citizen woman, has no 14 Csapo, Performing Comedy, E.W. Handley, The Conventions of the Comic Stage and Their Exploitation by Menander, in Oxford Readings in Menander, Plautus, and Terence, ed. Erich Segal, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001), 30 4

9 choice but to accept Polemon. Given her new social status she would be rejected by society for having had extramarital affairs. Konstan argues that this resolution is unsatisfactory from an Aristotelian point of view and suggests Menander s indifference to repairing the relationship of the two characters in a manner pertinent to their disagreement. 16 Susan Lape similarly remarks that Polemon s apology to Glykera is not a proper apology in the Aristotelian sense. She adds, however, that, the quasi- Aristotelian characterization of his action serves the dramatic purpose of allowing him to escape the full, opprobrious connotations of his behavior. 17 She concludes that the presentation of Polemon s misdeed as a mistake covers for Glykera s lack of a formal pardon. 18 R.L. Hunter notes ethical situations in Menander that reflect Aristotle s ethical thinking. In the Perikeiromene, Menander presents the Aristotelian quandary of where responsibility lies in an action in the case of an action done in ignorance. Hunter notes that this question about voluntary and involuntary errors is a theme to which both Aristotle and Menander often turn. He further notes an additional connection between Aristotle and Menander through Terence s Adelphoe, a Roman adaptation of Menander: Here we find many themes in common between Aristotle and Menander: the respective roles of shame and fear in education, whether young men should be given their head or not, the rejection of unbending dogmatism and the advocacy of a 16 David Konstan, Between Courtesan and Wife, Phoenix 41, no. 4 (1987): Lape, Reproducing Athens, Lape, Reproducing Athens,

10 flexible and open approach to human relationships. 19 Hunter asserts that it is easy to see how the Aristotelian notion that a virtue is the adherence to the mean between two extremes come into effect in this play. He suggests that it might be helpful to analyze Menander s plays in Aristotelian terms. He concludes that Peripatetic ethics and New Comedy both developed around the same time and they both are concerned with how man functions in society. He urges that if one is reminiscent of the other it does not necessary mean that they are dependent upon each other, but rather this similarity confirms the reality of the social and moral patterns which both assume. 20 In this way, Hunter asserts that the shared themes and presentations of morality between Menander and Aristotle reflect the contemporary social view of ethics. 21 Modern scholars were not the first to draw a connection between Menander and philosophy. Plutarch, in his Comparison of Aristophanes and Menander, writes and just as painters, when their eyes are tired, turn to the colors of the flowers and grass, so to philosophers and men of learning Menander is a rest from their concentrated and intense studies (Plut. Mor. 854c). Konstan observes that Plutarch here seems to have in mind Aristotle s assertion that good taste as a characteristic of comedy, reflects the virtue of temperance. 22 When Aristotle is brought into the reading of Menander, there is a tendency to focus the discussion on ethics and 19 Hunter, The New Comedy, Ibid. 21 Hunter, The New Comedy, David Konstan, Crossing Conceptual Worlds: Greek Comedy and Philosophy, in The Oxford Handbook of Greek and Roman Comedy, ed. Michael Fontaine and Adele C. Scafuro, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014), 292 6

11 morality in the plays. In this regard, the comparison between characterization in Menander and Aristotle caters more to a discussion of philosophy than of theater. Thus previous discussion of Menander s characterization has either focused on characterization strictly within the tenure of dramatic conventions, or considered Menander in the context of the ethical philosophy of his day, but with a focus on the philosophy rather than the drama. I explore the area between these two discussions. My question then is how does characterization in Menander s plays compare to ideas about characterization in the works of ancient philosophers strictly as a literary device? The Study of Characterization Before I continue I want to elaborate on what I mean by characterization. The term itself is difficult to define because the purpose and function of character changes not only throughout different genres, but also over time. As such, modern dramaturgy often is more compelled to depict characters with a more rounded internal psychology than ancient drama, which is more concerned with exploring normative ethics. 23 Ian Ruffell asserts that such a stance draws heavily on Aristotelian ideas of êthos and reacts against psychoanalysis. 24 In this sense, it is useful to compare these two genres in terms of their characterization, because both approach character with similar objectives. 23 Ian Ruffell, Character types, Ibid. 7

12 Ancient and modern scholars have distinguished two broad techniques of characterization: direct and indirect. 25 Koen De Temmerman distinguishes the two techniques: Whereas the former describe character explicitly through overt evaluation or the attribution of characteristics and epithets, the latter leave the characteristics themselves implicit and merely provide attributes from which they can (and should) be inferred. 26 De Temmerman, however, provides a caveat that direct characterization does not automatically exclude inference on the part of the reader, but rather social and cultural contexts must usually be considered. 27 Furthermore, it is necessary to acknowledge that there are various techniques within the category of indirect characterization itself. 28 The types of indirect characterization, because their general technique is based on implication, generally rely on cultural assumptions and associations. For example, one type of indirect characterization is established through comparison or paradigm. According to ancient writers comparison involves juxtaposition with objects and animals, while paradigm involves historical, mythical, or literary persons. Such a method of characterization was highly dependent upon the contemporary audience s ideas about the specific comparandum in use. 29 Another indirect technique is what De Temmerman calls metonymical characterization. According to ancient rhetorical theory metonymic characterization 25 Koen De Temmerman, Crafting Characters, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014), Ibid. 27 De Temmerman, Crafting Characters, Ibid. 29 De Temmerman, Crafting Characters, 34 8

13 relies upon six techniques: emotion, group membership, action, speech, appearance, and setting. Emotion, as a form of metonymical characterization, is distinct from êthos, permanent characteristics, and is classified as pathos, temporary feelings, which are more easily influenced than êthos. This distinction is important to note, because êthos is more an aspect of character than of characterization. Group association is subdivided into different categories: macro-social group (fatherland/city), micro-social group (birth/ social station/ parents/ wealth), and educated-intellectual peer group (upbringing/education). Like the metaphorical methods of characterization, these group associations depend upon contemporaneous biases and may imply moral evaluations. Actions as a means of characterization reflects the ethical theory that êthos is deductive from observable praxis. Speech also constructs character either through the representation of one character through the words of another or the speaker s depiction of himself. Physical appearance as an indication of character is related to the ancient study of physiognomy. Physical appearance has the potential to depict both the êthos and pathos of a character, depending on whether such an appearance suggests either a persistent or temporary personal quality. Lastly, setting can be important for characterization, although it is scarcely contemplated in ancient rhetorical theory, despite being considered one of the basic narrative components. Setting differs from the macro-social group associations in that a place is relevant to the latter as part of the character s essence, whence he comes, whereas the former considers a place in regards to the character s current location, where he is; place in terms of macro-social group association is stagnate for a character, but in terms of 9

14 setting place varies for a character relative to the current narrative situation. De Temmerman, however, additionally notes that setting has the ability to characterize through similarity, and as such functions as metaphorical characterization. Therefore, setting as a technique for characterization shares qualities of both metaphorical and metonymical characterization. 30 De Temmerman also acknowledges another more overt technique for characterization, name-giving and antonomasia. Name-giving practices characterization through the meaning of a character s name, while he defines antonomasia as the substitution of a proper name by a word or paraphrase. 31 Namegiving and antonomasia distinguish themselves as a characterization technique by being direct statements of character, which are made by a title, rather than explicit description of characteristics. 32 Menander practices all of these techniques in his creation of characters. In the Dyskolos and Samia there are examples, which demonstrate how Menander uses these methods of characterization. Name-giving is fairly common as a means of characterization in New Comedy, as specific names were frequently used for individual stock types. 33 These stock names typically denote that a character belongs to a certain social class and these designations are based on the roots of the name. 34 For instance, a Kallippides would 30 De Temmerman, Crafting Characters, De Temmerman, Crafting Characters, De Temmerman, Crafting Characters, Ruffell, Character types, Csapo, Performing Comedy, 60 10

15 be a rich man, because the ippides ending, which comes from the word ἵππος, meaning horse, implies that he belongs to the upper-class. The name Gorgias, from the word γεωργός, which means farmer, typically is ascribed to a rustic character. Likewise, often a young man will be named Moschion, coming from the word μοσχίον which means little calf, because of his youth and uncontrolled passions. 35 There are several ways that Menander uses direct characterization. One way is by explicit statement of character as the author, such as the case with the Dyskolos, where Menander tells the audience Knemon s character through the title. Direct characterization, however, can also be found within the context of the play either by characters proclaiming the characteristics of others, such as when Pan calls Knemon δύσκολος (7), or self-identification of character, such as when Knemon calls himself δύσκολος (747). Menander also provides examples of antonomasia, substitution of a proper name by a word or paraphrase, 36 like when Getas calls Knemon a gray-haired viper (ἔχις πολιὸς, 480). Metaphorical characterization is not too common in Menander, as might be expected considering New Comedy typically refrains from referencing specific people. 37 There are, however, still some instances in which Menander uses metaphorical characterization. Knemon compares the sacrificers at the shrine to man-eating beasts (ἀνδροφόνα θηρί, 481). There are also some instances in which 35 Ibid. 36 De Temmerman, Crafting Characters, Walton and Arnott, Menander and the Making of Comedy, 3 11

16 Menander uses paradigm, like when Nikeratos compares Moschion to Thyestes, Oedipus, and Tereus (667-8J). Likewise, Menander practices the various methods of metonymical characterization. Emotion is regularly used by Menander as part of his characterization. For instance, Moschion is often shown to be afraid or Knemon is frequently portrayed as angry. Group association as a form of characterization comes in three forms: the macro-social group, the micro-social group, and the educated-intellectual group. The macro-social group, which relates to fatherland and city, can be seen in the title of the Samia and throughout the play when Chrysis is referred to as the Samian woman. The aspects from the micro-social group, which are noble birth, social station, parentage, and wealth, are frequently featured in both the Dyskolos and Samia. Some examples include Sostratos mentioning his father is Kallippides (773), Moschion mentioning his public offices and services (22-5J), Moschion being Demeas adopted son (518J), and Gorgias mentioning that he is poor (296). The educated-intellectual peer group, which consists of one s upbringing and education, is also mentioned by Moschion in the prologue (16J). According to ethical theory actions are an observable presentation of êthos. As it might be assumed, as a common element of drama, actions as a type of metonymical characterization occur often in Menander s plays, for instance when Knemon beats slaves (111 and 515) or when Moschion pretends to be a soldier (863J). 12

17 Speech also is a frequent type of characterization in Menander, as would be expected in drama. Relevant examples include when Knemon curses (108), when he says perhaps (713, 730, and 746), or when Demeas refers to himself in the second person (522J). Physical appearance as a form of characterization is a little harder to discern from a text, but it was definitely an important aspect of the dramatic presentation of Menander s plays. The use of masks was directly related to characterization and would have been a device for the audience to presume aspects of character. 38 The use of props would also contribute to characterization through appearance. The last type of characterization is setting. Menander practices both metonymical and metaphorical characterization by setting. For instance, the rural location of the Dyskolos plays a metonymical role in the characterization of Knemon (129-30), but also the description of the land as being difficult and barren (3-4) characterizes Knemon through metaphor. 39 As a genre New Comedy relied on stock types, and so they play an essentially relevant role in understanding characterization in Menander. 40 E.W. Handley distinguishes three types of conventions which contribute to the establishment of stock types: language (vocabulary, phrasing, meter), theatrical performance (masks, costumes, props), and representation of real life (details of characters lives, locations, time-settings). 41 These conventions are among the various types of dramatic 38 Ruffell, Character Types, Lape, Reproducing Athens, Hunter, The New Comedy, Handley, The Conventions of the Comic Stage,

18 techniques that De Temmerman acknowledges are part of metonymical characterization: respectively, speech, appearance, and group association and setting. The use of stock types provides some of the implicit elements of character, which are part of indirect characterization. Yet, while Menander uses stock characters, he does not strictly adhere to all their dramatic expectations, but relies on variation. As Ian Ruffell states, It seems that Menander largely plays against expectations not so much to reverse expectations as to enrich characterization both of the typical characters themselves and those with whom they are interacting. 42 Menander does not only emphasize these social attributes in his presentation of characters, but focuses heavily on their emotions as well. In fact, much of the individuality of his characters comes from their unique emotional traits. 43 Furthermore, while the basic structure of Menander s plots might be formulaic, his dramatic variation often relies upon differing behaviors and reactions among stock types. In Menandrean comedy it is not so much what happens that matters, but how. 44 It is in his variations from dramatic conventions, that Menander exhibits the other techniques of metonymical characterization: emotion and action. My intention is to analyze how Menander characterizes six characters in the Dyskolos and Samia, four from the former play and two from the latter; that is, how he demonstrates the behaviors of his characters are affected by their social traits and emotions. I will then compare Menander s style of characterization to characterization 42 Ruffell, Character types, A.W. Gomme and F.H. Sandbach, Menander: A Commentary, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1973), Handley, The Conventions of the Comic Stage, 41 14

19 as presented by ancient philosophers. The philosophers I will use for comparison are Plato, Aristotle, and Theophrastus. As a student, Menander studied at the Lyceum under Theophrastus, who was a student of Aristotle, who was a student of Plato. 45 Besides this historical connection, the works of these authors themselves lend to comparison. As noted, authors have associated Menander with the philosophy of Aristotle for over a thousand years. Theophrastus Characters provides a list of various stock types that seem dramatic in nature and presentation. Lastly, the dialogues of Plato are recognized for their dramatic qualities. 46 Menander is thus connected to these philosophers through biography and through an interest in human character. The method of my comparison will be through a systematic evaluation of character. I will identify key characteristics of the relevant characters from Menander s plays. These characteristics will include attributes relating to êthos, consistent emotional and behavioral temperaments, as well as accidental attributes, such as age and social class. I will demonstrate the various ways in which Menander portrays these characteristics, such as through actions, speech, or emotional displays. After demonstrating how Menander portrays these characteristics, I will observe whether these same characteristics are discussed by any of the three philosophers and compare how the philosophers presentation of character compares to Menander s. 45 T.B.L. Webster, Studies in Menander, (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1960), 4 46 Richard Hunter, Plato and the Traditions of Ancient Literature, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012), 3 15

20 I want to emphasize that my thesis is strictly a comparison of characterization as it appears in the works of Menander and these philosophers and I am not asserting that Menander is using these philosophical texts as precedent for characterization. I intend to show that there are similarities in their styles of characterization, but also differences. In short, the goal of this thesis is to discuss characterization in Menander and to compare to ideas about characterization in the philosophers. Characterization in Philosophy Before I move onto characterization in Menander, it would be beneficial to develop an idea of characterization in the philosophers. The relevant discussions appear in Book VIII and the beginning of Book IX of Plato s Republic, Theophrastus Characters, and Books III and IV of Aristotle s Nicomachean Ethics and Book II of the Rhetoric. De Temmerman asserts that character typification is an important feature in ancient ethical philosophy and rhetoric as well as the ancient novel. He states that Aristotle, in his ethical works, offers the first systematic treatment of typified characters. 47 In the Nicomachean Ethics character is presented as being dependent upon a system of virtues and vices. In this sense, there is an obvious connection being made between character and morality, with certain types of character being presented as morally superior. Characterization in ethical philosophy is presented through 47 De Temmerman, Where Philosophy and Rhetoric Meet: Character Typification in the Greek Novel, in Philosophical Presences in the Ancient Novel, ed. J.R. Morgan and Meriel Jones, (Gronigen: Barkhuis; Gronigen University Library, 2007), 86 16

21 human emotions and behaviors, rather than socially based attributes. However, the ancient philosophers too noted the social dimension of character. In ancient rhetoric too, characterization was more a matter of conforming to (often morally significant) ready-made stock types than of psychological individuation. 48 De Temmerman supports the notion that stock types are directly related to characterization, but additionally notes that these stereotypes may be imbued with ethical or moral value. He comments that in Aristotle s Rhetoric characterization logically follows from an orator s need to address a certain character type. 49 Although the Rhetoric is not explicitly a work of ethical philosophy, characterization of this sort is still dependent upon morality. De Temmerman also notes the connection between morality and characterization based upon stock types in Theophrastus Characters. The Characters, while a work dealing with stock types, is greatly indebted to Aristotle s ethical works. 50 The exact purpose of Theophrastus work is debated among scholars. However, it is agreed that the Characters cannot have been intended as a full exploration of ethical philosophy, lacking, as it does, virtuous characters and any analysis of the connection between character and behavior. 51 The Characters seems to have been written as a rhetorical guide for students to identify and understand 48 De Temmerman, Where Philosophy and Rhetoric Meet, Ibid. 50 De Temmerman, Where Philosophy and Rhetoric Meet, Jeffrey Rusten, trans. and ed. Characters, by Theophrastus, in Theophrastus: Characters, Herodas: Mimes, Cercidas and the Choliambic Poets, ed. and trans. Jeffrey Rusten, et al. (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993),

22 character. 52 Theophrastus seems interested in how his characters interact with society and how they affect their fellow citizens. In the Ethics, Aristotle considers happiness and what it means to be happy. Since humans are distinct from other animals in rationality, the highest Good would be an action most in accordance with virtue, being the goodness of rationality. There are a few important premises on which he bases his argument. First, the soul has two parts: the rational and the irrational. The irrational soul has vegetative and appetitive aspects to it. The vegetative aspect, which is concerned with nourishment and growth, is purely instinctual and has no role in virtue. The appetitive aspect of soul, however, rules one s impulses and desires. The rational part of the soul, then is responsible for maintaining these impulses. Next, Aristotle distinguishes between intellectual and moral virtues; the former are virtues which can be learnt through instruction, but the latter virtues can only be learned through practice. He defines moral virtue as a settled disposition (ἓξις προαιρετική, 1107a) observant to the mean of two extremes relative to us, which would be determinable by any prudent man (φρόνιμος, 1107a). As he defines it, a moral virtue is a type of character; it is a habit (ἤθος, 1103a) in regards to actions and feelings. While all moral virtues are character types, the reverse is not true. Aristotle s definition of moral virtue as a mean between two extremes, implies that for every virtuous character, there are two additional unvirtuous characters. Aristotle provides one last stipulation before discussing the different virtues, that in 52 D.J. Furley, The Purpose of Theophrastus Characters. Symbolae Osloenses 30, no. 1 (1953): 60 18

23 order for an action to be judged in regards to virtue, it must be done by choice; it must be done voluntarily and willingly. In Books III and IV of the Ethics, Aristotle systematically demonstrates his definition by presenting different virtues and the qualities to which they are the means, along with the excessive and deficient characters that accompany each virtue. It is interesting to note that he provides certain scenarios in which these virtues apply. For instance, courage is a virtue that is concerned with fear and confidence. The deficiency of courage is considered cowardice, while the excess is recklessness. Therefore, as a virtue, courage is in the middle between these two extremes. Often a man can be courageous in battle. Aristotle, however, recognizes that bravery in battle is not necessarily true courage, because there are penalties for cowardice, and so often these acts of bravery are not done voluntarily. Likewise, some acts, done out of passion, resemble courage, like animals charging hunters or adulterers proceeding boldly. Yet such actions are done out of appetite and not for the sake of courage as its own pursuit, and so they cannot be called courage. Furthermore, anyone who faces danger bravely, but is unaware of the severity of the danger, cannot be said to have courage, because his ignorance disqualifies his bravery from being voluntary (1106b-9b). Aristotle describes temperance as being related to pleasure and pain; overindulgence is the excess, while the deficiency is rather uncommon. Aristotle sees licentiousness in adults and the naughtiness of children to be the primary examples of the excess in relation to temperance, whereas the virtue itself is a result of a disciplined participation in pleasures. Overindulgence is a more voluntary vice than 19

24 cowardice, because it is not rooted in a basic instinct for survival, but rather, by its nature, is participating in something beyond necessity. As for the rare instances of a deficiency of pleasure, a person with such quality is unable to find pleasure in things which he ought, though Aristotle has no designated term for such a person (1117b-9b). Aristotle considers courage and temperance to be the two major virtues, but also denotes several lesser virtues. These include virtues such as liberality, honesty, friendliness, and gentleness. He describes these lesser virtues and their associated behaviors and corresponding vices. Of these lesser virtues, friendliness and gentleness and their corresponding vices will be relevant in comparison with Menander. Aristotle concludes his survey of virtue with an analysis of the ultimate virtue, justice. Justice is defined as taking the appropriate course of action; by its nature it is the mean between two extremes, which is what qualified all the other virtues. In this way, the practice of virtue is also the practice of justice (1129a-30a). In the Ethics every character type falls onto a spectrum of morality, in which some characters are inherently virtuous and others are inherently defective. Character is revealed through deliberate choice. The only actions that reveal character are the ones that are purposely made by the person. This analysis appears to ignore social aspects of character. However, a normative social status has been assumed the male citizen. In his definition of moral virtue, Aristotle qualifies the statement that it is a mean by saying relative to us (πρὸς ἡμᾶς, 1107a). These virtues and vices describe generic character types, rather than individuals Susan Sauvé Meyer, Aristotle on Moral Responsibility (Cambridge, MA: Blackwell Publishers, 1993), 30 20

25 In the Ethics Aristotle s analysis of characterization focuses on the internal foundation of character, rather than the resulting behavior. 54 He takes a different approach in Book II of the Rhetoric. His analysis there distinguishes two separate categories: emotions and social attributes, which Aristotle calls ages and fortunes (τὰς ἡλικίας καὶ τὰς τύχας, 1388b). He describes each emotion first with a short definition. Then he offers examples of circumstances that cause a person to experience such an emotion, followed by examples of the types of people who instigate that emotional state. For instance, he defines anger as desire for revenge, accompanied by pain, for a real or apparent undeserved slight, which affects the man himself or his loved ones (1378a). He then says that a person can become angry if he is denied something which he wants or needs, like a thirsty man being denied water. Furthermore, when a person is in need, he is easily angered when a person makes light of his suffering. Additionally, men can become angry when the event which pains them happens contrary to their expectations. These are the conditions under which a person feels angry (1379a). Aristotle also provides examples of people with whom a person is angry. Such people include those who mock the person or his loved ones, those who speak poorly of something which the person loves, those who treat the person poorly if they are inferior, and those who do not realize that they are hurting the person (1379a-1380a). This is the method he uses for characterization in regards to emotions and repeats for calmness, friendship, enmity, fear, confidence, shame, favor, pity, 54 De Temmerman, Where Philosophy and Rhetoric Meet, 87 21

26 indignation, envy, and jealousy. Although many of these emotions are similar to virtues and vices he describes in the Ethics, he is not presenting them as ethical philosophy, but rather is just presenting them as observations of their conditions and behaviors. Aristotle s analysis of the emotions of anger, friendship, fear, and shame will be relevant to the discussion of character in Menander. The next section of the Rhetoric is devoted to attributes dealing with age and fortune (1388b). Since these attributes are accidental qualities rather than consequential qualities, Aristotle does not focus on the conditions which cause these attributes, but rather focuses exclusively on the behaviors associated. Aristotle separates age into three distinct phases of life: youth, old age, and prime of life. He first describes young men and gives various examples of their personalities and behaviors. The young man has little control of his passions and appetites; his passions are easily triggered, but are not persistent. He is ambitious and eager and maintains unbroken optimism. He is an idealist and wants to do what he believes is noble, rather than what is realistic or in his best interest. In general, his mistakes are resultant of acting in excess (1389a-b). Meanwhile, the old man, in many regards, acts as the reverse of the young. He is rather pessimistic and lacks confidence and vigor. He often qualifies his speech with perhaps and maybe (ἴσως καὶ τάχα, 1389b). He is ill-tempered and grumpy and is weak in his emotions. He desires nothing more than that which is necessary and is extremely frugal with his money. He is overly found of himself and cares more for his own interests than nobility. His appetites are not easily evoked, but rather he is 22

27 moved by profit, which makes his character rather calculating. Lastly, he is prone to pity, on account of his feebleness and fragility (1389b-1390a). Aristotle does not give much detail about the man in his prime, but simply describes him as having qualities which are intermediate between the young and old men. He says that during this time a man possesses all the advantages of both youth and old age and deficiencies and excesses are replaced by moderation. He reasons that in his prime, man has the energy and optimism of youth, but the experience and expedience of old age (1390a-b). Aristotle divides fortune into three categories: birth, wealth, and power. He limits his discussion of fortune by only describing those with good fortune, so he ignores those born in families of no repute, with little wealth, and with little political influence. The man with good birth is characterized by being ambitious, desiring to add on to the reputation of his ancestors. He is also rather foolish and not necessarily noble, for he inherited his advantages, rather than earned them for himself (1390b). The wealthy man is often arrogant, on account of his wealth, for he considers wealth to be a great good, of which he has much. Additionally he indulges in luxury and is unaware of the fact that others lack his same advantages. He also believes himself worthy of power and authority, since he believes that wealth is what makes one fit to rule. Aristotle also notes that there is a difference in character between those who were born rich and those who came into wealth later in life, the latter being more prone to vices due to inexperience and lack of education (1391a). The last type man of fortune is the man with power. This man is more ambitious and virile than the rich 23

28 man and his endeavors are more serious and he does them with greater intensity. Likewise, if he commits a crime it will be one that is more severe (1391a-b). While the descriptions of the emotions are accompanied by a psychological evaluation of their origin, overall the discussion of character in the Rhetoric is directed by anecdotal illustrations. These illustrations, however, are akin to drama, because they imagine individuals acting on the basis of character. Theophrastus Characters provides another example of character presented through anecdote. The structure of the Characters is straightforward. Each chapter is about some specific personality and offers examples of the behaviors typical of a person with such a personality. Most of the chapters begin with a definition of the personality. However, as Jeff Rusten notes, these definitions come from other sources, such as Aristotle s Nicomachean Ethics and Eudemian Ethics, not from Theophrastus himself. 55 What he lacks in definitions and psychological explanations, he compensates for with vivid description of behavior. The result is that his characters in themselves are rather dramatic. Each description is composed of small scenes of action and conflict caused by the characters and it is not difficult to imagine them appearing within the context of a play. Of the Theophrastus thirty different characters, three are relevant to the characters in the Dyskolos and Samia: Αὐθαδεία ( grouchiness, character fifteen), Ἀπιστία ( mistrust, character eighteen), and Δειλία ( cowardice, character twenty-five). 55 Rusten, Characters, 53 24

29 Plato s analysis of character appears in Books VIII and IX of the Republic (543a-592b). There Plato uses characters as representations of different systems of governance, which in turn he relates to different types of souls. The discussion is schematized. There is a general sequence of events with a pattern to them. Plato begins with a type of constitution, reflected in a father and a son. Various influences and experiences specific to that particular constitution alter the son s personality. The son comes to represent a new system of government. For instance, the oligarch is miserly and illiberal. His son, denied his father s generosity, is neglected a proper education. The son comes into contact with the lower-classes of the city, whom Plato calls the drones. These drones urge the son to indulge in his desires and to spend his money carelessly. Thus the son develops the democratic soul, which has little control over his passions. This degradation of the soul begins with the aristocratic type followed by the timocratic, then the oligarchic, then the democratic until there is the son who represents tyranny, or total corruption. Of these constitutions, the oligarchic, democratic, and tyrannical have possible relevance for Menander. Of particular interest is Plato s emphasis on causation in the development of character. Each character undergoes three phases of character development: he inherits the traits of his father; he is influenced by society; he develops his own unique traits. There is an explicit schematization of the process, by which a character becomes such as he is. Plato extends his examination of the development of character, by exploring the psychological implications of the personality types. In Book IV, he had established that the soul consists of three parts: the logical, the emotional, and the 25

30 appetitive (436a-b). The appetitive part of the soul is broken down into two subcategories: necessary appetites and unnecessary appetites. In Plato s model, the logical part of the soul is the best, then the emotional, then the appetitive, with necessary appetites being better than unnecessary ones. Each variety of character is defined by which part of the soul the person values most. The relation between these characters and the different parts of the soul, which have different moral value, implies a hierarchy of character. In fact, it seems to be one of Plato s efforts to distinguish certain characters as being objectively superior to others, as are different constitutions. Certain elements of The Republic seem to lend themselves well to a theatrical interpretation. 56 The characters do not exist in a vacuum, but are presented within the context of their family and society. Furthermore, Plato provides a series of mini-plots in which his characters play roles. Although his characters represent anthropomorphized constitutions, Plato adds a dimension of realism that makes his characters seem believable by presenting them in the context of a story. For example, the man with the timocratic soul has some interest in the arts, but is not skilled in practicing them. He is severe towards slaves, but civil towards free men and reverent towards authority. He believes that military acumen should determine political power and considers physical and athletic prowess to be the more 56 Cf. Nikos G. Charalabopoulos, Platonic Drama and Its Ancient Reception (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012), 19, who argues that features of [Plato s] dialogues point to an underlying dialectics with dramatic poetry, exemplified by comment on and appropriation of dramatic techniques and conventions. 26

31 important than intellect. Also, as a child he would not care for materialism, but as he grows up he accumulates and hoards his wealth (549a-b). The formation of the oligarchic soul appears in a domestic vignette. The oligarchic man at first emulates the timocratic man, until he sees his father suffer some great misfortune and loss of his wealth, power, citizenship, or life. This catastrophic event reroutes the son s pursuit of power and honor to a strict pursuit of wealth. He no longer cares for any knowledge or art unless it can be used to help him profit. He becomes extremely frugal and neglects care for himself. Furthermore, due to his lack of education, the only restraint he has over his criminal desires comes from anxiety that someone would enact the same injustices upon him, but not from an understanding of morality. The result is that in the mind of the public he seems virtuous, but in actuality this appearance of decency is merely a façade. Lastly, his severe frugality will keeps him from spending money on public expenses or on acts of goodwill (554a-555a). Plato asserts that the transition from the oligarchic constitution to the democratic constitution would happen by way of a revolt among the lower-class, unhappy with the city being run by the wealthy citizens. The type of man whose soul corresponds with this system of government is most prominently distinct in his sense of liberty. Having been raised by the oligarchic father, and subsequently having been neglected in many of his wants and desires, the democratic man pursues all of his wishes, being urged by outside influences. However, he still retains some of the restraint inherited by his father, and so his most vile and unlawful impulses are kept in 27

32 check. These two parts of himself, unbridled desire and miserly restraint, wage a constant war within his soul and there is no consistency in his lifestyle. Day by day according to his whim, he fasts or gorges; gets drunk or keeps sober; zealously works or is lazy; studies philosophy or puts off learning altogether. Essentially he lives his life without any order and follows his inclinations, which sometimes might be good and other times bad (559d-561e). Plato s brand of characterization heavily emphasizes the influential factors, which is relevant to Menander s presentation of characters interacting with and impacting each other. Within the context of the mini-episodes describing the formation of the types of souls, two types of relationships are placed in the spotlight: young men and their fathers, young men and their peers. Plato seems to distinguish these relationships as especially formative of character. There is also some demographical and sociological information ascribed to certain characters. While the main characters he presents belong to the upper-class, he also describes under what conditions the working-class, paupers, and criminals arise. Plato investigates the origins of character more than the other philosophers. Aristotle, Theophrastus, and Plato investigate the nature of character in different ways. Overall the style of characterization in these works of philosophy represents a variety of different manners in which character is explored: emotions, social attributes, psychology, social interactions, etc., which allows for a full spectrum of character presentation. There is also an overall commonality among these philosophers in that all of the characters that they describe are citizen males. This is 28

Phil Aristotle. Instructor: Jason Sheley

Phil Aristotle. Instructor: Jason Sheley Phil 290 - Aristotle Instructor: Jason Sheley To sum up the method 1) Human beings are naturally curious. 2) We need a place to begin our inquiry. 3) The best place to start is with commonly held beliefs.

More information

Reading the Nichomachean Ethics

Reading the Nichomachean Ethics 1 Reading the Nichomachean Ethics Book I: Chapter 1: Good as the aim of action Every art, applied science, systematic investigation, action and choice aims at some good: either an activity, or a product

More information

Virtue Ethics. A Basic Introductory Essay, by Dr. Garrett. Latest minor modification November 28, 2005

Virtue Ethics. A Basic Introductory Essay, by Dr. Garrett. Latest minor modification November 28, 2005 Virtue Ethics A Basic Introductory Essay, by Dr. Garrett Latest minor modification November 28, 2005 Some students would prefer not to study my introductions to philosophical issues and approaches but

More information

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

PHI 1700: Global Ethics PHI 1700: Global Ethics Session 8 March 1 st, 2016 Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics 1 Ø Today we begin Unit 2 of the course, focused on Normative Ethics = the practical development of standards for right

More information

Aristotle s Doctrine of the Mean and the Circularity of Human Nature

Aristotle s Doctrine of the Mean and the Circularity of Human Nature KRITIKE VOLUME TEN NUMBER TWO (DECEMBER 2016) 122-131 ARTICLE Thoughts on Classical Philosophy Aristotle s Doctrine of the Mean and the Circularity of Human Nature Nahum Brown Abstract: Aristotle's famous

More information

Chapter Six. Aristotle s Theory of Causation and the Ideas of Potentiality and Actuality

Chapter Six. Aristotle s Theory of Causation and the Ideas of Potentiality and Actuality Chapter Six Aristotle s Theory of Causation and the Ideas of Potentiality and Actuality Key Words: Form and matter, potentiality and actuality, teleological, change, evolution. Formal cause, material cause,

More information

Text 1: Philosophers and the Pursuit of Wisdom. Topic 5: Ancient Greece Lesson 3: Greek Thinkers, Artists, and Writers

Text 1: Philosophers and the Pursuit of Wisdom. Topic 5: Ancient Greece Lesson 3: Greek Thinkers, Artists, and Writers Text 1: Philosophers and the Pursuit of Wisdom Topic 5: Ancient Greece Lesson 3: Greek Thinkers, Artists, and Writers OBJECTIVES Identify the men responsible for the philosophy movement in Greece Discuss

More information

City and Soul in Plato s Republic. By G.R.F. Ferrari. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, Pp $17.00 (paper). ISBN

City and Soul in Plato s Republic. By G.R.F. Ferrari. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, Pp $17.00 (paper). ISBN 174 good cannot be friends does much to illuminate Socratic eudaimonism. The translation of the dialogue is an outstanding work of scholarship. The authors either transliterate the Greek or discuss the

More information

Socratic and Platonic Ethics

Socratic and Platonic Ethics Socratic and Platonic Ethics G. J. Mattey Winter, 2017 / Philosophy 1 Ethics and Political Philosophy The first part of the course is a brief survey of important texts in the history of ethics and political

More information

Practical Wisdom and Politics

Practical Wisdom and Politics Practical Wisdom and Politics In discussing Book I in subunit 1.6, you learned that the Ethics specifically addresses the close relationship between ethical inquiry and politics. At the outset, Aristotle

More information

- 1 - Outline of NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, Book I Book I--Dialectical discussion leading to Aristotle's definition of happiness: activity in accordance

- 1 - Outline of NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, Book I Book I--Dialectical discussion leading to Aristotle's definition of happiness: activity in accordance - 1 - Outline of NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, Book I Book I--Dialectical discussion leading to Aristotle's definition of happiness: activity in accordance with virtue or excellence (arete) in a complete life Chapter

More information

Selections of the Nicomachean Ethics for GGL Unit: Learning to Live Well Taken from classic.mit.edu archive. Translated by W.D. Ross I.

Selections of the Nicomachean Ethics for GGL Unit: Learning to Live Well Taken from classic.mit.edu archive. Translated by W.D. Ross I. Selections of the Nicomachean Ethics for GGL Unit: Learning to Live Well Taken from classic.mit.edu archive. Translated by W.D. Ross I.7 Let us again return to the good we are seeking, and ask what it

More information

The Culture of Classical Greece

The Culture of Classical Greece The Culture of Classical Greece Greeks considered religion to be important to the well being of the state and it affected every aspect of Greek life. Twelve chief gods and goddesses were believed to reside

More information

Synopsis of Plato s Republic Books I - IV. From the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Synopsis of Plato s Republic Books I - IV. From the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Synopsis of Plato s Republic Books I - IV From the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy 1 Introduction Since the mid-nineteenth century, the Republic has been Plato s most famous and widely read dialogue.

More information

Aristotle s Virtue Ethics

Aristotle s Virtue Ethics Aristotle s Virtue Ethics Aristotle, Virtue Ethics Every art and every inquiry, and similarly every action and pursuit, is thought to aim at some good; and for this reason the good has rightly been declared

More information

Nichomachean Ethics. Philosophy 21 Fall, 2004 G. J. Mattey

Nichomachean Ethics. Philosophy 21 Fall, 2004 G. J. Mattey Nichomachean Ethics Philosophy 21 Fall, 2004 G. J. Mattey The Highest Good The good is that at which everything aims Crafts, investigations, actions, decisions If one science is subordinate to another,

More information

Reading Euthyphro Plato as a literary artist

Reading Euthyphro Plato as a literary artist The objectives of studying the Euthyphro Reading Euthyphro The main objective is to learn what the method of philosophy is through the method Socrates used. The secondary objectives are (1) to be acquainted

More information

Chapter 10: Later Greek Comedy

Chapter 10: Later Greek Comedy The Hellenistic Age general chaos and confusion after Sparta s victory in the Peloponnesian War led to a civil war of sorts inside Greece the rise of Thebes the Battle of Leuctra (371 BCE): the graveyard

More information

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Author: Terence Rajivan Edward, University of Manchester. Abstract. In the sixth chapter of The View from Nowhere, Thomas Nagel attempts to identify a form of idealism.

More information

EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES My Answers

EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES My Answers EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES My Answers Diagram and evaluate each of the following arguments. Arguments with Definitional Premises Altruism. Altruism is the practice of doing something solely because

More information

Friendship in Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics

Friendship in Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics Parkland College A with Honors Projects Honors Program 2011 Friendship in Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics Jason Ader Parkland College Recommended Citation Ader, Jason, "Friendship in Aristotle's Nicomachean

More information

What We Are: Our Metaphysical Nature & Moral Implications

What We Are: Our Metaphysical Nature & Moral Implications What We Are: Our Metaphysical Nature & Moral Implications Julia Lei Western University ABSTRACT An account of our metaphysical nature provides an answer to the question of what are we? One such account

More information

Virtue Ethics without Character Traits

Virtue Ethics without Character Traits Virtue Ethics without Character Traits Gilbert Harman Princeton University August 18, 1999 Presumed parts of normative moral philosophy Normative moral philosophy is often thought to be concerned with

More information

McKenzie Study Center, an Institute of Gutenberg College. Handout 5 The Bible and the History of Ideas Teacher: John A. Jack Crabtree.

McKenzie Study Center, an Institute of Gutenberg College. Handout 5 The Bible and the History of Ideas Teacher: John A. Jack Crabtree. , an Institute of Gutenberg College Handout 5 The Bible and the History of Ideas Teacher: John A. Jack Crabtree Aristotle A. Aristotle (384 321 BC) was the tutor of Alexander the Great. 1. Socrates taught

More information

In this painting by Raphael, Plato (holding the Timeus) pointing up, representing the importance of focusing on the eternal Eidos, while Aristotle

In this painting by Raphael, Plato (holding the Timeus) pointing up, representing the importance of focusing on the eternal Eidos, while Aristotle In this painting by Raphael, Plato (holding the Timeus) pointing up, representing the importance of focusing on the eternal Eidos, while Aristotle (carrying his Nichomachean Ethics) holds his hand out

More information

How to Teach The Writings of the New Testament, 3 rd Edition Luke Timothy Johnson

How to Teach The Writings of the New Testament, 3 rd Edition Luke Timothy Johnson How to Teach The Writings of the New Testament, 3 rd Edition Luke Timothy Johnson As every experienced instructor understands, textbooks can be used in a variety of ways for effective teaching. In this

More information

Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak.

Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak. On Interpretation By Aristotle Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak. First we must define the terms 'noun' and 'verb', then the terms 'denial' and 'affirmation',

More information

Well-Being, Time, and Dementia. Jennifer Hawkins. University of Toronto

Well-Being, Time, and Dementia. Jennifer Hawkins. University of Toronto Well-Being, Time, and Dementia Jennifer Hawkins University of Toronto Philosophers often discuss what makes a life as a whole good. More significantly, it is sometimes assumed that beneficence, which is

More information

NICOMACHEAN ETHICS (BOOKS VIII IX)

NICOMACHEAN ETHICS (BOOKS VIII IX) NICOMACHEAN ETHICS (BOOKS VIII IX) Aristotle Introduction, M. Andrew Holowchak THE FOCUS OF ARISTOTLE S Nicomachean Ethics (hereafter, EN) is eudaimonia, a word for which there is no English equivalent.

More information

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Res Cogitans Volume 5 Issue 1 Article 20 6-4-2014 Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Kevin Harriman Lewis & Clark College Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans

More information

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory Western University Scholarship@Western 2015 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2015 Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory David Hakim Western University, davidhakim266@gmail.com

More information

So130 Week 10 SG3 #51-93 #51. What are some of the consequences of divorcing the biblical text from their original cultural context?

So130 Week 10 SG3 #51-93 #51. What are some of the consequences of divorcing the biblical text from their original cultural context? Week 10 STUDY GUIDE QUESTIONS SG3 #51-93 1 #51 What are some of the consequences of divorcing the biblical text from their original cultural context? 19 We will miss much of the instruction that the texts

More information

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Chapter 98 Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Lars Leeten Universität Hildesheim Practical thinking is a tricky business. Its aim will never be fulfilled unless influence on practical

More information

Virtuous act, virtuous dispositions

Virtuous act, virtuous dispositions virtuous act, virtuous dispositions 69 Virtuous act, virtuous dispositions Thomas Hurka Everyday moral thought uses the concepts of virtue and vice at two different levels. At what I will call a global

More information

Logical Appeal (Logos)

Logical Appeal (Logos) Logical Appeal (Logos) Relies on sound reasoning, facts, statistics Uses evidence well Analyzes cause-effect relationships Uses patterns of inductive and deductive reasoning Pitfall: failure to clearly

More information

Morally Adaptive or Morally Maladaptive: A Look at Compassion, Mercy, and Bravery

Morally Adaptive or Morally Maladaptive: A Look at Compassion, Mercy, and Bravery ESSAI Volume 10 Article 17 4-1-2012 Morally Adaptive or Morally Maladaptive: A Look at Compassion, Mercy, and Bravery Alec Dorner College of DuPage Follow this and additional works at: http://dc.cod.edu/essai

More information

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström From: Who Owns Our Genes?, Proceedings of an international conference, October 1999, Tallin, Estonia, The Nordic Committee on Bioethics, 2000. THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström I shall be mainly

More information

A primer of major ethical theories

A primer of major ethical theories Chapter 1 A primer of major ethical theories Our topic in this course is privacy. Hence we want to understand (i) what privacy is and also (ii) why we value it and how this value is reflected in our norms

More information

JUDICIAL OPINION WRITING

JUDICIAL OPINION WRITING JUDICIAL OPINION WRITING What's an Opinion For? James Boyd Whitet The question the papers in this Special Issue address is whether it matters how judicial opinions are written, and if so why. My hope here

More information

Ancient Greece Important Men

Ancient Greece Important Men Ancient Greece Important Men Sophist success was more important than moral truth developed skills in rhetoric Ambitious men could use clever and persuasive rhetoric to advance their careers Older citizens,

More information

to convey a truth through a longer story utilizing elements of character, setting, and plot where the moral is not stated outright

to convey a truth through a longer story utilizing elements of character, setting, and plot where the moral is not stated outright sling & stone writing assignment TR Progymnasmata Summary fable to convey a truth through a short story where the moral is stated outright, often using flat characters and animals narrative to convey a

More information

Honors Ethics Oral Presentations: Instructions

Honors Ethics Oral Presentations: Instructions Cabrillo College Claudia Close Honors Ethics Philosophy 10H Fall 2018 Honors Ethics Oral Presentations: Instructions Your initial presentation should be approximately 6-7 minutes and you should prepare

More information

Virtue Ethics. What kind of person do you want to grow up to be? Virtue Ethics (VE): The Basic Idea

Virtue Ethics. What kind of person do you want to grow up to be? Virtue Ethics (VE): The Basic Idea Virtue Ethics What kind of person do you want to grow up to be? Virtue Ethics (VE): The Basic Idea Whereas most modern (i.e., post 17 th century) ethical theories stress rules and principles as the content

More information

What Part of the Soul Does Justice Perfect? Shane Drefcinski Department of Humanities/Philosophy University of Wisconsin Platteville

What Part of the Soul Does Justice Perfect? Shane Drefcinski Department of Humanities/Philosophy University of Wisconsin Platteville What Part of the Soul Does Justice Perfect? Shane Drefcinski Department of Humanities/Philosophy University of Wisconsin Platteville Interpreters of Aristotle generally agree that each of the particular

More information

Nicomachean Ethics, Book II

Nicomachean Ethics, Book II Nicomachean Ethics, Book II Aristotle In the first chapter of Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle argues that the good life consists in acting rationally, in accordance with the virtues, for a sufficiently long

More information

SAT Essay Prompts (October June 2013 )

SAT Essay Prompts (October June 2013 ) SAT Essay Prompts (October 2012 - June 2013 ) June 2013 Our cherished notions of what is equal and what is fair frequently conflict. Democracy presumes that we are all created equal; competition proves

More information

On Interpretation. Section 1. Aristotle Translated by E. M. Edghill. Part 1

On Interpretation. Section 1. Aristotle Translated by E. M. Edghill. Part 1 On Interpretation Aristotle Translated by E. M. Edghill Section 1 Part 1 First we must define the terms noun and verb, then the terms denial and affirmation, then proposition and sentence. Spoken words

More information

SAMPLE ESSAYS--FOR DISCUSSION

SAMPLE ESSAYS--FOR DISCUSSION packet toc file:///l:/public_html/101/packet_toc.htm /7/2007 5:01 PM 1 of 1 READING MATERIALS Finding a Subject 1 Show Not Tell Time 3 The Persuasive Principle 4 SAMPLE ESSAYS--FOR DISCUSSION Key Club

More information

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 5

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 5 University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 5 May 14th, 9:00 AM - May 17th, 5:00 PM Commentary pm Krabbe Dale Jacquette Follow this and additional works at: http://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive

More information

One's. Character Change

One's. Character Change Aristotle on and the Responsibility for Possibility of Character One's Character Change 1 WILLIAM BONDESON ristotle's discussion of the voluntary and the involuntary occurs Book III, in chapters 1 through

More information

Florida State University Libraries

Florida State University Libraries Florida State University Libraries Undergraduate Research Honors Ethical Issues and Life Choices (PHI2630) 2013 How We Should Make Moral Career Choices Rebecca Hallock Follow this and additional works

More information

The Problem of Freedom. Taylor Thompson, Columbia University

The Problem of Freedom. Taylor Thompson, Columbia University Thompson: The Problem of Freedom Thompson 1 The Problem of Freedom Taylor Thompson, Columbia University The main argument in Plato's Republic is first sketched through the attempt to define and characterize

More information

What Is Virtue? Historical and Philosophical Context

What Is Virtue? Historical and Philosophical Context What Is Virtue? Historical and Philosophical Context Some assumptions underlie our selection and discussion of virtues. Right and wrong exist. Understanding civic virtue means acknowledging this. To further

More information

270 Now that we have settled these issues, we should answer the first question [n.

270 Now that we have settled these issues, we should answer the first question [n. Ordinatio prologue, q. 5, nn. 270 313 A. The views of others 270 Now that we have settled these issues, we should answer the first question [n. 217]. There are five ways to answer in the negative. [The

More information

(i) Morality is a system; and (ii) It is a system comprised of moral rules and principles.

(i) Morality is a system; and (ii) It is a system comprised of moral rules and principles. Ethics and Morality Ethos (Greek) and Mores (Latin) are terms having to do with custom, habit, and behavior. Ethics is the study of morality. This definition raises two questions: (a) What is morality?

More information

Platonic Idealism: Too High a Standard for Political Activity. As I have re-read Plato s Republic, and read for the first time Eric Voegelin s

Platonic Idealism: Too High a Standard for Political Activity. As I have re-read Plato s Republic, and read for the first time Eric Voegelin s Platonic Idealism: Too High a Standard for Political Activity Geoffrey Plauché POLI 7990 - #1 September 22, 2004 As I have re-read Plato s Republic, and read for the first time Eric Voegelin s interpretation

More information

Meno. 70a. 70b. 70c. 71a. Cambridge University Press Meno and Phaedo Edited by David Sedley and Alex Long Excerpt More information

Meno. 70a. 70b. 70c. 71a. Cambridge University Press Meno and Phaedo Edited by David Sedley and Alex Long Excerpt More information Meno meno: 1 Can you tell me, Socrates, whether virtue is teachable? 2 Or is it not teachable, but attainable by practice? Or is it attainable neither by practice nor by learning, and do people instead

More information

THE MENO by Plato Written in approximately 380 B.C.

THE MENO by Plato Written in approximately 380 B.C. THE MENO by Plato Written in approximately 380 B.C. The is a selection from a book titled The Meno by the philosopher Plato. Meno is a prominent Greek, and a follower of Gorgias, who is a Sophist. Socrates

More information

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between Lee Anne Detzel PHI 8338 Revised: November 1, 2004 The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between philosophy

More information

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg 1 In Search of the Ontological Argument Richard Oxenberg Abstract We can attend to the logic of Anselm's ontological argument, and amuse ourselves for a few hours unraveling its convoluted word-play, or

More information

Government 203 Political Theorists and Their Theories: Plato Spring Semester 2010 Clark University

Government 203 Political Theorists and Their Theories: Plato Spring Semester 2010 Clark University Government 203 Political Theorists and Their Theories: Plato Spring Semester 2010 Clark University Jefferson 400 Friday, 1:25-4:15 Professor Robert Boatright JEF 313A; (508) 793-7632 Office Hours: Wed.

More information

Virtue Ethics. Chapter 7 ETCI Barbara MacKinnon Ethics and Contemporary Issues Professor Douglas Olena

Virtue Ethics. Chapter 7 ETCI Barbara MacKinnon Ethics and Contemporary Issues Professor Douglas Olena Virtue Ethics Chapter 7 ETCI Barbara MacKinnon Ethics and Contemporary Issues Professor Douglas Olena Introductory Paragraphs 109 Story of Abraham Whom do you admire? The list of traits is instructive.

More information

Scholarship 2014 Classical Studies

Scholarship 2014 Classical Studies 93404Q 934042 S Scholarship 2014 Classical Studies 2.00 pm Wednesday 12 November 2014 Time allowed: Three hours Total marks: 24 QUESTION BOOKLET Answer THREE questions from this booklet: TWO questions

More information

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING 1 REASONING Reasoning is, broadly speaking, the cognitive process of establishing reasons to justify beliefs, conclusions, actions or feelings. It also refers, more specifically, to the act or process

More information

Nicomachean Ethics, Book II By Aristotle Written 350 B.C.E Translated by W. D. Ross

Nicomachean Ethics, Book II By Aristotle Written 350 B.C.E Translated by W. D. Ross Nicomachean Ethics, Book II By Aristotle Written 350 B.C.E Translated by W. D. Ross 1 Virtue, then, being of two kinds, intellectual and moral, intellectual virtue in the main owes both its birth and its

More information

Reviewed Work: Why We Argue (and How We Should): A Guide to Political Disagreement, by Scott Aikin and Robert Talisse

Reviewed Work: Why We Argue (and How We Should): A Guide to Political Disagreement, by Scott Aikin and Robert Talisse College of Saint Benedict and Saint John s University DigitalCommons@CSB/SJU Philosophy Faculty Publications Philosophy 12-2014 Reviewed Work: Why We Argue (and How We Should): A Guide to Political Disagreement,

More information

Chapter 2--How Should One Live?

Chapter 2--How Should One Live? Chapter 2--How Should One Live? Student: 1. If we studied the kinds of moral values people actually hold, we would be engaging in a study of ethics. A. normative B. descriptive C. normative and a descriptive

More information

Nicomachean Ethics by Aristotle (ca 330 BC) (Selections from Books I, II & X)

Nicomachean Ethics by Aristotle (ca 330 BC) (Selections from Books I, II & X) Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics 1 Nicomachean Ethics by Aristotle (ca 330 BC) (Selections from Books I, II & X) Space for Notes Book I Our discussion will be adequate if it has as much clearness as the subjectmatter

More information

Socrates was born around 470/469 BC in Alopeke, a suburb of Athens but, located outside the wall, and belonged to the tribe Antiochis.

Socrates was born around 470/469 BC in Alopeke, a suburb of Athens but, located outside the wall, and belonged to the tribe Antiochis. SOCRATES Greek philosopher Who was Socrates? Socrates was born around 470/469 BC in Alopeke, a suburb of Athens but, located outside the wall, and belonged to the tribe Antiochis. His father was a sculptor

More information

Critique of Cosmological Argument

Critique of Cosmological Argument David Hume: Critique of Cosmological Argument Critique of Cosmological Argument DAVID HUME (1711-1776) David Hume is one of the most important philosophers in the history of philosophy. Born in Edinburgh,

More information

1/13. Locke on Power

1/13. Locke on Power 1/13 Locke on Power Locke s chapter on power is the longest chapter of the Essay Concerning Human Understanding and its claims are amongst the most controversial and influential that Locke sets out in

More information

Review of Thomas C. Brickhouse and Nicholas D. Smith, "Socratic Moral Psychology"

Review of Thomas C. Brickhouse and Nicholas D. Smith, Socratic Moral Psychology Review of Thomas C. Brickhouse and Nicholas D. Smith, "Socratic Moral Psychology" The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters

More information

Building Systematic Theology

Building Systematic Theology 1 Building Systematic Theology Lesson Guide LESSON ONE WHAT IS SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY? 2013 by Third Millennium Ministries www.thirdmill.org For videos, manuscripts, and other resources, visit Third Millennium

More information

Knowledge and True Opinion in Plato s Meno

Knowledge and True Opinion in Plato s Meno Knowledge and True Opinion in Plato s Meno Ariel Weiner In Plato s dialogue, the Meno, Socrates inquires into how humans may become virtuous, and, corollary to that, whether humans have access to any form

More information

Prentice Hall. Conexiones Comunicación y cultura North Carolina Course of Study for High School Level IV

Prentice Hall. Conexiones Comunicación y cultura North Carolina Course of Study for High School Level IV Prentice Hall Conexiones Comunicación y cultura 2010 C O R R E L A T E D T O SECOND LANGUAGES :: 2004 :: HIGH SCHOOL LEVEL IV HIGH SCHOOL LEVEL IV Students enrolled in this course have successfully completed

More information

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1 310 Book Review Book Review ISSN (Print) 1225-4924, ISSN (Online) 2508-3104 Catholic Theology and Thought, Vol. 79, July 2017 http://dx.doi.org/10.21731/ctat.2017.79.310 A Review on What Is This Thing

More information

Question Bank UNIT I 1. What are human values? Values decide the standard of behavior. Some universally accepted values are freedom justice and equality. Other principles of values are love, care, honesty,

More information

Courage in the Heart. Susan A. Schiller. Pedagogy, Volume 1, Issue 1, Winter 2001, pp (Review) Published by Duke University Press

Courage in the Heart. Susan A. Schiller. Pedagogy, Volume 1, Issue 1, Winter 2001, pp (Review) Published by Duke University Press Courage in the Heart Susan A. Schiller Pedagogy, Volume 1, Issue 1, Winter 2001, pp. 225-229 (Review) Published by Duke University Press For additional information about this article https://muse.jhu.edu/article/26331

More information

Excerpts from Aristotle

Excerpts from Aristotle Excerpts from Aristotle This online version of Aristotle's Rhetoric (a hypertextual resource compiled by Lee Honeycutt) is based on the translation of noted classical scholar W. Rhys Roberts. Book I -

More information

We Believe in God. Lesson Guide WHAT WE KNOW ABOUT GOD LESSON ONE. We Believe in God by Third Millennium Ministries

We Believe in God. Lesson Guide WHAT WE KNOW ABOUT GOD LESSON ONE. We Believe in God by Third Millennium Ministries 1 Lesson Guide LESSON ONE WHAT WE KNOW ABOUT GOD For videos, manuscripts, and other Lesson resources, 1: What We visit Know Third About Millennium God Ministries at thirdmill.org. 2 CONTENTS HOW TO USE

More information

Unit 1 Philosophy of Education: Introduction INTRODUCTION

Unit 1 Philosophy of Education: Introduction INTRODUCTION Unit 1 Philosophy of Education: Introduction INTRODUCTION It is not easy to say what exactly philosophy is, how to study it, or how to do it. Philosophy, like all other field, is unique. The reason why

More information

World-Wide Ethics. Chapter Seven. Virtue Theory

World-Wide Ethics. Chapter Seven. Virtue Theory World-Wide Ethics Chapter Seven Virtue Theory An ancient approach to understanding moral principles, especially popular among the Greeks, was what is today known as virtue ethics. Although the Greeks recognized

More information

Philosophy Courses-1

Philosophy Courses-1 Philosophy Courses-1 PHL 100/Introduction to Philosophy A course that examines the fundamentals of philosophical argument, analysis and reasoning, as applied to a series of issues in logic, epistemology,

More information

Happiness and Moral Virtue Aristotle

Happiness and Moral Virtue Aristotle Happiness and Moral Virtue Aristotle BOOK ONE 1. Every art and every inquiry, and similarly every action and pursuit, is thought to aim at some good; and for this reason the good has rightly been declared

More information

What God Could Have Made

What God Could Have Made 1 What God Could Have Made By Heimir Geirsson and Michael Losonsky I. Introduction Atheists have argued that if there is a God who is omnipotent, omniscient and omnibenevolent, then God would have made

More information

A historical overview of philosophical views on moral character

A historical overview of philosophical views on moral character A historical overview of philosophical views on moral character Terminology The English word character is derived from the Greek charaktêr, which was originally used to describe a mark impressed upon a

More information

What is Freedom? Should Socrates be Set Free? Plato s Crito

What is Freedom? Should Socrates be Set Free? Plato s Crito What is Freedom? Should Socrates be Set Free? Plato s Crito Quick Review of the Apology SGD of DQs Side 1: Questions 1 through 3 / Side 2: Questions 4 through 6 What is the major / provocative takeaway?

More information

Take Home Exam #2. PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert

Take Home Exam #2. PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert Name: Date: Take Home Exam #2 Instructions (Read Before Proceeding!) Material for this exam is from class sessions 8-15. Matching and fill-in-the-blank questions

More information

Preface. amalgam of "invented and imagined events", but as "the story" which is. narrative of Luke's Gospel has made of it. The emphasis is on the

Preface. amalgam of invented and imagined events, but as the story which is. narrative of Luke's Gospel has made of it. The emphasis is on the Preface In the narrative-critical analysis of Luke's Gospel as story, the Gospel is studied not as "story" in the conventional sense of a fictitious amalgam of "invented and imagined events", but as "the

More information

CHAPTER 6 ARISTOTLE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS : L.9, C.6.

CHAPTER 6 ARISTOTLE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS : L.9, C.6. ARISTOTLE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS : L.9, C.6. CHAPTER 6 Now that we have spoken of the virtues, the forms of friendship, and the varieties of pleasure, what remains is to discuss in outline the nature of happiness,

More information

Are There Moral Facts

Are There Moral Facts Are There Moral Facts Birkbeck Philosophy Study Guide 2016 Are There Moral Facts? Dr. Cristian Constantinescu & Prof. Hallvard Lillehammer Department of Philosophy, Birkbeck College This Study Guide is

More information

REVIEW THE MORALS OF HISTORIOGRAPHY

REVIEW THE MORALS OF HISTORIOGRAPHY Histos 11 (2017) lxxi lxxv REVIEW THE MORALS OF HISTORIOGRAPHY Lisa Irene Hau, Moral History from Herodotus to Diodorus Siculus. Edinburgh: University of Edinburgh Press, 2016. Pp. viii + 312. Hardback,

More information

SPIRITUAL FORMATION (TTSF)

SPIRITUAL FORMATION (TTSF) Biola University 1 SPIRITUAL FORMATION (TTSF) TTSF 501 - Introduction to Spiritual Theology and Formation Credits 0-3 Introductory study of the nature of spiritual theology and formation, which attempts

More information

Nicomachean Ethics. by Aristotle ( B.C.)

Nicomachean Ethics. by Aristotle ( B.C.) by Aristotle (384 322 B.C.) IT IS NOT UNREASONABLE that men should derive their concept of the good and of happiness from the lives which they lead. The common run of people and the most vulgar identify

More information

Chapter 1 Foundations

Chapter 1 Foundations Chapter 1 Foundations Imagine this scenario: You have just passed your driver s test, and you are now the proud owner of a license. You are excited about your new freedom and can t wait to go out on the

More information

Against Christianity Peter J. Leithart (Canon Press, 2003) Week 1: Preface and Chapter 1 Against Christianity

Against Christianity Peter J. Leithart (Canon Press, 2003) Week 1: Preface and Chapter 1 Against Christianity Week 1: Preface and Chapter 1 The aphorism is a common literary device that offers a concise statement of a principle or precept given in pointed words. It is a genre often used by philosophers and writers

More information

Unpacking the City-Soul Analogy

Unpacking the City-Soul Analogy Res Cogitans Volume 8 Issue 1 Article 9 2017 Unpacking the City-Soul Analogy Kexin Yu University of Rochester, kyu15@u.rochester.edu Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans

More information

For a brilliant introductory lecture on the meaning of practical wisdom in virtue ethics by Professor Schwartz of the University of Colorado go to:

For a brilliant introductory lecture on the meaning of practical wisdom in virtue ethics by Professor Schwartz of the University of Colorado go to: Virtue activity ARISTOTLE S VIRTUE ETHICS Ethical system based on defining the personal qualities that make a person moral; the focus on a person s character rather than their specific actions; Aristotle

More information

Other Recommended Books (on reserve at library):

Other Recommended Books (on reserve at library): Ethics, Fall 2015 TTH 11:30-12:50, GRHM 2302 Instructor: John, Ph.D. Office: Mackinnon 330 Office Hrs: TTH 1:00-2:00 and by appointment Phone Ext.: 56765 Email: jhackerw@uoguelph.ca OVERVIEW This course

More information

Plato and the art of philosophical writing

Plato and the art of philosophical writing Plato and the art of philosophical writing Author: Marina McCoy Persistent link: http://hdl.handle.net/2345/3016 This work is posted on escholarship@bc, Boston College University Libraries. Pre-print version

More information