In Pursuit of Equality: Bringing Human Dignity to the Forefront of Section 15. Christina Malezis. A thesis submitted to the Department of Philosophy

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "In Pursuit of Equality: Bringing Human Dignity to the Forefront of Section 15. Christina Malezis. A thesis submitted to the Department of Philosophy"

Transcription

1 In Pursuit of Equality: Bringing Human Dignity to the Forefront of Section 15 by Christina Malezis A thesis submitted to the Department of Philosophy In conformity with the requirements for the degree of Masters of Arts Queen s University Kingston, Ontario, Canada September 2012 Copyright Christina Malezis, 2012

2 ABSTRACT While it is clear that section 15 of the Charter of Rights and Freedoms should be read as prohibiting only of those violations of equality that amount to discrimination, it remains unclear how to determine what it means for a state to treat its citizens as equals, and more specifically, what constitutes discrimination. Thus, the idea of human dignity in section 15 the Charter has been, in many ways, groundbreaking in its recognition of the far-reaching impact of unequal treatment. There remains, however much scholarly dissension surrounding the concept s meaning and use within section 15 equality jurisprudence. As a result, many have argued that the concept suffers from ambiguity and indeterminacy, thus creating an additional burden on equality claimants. This work advances the thesis that the concept of human dignity, understood in the objective sense as autonomy and self-determination, explains the nature and scope of the government s obligation to show equal concern and respect, and offers us valuable guidance as to why certain types of unequal treatment are unfair and illegitimate. The concept can, I believe, help to delineate how equality is to be conceived, specified and realised under section 15 of the Charter. To make my case, I reject and show as flawed the Supreme Court of Canada s interpretation and use of dignity in section 15(1) jurisprudence. Finally, in an attempt to demonstrate that the concept of dignity is relevant and necessary to an analysis of discrimination, I show that such a concept is in fact grounded in Sophia Moreau s own illuminating account of the wrongs of unequal treatment. ii

3 Acknowledgments First and foremost, I wish to extend my utmost appreciation and gratitude to Christine Sypnowich for her guidance and supervision in this project. I am indebted to her insightful comments and questions; any shortcomings of this work are entirely my own. Christine s kindness and mentorship have been invaluable to me and her own work on human flourishing has greatly influenced this piece. I thank Will Kymlicka for his incisive questions and comments on an earlier draft of this paper and Beverley Baines for her contributions and gracious participation in this project. I thank Kerri A. Froc for inspiring me to write about human dignity with her most enlightening class on section 15 of the Charter. I thank Katerina Malezis and Bradley J. Vanderkam for their endless encouragement, coaxing support, and confidence in me. I also thank Lana De Gasperis for her intellectual and emotional friendship. Above all, I thank my parents, for without their unwavering love and support, I would not be where I am today. iii

4 Table of Contents I. Introduction...1 I.1.1. Section 15: The Groundwork...3 I.1.2. The Context of Equality Claims...7 I.1.3. Conclusion...9 II. Human Dignity and Section 15 of the Charter...10 II.1.1. Dignity and Equality Rights..11 II.1.2. Philosophical Foundations of Human Dignity...12 II Dignity Grounded in Rights..14 II Dignity Grounded in Status...15 II Dignity Grounded in Emotion...16 II.1.3. Dignity and the Law test 17 II.1.4. Problems with Dignity in Law: An Emotions Grounding Account...21 II.1.5. A Way Forward for the Concept of Human Dignity...25 II.1.6. Conclusion...33 III. IV. The Role of Human Dignity in Conceptualizing the Wrongs of Unequal Treatment 34 III.1.1. The Wrongs of Unequal Treatment III Stereotype and Prejudice...35 III The Perpetuation of Oppressive Power Relations.39 III Denial of Goods.40 III Diminishing Self-Worth.43 III.1.2. Room For Human Dignity?...44 III.1.3. How Unfair Differential Treatment Can Be Explained as Harmful to Human Dignity..47 III Stereotype and Prejudice...48 III The Perpetuation of Oppressive Power Relations.51 III Denial of Basic Goods...52 III Diminishing Self-Worth 56 III.1.4. Conclusion.57 Objections V. Conclusion..62 Bibliography...64 iv

5 I. Introduction No government is legitimate that does not show equal concern for the fate of all those citizens over whom it claims dominion and from whom it claims allegiance. Equal concern is the sovereign virtue of political community. 1 Section 15(1) of the Charter of Rights and Freedoms guarantees equality, but its precise formulation is restricted to the prohibition of discrimination, on such grounds as race, national or ethnic origin, color, religion, sex, age or mental or physical disability. Thus, it is clear that section 15 should be read as prohibiting only those violations of equality that amount to discrimination. But how do we determine what it means for a state to treat its citizens as equals and, more specifically, what constitutes discrimination? The idea of discrimination involves a normative assessment that certain instances of unequal treatment are unfair. We might ask then, when unequal treatment is unfair, what makes it so? Likewise, how can we delineate the wrong done to individuals when they are treated unfairly and unequally by the state? These are the sorts of questions that the Supreme Court of Canada has struggled with when interpreting the equality rights of section 15. These questions have also preoccupied philosophers who have analysed the reasons we have for valuing justice and equality and the different ways we can conceptualize the wrong done to individuals when the state does not treat them as equals. Specifically, philosophers have been concerned with inequalities in the distribution of benefits and burdens in society, with political or social power, and with institutional structures that stigmatize, marginalize, and oppress individuals. The latter question is of 1 Dworkin, Ronald, Sovereign Virtue: The Theory and Practice of Equality (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2000) [Hereinafter Sovereign Virtue], at 1.

6 particular relevance to Canadian equality jurisprudence, as the Supreme Court of Canada has construed and employed the protection offered by section 15 of the Charter as those forms of unequal treatment that deprive some of a benefit available to others in circumstances where this treatment is unfair. 2 To be sure, no plausible account of equality maintains that what is objectionable about unequal treatment is the mere fact that some individuals end up with more or less than others, but rather that unequal treatment is objectionable when this treatment is said to be unfair. While there has been vigorous philosophical debate about the meaning of equality, until recently there has been little work done in attempting to marry philosophical and jurisprudential fields into a more fully developed and refined account of equality. This project seeks to contribute to current efforts to bridge the gap between the theory and practice of equality. The philosophical literature on equality, I believe, can help shed light on the question: what constitutes discrimination? We can learn from some of the conceptual distinctions that have been drawn in the philosophical literature between the various ways of understanding the wrongs that are done to individuals when the state unfairly treats them unequally and particularly from the philosophical ideal of human dignity. In what follows, I will argue that the concept of human dignity, as understood in the objective sense as autonomy and self-determination, explains the nature and scope of the government s obligation to show equal concern and respect, and offers us valuable guidance as to why certain types of unequal treatment are unfair and illegitimate. Indeed, as I will suggest, questions of human dignity are central to questions of equality. As such, 2 See: Andrews v. Law Society of British Columbia [1989] 1 S.C.R. 143, at para 35; Moreau, Sophia, The Wrongs of Unequal Treatment in Fay Faraday, Margaret Denike, and M. Kate Stephenson, eds. Making Equality Rights Real: Securing Substantive Equality under the Charter (Toronto: Irwin Law, 2006) p 4. 2

7 the concept can, I believe, help delineate how equality is to be conceived, specified, and realised under section 15 of the Charter. To substantiate my thesis I will (a) reject and show as flawed, the Supreme Court of Canada s interpretation and use of dignity; and (b) reject Sophia Moreau s critique of dignity and show that her account of the wrongs of unequal treatment is in fact grounded in an understanding of dignity. Indeed, without the concept of human dignity, it is not clear that we have any handle on what human interest underlies the right to equality, nor are we likely to do little more than correct glaring deviations from the terms of statutory rules themselves unless we put the interest in dignity at the forefront. The body of the argument of this project is laid out in two chapters. In Chapter II, I outline and criticize the Supreme Court of Canada s interpretation and use of the concept of human dignity and advance my own account of the ideal, one that I believe escapes the criticisms mounted against it. In Chapter III, I focus in on Sophia Moreau whose recent work attempts to conceptualize the wrongs done to individuals when the state treats them unfairly and unequally. I argue that the concept of dignity is relevant and necessary to an analysis of discrimination by demonstrating that an account of dignity is grounded in Moreau s own illuminating account of the wrongs of unequal treatment. But first, it is necessary to set the stage by taking a closer look at section 15(1) of the Charter: its purpose, use and context as interpreted by the Supreme Court of Canada Section 15: The Groundwork Section 15 of the Charter of Rights and Freedoms sets out the following: 15(1) Every individual is equal before and under the law and has the right to the equal protection and equal benefit of the law without discrimination and, in particular, without discrimination based on race, national or ethnic 3

8 origin, color, religion, sex, age or mental or physical disability. 3 (2) Subsection (1) does not preclude any law, program or activity that has as its object the amelioration of conditions of disadvantaged individuals or groups including those that are disadvantaged because of race, national or ethnic origin, colour, religion, sex, age or mental or physical disability. 4 Section 15(1) of the Charter provides for every individual a guarantee of equality before and under the law, as well as the equal protection and equal benefit of the law without discrimination. This is not a general guarantee of equality; it does not provide for equality between individuals or groups within society in a general or abstract sense, nor does it impose on individuals or groups an obligation to accord equal treatment to others. It is rather concerned with the formulation and application of the law. The promotion of equality under section 15 of the Charter entails the promotion of a society in which all are secure in the knowledge that they are recognized by the law as human beings equally deserving of concern, respect, and consideration. Beyond this, however, the Charter itself provides no guidance as to what it means for the government to treat its citizens as equals, nor what constitutes discrimination in breach of section 15. Thus, with the enactment of the Charter in 1982, the Supreme Court of Canada faced a dilemma. At one extreme was the theory that every distinction drawn in a statute constituted discrimination in breach of section 15. On this theory, the structure of analysis developed in R. v. Oakes 5 for justification under section 1 (sufficiently important objective, rational connection to that objective, minimum impairment and proportionality) would be the analysis that would be applied to all section 15 challenges. At the other end was the position taken by 3 There exist four equalities under this guarantee; that is, s. 15 provides that every individual is equal before and under the law and has the right to the equal protection and equal benefit of the law 3. 4 Hogg, Peter W. Constitutional Law of Canada, 2011 Student Edition. Toronto: Carswell, Print. S R. v. Oakes [1986] 1 S.C.R

9 McLachlin J. who held that the only legislative distinctions that would amount to discrimination were those that were unreasonable or unfair. For McLachlin J., section 15 contained its own implicit requirement of justification, and the question whether a legislative distinction was justified or not would be determined by an assessment of its reasonableness or unfairness according to standards that the courts would have to develop within section 15 itself. 6 Both approaches, however, shared the reasonable assumption that all legislative distinctions are open to review under section 15. To be clear, section 15 does have significant scope; the listed grounds, though not exhaustive, point to personal characteristics of individuals that cannot easily be changed and which have often been the target of prejudice and stereotyping. This has proved to be a useful and far-reaching approach for specifying what forms of unequal treatment that are unfair and illegitimate. Moreover, the reference in subsection (2) the affirmative action clause to disadvantaged individuals or groups also suggests that the role of section 15 is not just to prohibit, but correct discrimination. These features of section 15 suggest that the proper role of the equality guarantee is not to eliminate all unfairness from our laws, but rather to eliminate discrimination based on immutable personal characteristics. Andrews v. Law Society of British Columbia was the first section 15 case to reach the Supreme Court of Canada. It was a challenge to the statutory requirement of the province of British Columbia that members of the bar had to be citizens of Canada. The Court held unanimously that this requirement was contrary to section 15, and by a majority that it was not saved by section 1. McIntyre J., writing for the unanimous Court 6 See Hogg, supra note 5, S. 55.6(b)

10 on the interpretation of section 15, rejected both the view that section 15 condemned all legislative classifications and that section 15 condemned unreasonable or unfair classifications, holding instead that there was a middle ground between the two positions, which was to interpret discrimination in section 15 as applying to only the grounds listed in section 15 and analogous grounds. The Court went on to hold that citizenship qualified as an analogous ground of discrimination. Andrews made clear that section 15 was a prohibition of discrimination, and that discrimination involved the denial of a benefit or imposition of a burden (i.e. disadvantage) on an individual as a result of an immutable characteristic that was either listed or analogous to those in section 15. The restriction of section 15 to enumerated and analogous grounds is now a permanent feature of the section 15 jurisprudence. Since Andrews, the Supreme Court has worked its way towards an understanding of section 15 based on the concept of human dignity as the underlying interest grounding claims of equality. In Law v. Canada (Minister of Employment and Immigration) 7, the Court added the new restriction: that discrimination involved an impairment of human dignity. Dignity began as an idea about the enumerated grounds given in section 15 and their relationship with one another 8 the idea being that the enumerated grounds are so tied to one s person that distinctions based on them affect one s dignity. Thus, in a sense, dignity was the criterion for the enumeration. This is illustrated in McLachlin J. s 7 Law v. Canada (Minister of Employment and Immigration), [1999] 1 S.C.R This position is illustrated in Miron v. Trudel, [1995] 2 S.C.R. 418 [Miron]. The idea being that enumerated grounds of section 15 are chosen because they have some link to a person s dignity that is, to be denied access to some benefit because of stereotypical application of presumed group characteristics (specifically those characteristics which define the grounds) is not to be treated with dignity. See also Denise Réaume on this: Réaume, Denise G., Discrimination and Dignity (2004). Anti-Discrimination Law, Part of the International Library of Essays in Law and Legal Theory, 2nd Series, Christopher McCrudden, ed., Hampshire: Ashgate Publishing, 2004, reprinted from (2003); Louisiana Law Review, Vol. 63, p 16. 6

11 description of the purpose of section 15 in Miron v. Trudel 9 as prevent[ing] the violation of human dignity and freedom by imposing limitations, disadvantages or burdens through the stereotypical application of presumed group characteristics rather than on the basis of individual merit, capacity, or circumstances 10. This linked the prohibited grounds of discrimination to dignity, suggesting that the grounds listed in section 15 were chosen because of their connection to some stereotype which falsely attributed negative characteristics to members of groups identified by these characteristics and, in turn, violated dignity. This also applied to the analogous grounds: a ground was analogous if and only if it was connected to the dignity of the claimant. The decision in Egan v. Canada 11, for instance, a case deemed a major victory for equality rights, connected dignity to the harm of discrimination on the basis of sexual orientation. Sexual orientation was thus recognized just as fundamental to persons as race or sex The Context of Equality Claims When discussing the wrongs of unequal treatment under section 15(1), it is necessary to first identify the context in which equality claims are made. Claims under section 15(1) are made in relation to any government action or program that allocates some good or opportunity to a certain individual or group, while denying other individuals or groups the same good or opportunity. Such schemes are necessarily predicated on legislative distinctions, which accord unequal treatment. Most often, it is government distributive schemes or programs that are challenged under section 15(1) (i.e. programs that distribute economic or social benefits of some kind or another). Many 9 Miron v. Trudel, [1995] 2 S.C.R Miron v. Trudel, supra note 10, at Egan v. Canada, [1995] 2 S.C.R

12 legislative schemes employ some sort of distinction and therefore engage section 15(1). For instance, government policies will often make legislative distinctions on the basis of personal characteristics or attributes that serve as a qualification for the benefit in question. Likewise, government schemes may treat citizens unequally in less explicit ways, by failing to consider the needs of a certain group or individual. It is crucial to note, however, that while unequal treatment serves as the basis for section 15(1) claims, it cannot be that all differential or unequal treatment constitutes a violation of the right to equality. As acknowledged by the Court in Andrews v. Law Society of British Columbia, claimants must show that differential treatment amounts to discrimination in order to be successful under section 15(1). This view that the harm of unequal treatment is more than simply inequality qua inequality is also supported by Sophia Moreau who states that: [n]o plausible theory of equality maintains that what is objectionable about unequal treatment is the mere fact that some individuals end up with more or less than others. Rather, such theories hold that unequal treatment is objectionable when, and to the extent that, this treatment is unfair. 12 With this understanding of equality, the obligation of the government is not to eliminate all types of unequal treatment, but rather to justify those distinctions that come under section 15(1) as fair or legitimate. 13 For the purposes of this paper, the pertinent question is, then, what makes certain types of treatment unfair or illegitimate? Put another way, what are the harms of unequal treatment, and why are they harmful? Responding to these and related questions will be the focus of the rest of this paper. 12 Moreau, supra note 3 at See R. v. Oakes, supra note 6. 8

13 1.3. Conclusion Thus far we have looked at section 15 as interpreted by the courts and the context in which equality claims have been made. We have seen that section 15 provides for every individual a guarantee of equality before and under the law, as well as the equal protection and equal benefit of the law without discrimination. While the Charter itself provides no guidance as to what it means for the government to treat its citizens as equals, nor what constitutes discrimination in breach of section 15, features of section 15, such as the enumerated and analogous grounds, suggest that the proper role of the equality guarantee is not to eliminate all unfairness from our laws, but rather to eliminate discrimination based on immutable personal characteristics. The Supreme Court later worked its way towards an understanding of section 15 based on the concept of human dignity as the underlying interest grounding claims of equality. As we will now see, many have questioned whether the concept of human dignity has the substantive content necessary to ascertain and delineate why certain types of unequal treatment are illegitimate and so I turn now to examine just that. That is, can the concept of human dignity help to conceptualize the wrongs of unequal treatment? 9

14 II. Human Dignity and Section 15 of the Charter Human dignity, while a central value guiding equality rights, has been charged for ambiguity and indeterminacy. In what follows, I will examine the past efforts of the Supreme Court of Canada to develop a substantive conception of equality based on the value of human dignity and argue that the legal test presented in Law v. Canada fails to make good use of the concept and that this has rendered the Court less able to recognise discriminatory instances in which the claimant has suffered a wrong. I will show that the Court has used dignity not in the objective sense but rather as a subjective concept, confining the analysis to the individual, and identifying a person s dignity with his or her feelings. My aim in this chapter is to defend the thesis that the concept of human dignity, understood objectively as involving autonomy and self-determination, can provide us with meaningful content that explains why certain types of unequal treatment are forms of discrimination and are thereby unfair and illegitimate. Human dignity in its application, I will argue, can help ascertain how equality is to be conceived, specified and realised under section 15 of the Charter. I will proceed in five sections. Section 1.1 will begin with a brief introduction of human dignity as it has emerged in the legal discourse. Section 1.2, will detail the philosophical foundations of human dignity. Section 1.3 will examine how human dignity has been presented and used in the Courts pre- and post- Law v. Canada. Section 1.4 will highlight the problems with the dignity interest, as used by the Courts. Finally Section 1.5 will explore my own interpretation of human dignity, one that, I argue, escapes the problems plagued by other conceptions.

15 II.1.1. Dignity and Equality Rights As we have seen, in Law v. Canada the Supreme Court of Canada issued a unanimous opinion, written by Justice Frank Iacobucci, that provided a new interpretation of section 15 of the Charter. The new consensus was that discrimination in section 15 involved an additional element to a distinction based on a listed or analogous ground that additional element was an impairment of human dignity. And though Iacobucci J., did not define human dignity, he did suggest four contextual factors that were to facilitate the inquiry. The four contextual factors are: (1) pre-existing disadvantage, vulnerability, stereotyping, or prejudice; (2) correspondence between the distinction and the actual needs, merits and circumstances of the members of the group affected by it; (3) whether the impugned provision has ameliorative purposes for a more disadvantaged group; and (4) the nature of the interest affected by the distinction. 14 There have been many criticisms of the concept of human dignity, but two predominate: first, the concept is vague and contentious members of the Supreme Court have often disagreed amongst themselves on the question of whether the impugned law impairs the human dignity of the claimant; second, it is burdensome to claimants as it introduces a new element to section 15 thereby establishing yet another barrier to finding a violation of section 15(1). 15 Indeed, scholarly disagreement about the foundations of human dignity and about its substantive meaning when applied to practical cases attests to the principle s vagueness and indeterminacy. This ambiguity is only made more problematic when dignity is elevated from its status as a moral value to that of a judicially enforceable legal test, as was established in Law. 14 Law, supra note 8, at para See page 30 for more on these criticisms. 11

16 The court abandoned the use of dignity as a legal test in R. v. Kapp 16, a 2008 Supreme Court case which found that a communal fishing license granted exclusively to Aboriginals did not violate section 15 of the Charter. It might be thought, therefore, that the Supreme Court rightly has given up on human dignity as a principle guiding human rights. 17 However, in this chapter, I will suggest that we can and should retrieve the valuable content inherent in human dignity, though not before we assess what is specifically useful about the concept. While Justice Iacobucci was simply content that there can be different conceptions of what dignity means, 18 without any examination of these different conceptions, I would suggest that, to the contrary, it is crucial that we closely examine the various accounts of dignity to specify a determinate meaning for the term. Thus, I turn first to the philosophical foundations of human dignity to help elucidate the conceptual problems within it and shore up the valuable content, which I believe is useful to a section 15 analysis. II.1.2. Philosophical Foundations of Human Dignity Human dignity has been a ubiquitous theoretical justification for human rights in Canada. As a legal value, human dignity is most commonly associated with post-second World War international legal developments. 19 As a reaction to the atrocities committed by the Nazis in World War II, the global community united around the belief in the equal 16 R. v. Kapp, [2008] 2 S.C.R. 483, 2008 SCC Thomas M.J. Bateman notes that Justice L Heureux-Dube, at the time of Law v. Canada, was the leading equality rights advocate on the court, and she retired in Thus, he suggests that L Heureux- Dube largely influenced the adoption of human dignity in the Law test and after her retirement in 2002, Justice Beverly McLachlin, who was promoted to Chief Justice in 2000, may have exercised influence in favor of a more restrained approach to Law s dignity test. See: Bateman, Thomas M. "Human Dignity's False Start in the Supreme Court of Canada: Equality Rights and the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms." The International Journal of Human Rights 16.4 (2012): Print. 18 Law, supra note 8, at para Bateman, supra note 18, p 2. 12

17 and inalienable worth of all members of the human family. The Universal Declaration of Human Rights is a statement of the commitment to protecting this fundamental human value. Human dignity is mentioned in the 1945 United Nations Charter, the preamble of the two 1966 Covenants emanating from the Universal Declaration, and virtually all human-rights declarations, conventions, and international court statutes. Although the concept does not explicitly appear in the Canadian Constitution, the concept has entered through judicial construction, engulfing Charter decisions and acting as a justificatory rhetorical device. As Justice MacIntyre stated in Kapp, There can be no doubt that human dignity is an essential value underlying the section 15 equality guarantee. In fact, the protection of all the rights guaranteed by the Charter has as its lodestar the promotion of human dignity. 20 Certainly, the idea of human dignity is rhetorically compelling. The Court is guided by values and principles essential to a free and democratic society and respect for the inherent dignity of the human person is a central value that highlights our commitment to social justice and equality. This is not to say, however, that there is a clear consensus on the idea s meaning. 21 Ranging from ancient stoicism through Christian theology to Kantian ethics and liberal thought, human dignity emanates from a myriad of intellectual origins. Though all accounts specify dignity as features of humanity, they do so in various ways. In what follows, I outline and briefly examine what I take to be the three most distinct and notable accounts of human dignity. 20 R. v. Kapp, supra note 16, at para Bateman, supra note 18, p 2. 13

18 II Dignity Grounded in Rights Dignity as rights-grounding derives from the Kantian tradition, which highlights reason as a central and inimitable human quality. Kant offers us an understanding of autonomy as the possession of practical reason, which gives its possessor the ability to think and decide for herself what to value, what to do, and how to live. 22 The emphasis here is on the intrinsic worth and dignity of all rational beings. To say that we should respect autonomy, or that we should respect people as autonomous beings, is to say that we should take this feature of persons as calling for a response, limiting our behaviour toward them in certain ways, and demanding types of behaviour in others. For Kant, respecting autonomy involves respecting people s ability to direct their own lives, refraining from interfering with their choices, and from imposing burdens on them that they would not themselves endorse. As autonomous beings we are able to act as selflegislatures. We are able to subject ourselves, not to the will of others, but rather to the requirements of right reason, which we can discover for ourselves using our own intellect. Thus, respect for autonomy urges us to let people decide for themselves how to lead their lives to interfere would bespeak a failure to appreciate the value of autonomy and one s power to generate reasons. On this rights-grounding account, how one uses one s rights is not central. Rather, dignity is linked to the making of autonomous choices, not to the choices one makes. On the Kantian understanding then, dignity is an unchanging and supreme value that inheres in every human being; that is, in Kant s words, the idea of a human being s unconditional and incomparable worth Immanuel Kant. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. Ed. Mary J. Gregor. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge UP, Print. 23 Paraphrased in: Moreau, Sophia, The Wrongs of Unequal Treatment in Fay Faraday, Margaret Denike, and M. Kate Stephenson, eds. Making Equality Rights Real: Securing Substantive Equality under the 14

19 For Sophia Moreau, however, because this worth is unconditional and thus independent of the individual s circumstances, or the extent to which she is actually shown respect by others, it follows that one s dignity cannot be diminished by others disregard for it. Hence, even if an individual is discriminated against, this cannot diminish her dignity in the objective sense, as she will always have a claim to concern and respect for her supreme worth. For Moreau, then, the objective conception of dignity, on its own, does not have sufficient content to explain the precise nature of the wrongs that are done to individuals who are not treated with equal concern and respect. That is, because the idea that all human beings simply have unconditional worth does not tell us what kinds of treatment fail to show proper consideration for that worth. The abstract ideal of equal concern and respect for dignity, Moreau argues, must therefore be given content by a substantial conception of what kinds of treatment violate human dignity. 24 II Dignity Grounded in Status Dignity as status-grounding takes a comprehensive look at humanity itself as an inalienable status which all persons possess and which brings obligations. As a result of one s status as a human being, one has certain duties to oneself and to others. On this account, then, dignity acts as a constraint on an agent s exercise of freedom that is to say, one s freedom is limited by one s status as a human being. Thomas M.J. Bateman illustrates this nicely, arguing that while prostitution on the rights-grounding account may be consistent with human dignity if it is freely chosen (rather than undertaken for survival), on the status-grounding view, it may nevertheless be a violation of one s duty to humanity since it is a form of degrading one s person. Charter (Toronto: Irwin Law, 2006) p 295. Original citation: Immanuel Kant, Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals, trans. James W. Ellington (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1993) at s. II, We will see this in detail in Chapter 2. 15

20 There have also been some efforts to synthesise the status-grounding view with rights-grounding accounts. George Kateb, for example, takes dignity to be an existential value defining what it is to be human. The human on his account includes, developed or distinctive selfhood, autonomy, authenticity, freedom, equality, power for its own sake, virtues for their own sake, perfectionism of character or style of life, honor, glory and fame 25. These features thus make up people s unique capacity to be agents with purposes. 26 Bateman suggests that while Kateb s attempt to combine the rightsgrounding and status-grounding views is compelling, it still leaves open questions on the limits that status places on rights. That is, are acts of freedom always dignified and can one act in a way to deny one s own humanity? Part of the problem, Bateman suggests, is determining what forms of human conduct are substantively caught by the idea of dignity. Actions can have various degrees of harm and so we might ask whether dignity seeks to establish a floor of conduct below which no deleterious action shall be countenanced; or [whether it reaches for] the ceiling, protecting humans from relatively minor affronts? 27 II Dignity Grounded in Emotion Finally, dignity grounded in emotion identifies what one feels as the litmus test of dignity. Feelings of indignation, for instance, signal an affront to human dignity. Thus, Bateman argues, by means of an emotional connection with the fate of others, we become aware of the indignity done to them by imagining ourselves in their position and 25 George Kateb, Human Dignity (Cambridge, MA: Belknap/Harvard University Press, 2011). P 12. See also: Bateman, supra note 18, p Kateb, supra note 26, at p 38. See also: Bateman, supra note 18, p Bateman, supra note 18, p 4. 16

21 then reflecting on our own reaction to that condition. 28 In historian Lynn Hunt s words, you know the meaning of human rights because you feel distressed when they are violated. 29 This account is largely based on the Humean tradition in which, morality is determined by sentiment 30. That is, while Kant seeks to ground morality in reason, David Hume, conversely, takes the emotivist position, seeking to preserve passion as taking priority. Hence, according to Hume, reason is and should be a slave of passions. II.1.3. Dignity And The Law Test Now that we have looked at some of the philosophical underpinnings of human dignity, let us turn to how the concept has been presented and used by the courts. The Supreme Court of Canada in R. v. Oakes declared that, when applying section 1 to rights violations, it must be guided by principles essential to a free and democratic society, one of which is respect for the inherent dignity of the human person. 31 Likewise, Justice McIntyre described the purpose of section 15 in Andrews v. Law Society 32 as that which ensures that all individuals are recognized at law as human beings equally deserving of concern, respect and consideration. The power of human dignity is such that some have suggested it be the subject of a right itself. However, this approach has been rejected by the courts, finding human dignity rather to be the basis for Charter rights such as equality. In Blencoe v. British Columbia (Human Rights Commission) 33, the court held that dignity has never been recognized by this Court as an independent right but rather has been 28 Bateman, supra note 18, p Lynn Hunt, Inventing Human Rights: A History (New York:W.W. Norton, 2007), 214; see also Bateman, supra note 18, p David Hume, An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals (Amherst: Prometheus Books, 2004 [1751]), R. v. Oakes, supra note 6, at para Andrews v. Law Society of British Columbia,, supra note 2, at Blencoe v. British Columbia (Human Rights Commission) [2000] 2 S.C.R

22 viewed as finding expression in rights, such as equality, privacy or protection from state compulsion 34. Thus, with the rejection of dignity as a free-standing right and the adoption of the concept as a tool for equality jurisprudence, the courts moved to a new section 15 interpretation in Law v. Canada, finding dignity to have the status of a legal rule. That is, the judicial interpretation of discrimination under section 15 was as follows: (1) The challenged law imposes (directly or indirectly) on the claimant a disadvantage (in the form of a burden or withheld benefit) in comparison to other comparable persons; (2) The disadvantage is based on a ground listed in or analogous to a ground listed in s. 15; and (3) The disadvantage also constitutes an impairment of the human dignity of the claimant. 35 Thus, the claimant who persuades the Court of these three elements is entitled to a finding of discrimination, meaning that the impugned law is in breach of section 15. More than a legal rule, the decision in Law held the prevention of the violation of human dignity to be the purpose of section 15. Law provides a telling statement of this purpose: It may be said that the purpose of s. 15(1) is to prevent the violation of essential human dignity and freedom through the imposition of disadvantage, stereotyping, or political or social prejudice, and to promote a society in which all persons enjoy equal recognition at law as human beings or as members of Canadian society, equally capable and equally deserving of concern, respect and consideration. Legislation which effects differential treatment between individuals or groups will violate this fundamental purpose where those who are subject to differential treatment fall within one or more enumerated or analogous grounds, and where the differential treatment reflects the stereotypical application of presumed group or personal characteristics, or otherwise has the effect of perpetuating or promoting the view that the individual is less capable or less worthy of recognition or value as a human being or as a member of Canadian society Ibid., at para Hogg, supra note 5, at S. 55.8(a). 36 Law, supra note 8, at para

23 In Law, the court considered a claim of age-based discrimination against the federal government for tailoring Canada Pension Plan survivor benefits by age. The impugned legislation dictated that the younger the survivor, the smaller the benefit. Nancy Law, a widow at 30 years of age, failed to meet the requirements for the survivor s benefit: she had no dependents, was not disabled, and was under the age of 35. The court took the opportunity in Law to re-articulate the section 15 test and consequently created the three-step analysis. First, Ms. Law was to establish that she had received differential treatment, that is, she was to demonstrate that she had been denied a benefit that others received. Second, she was to show that the differential treatment occurred on an enumerated or analogous ground. Finally, she was to demonstrate that this unequal treatment was unfair, or amounted to discrimination which, according to the Court in Law, involved showing that her dignity was infringed, in the sense that a reasonable person in her position would have been made to feel inferior. For the purpose of this Chapter, my focus will remain on the role of dignity within the Law test. In this regard, Justice Frank Iacobucci declared that the specific, albeit non-exhaustive definition was drawn from previous s. 15(1) jurisprudence: [The] equality guarantee in s. 15(1) is concerned with the realization of personal autonomy and self-determination. Human dignity means that an individual or group feels self-respect and self-worth. It is concerned with physical and psychological integrity and empowerment. Human dignity is harmed by unfair treatment premised upon personal traits or circumstances, which do not relate to individual needs, capacities, and merits. It is enhanced by laws, which are sensitive to the needs, capacities, and merits of different individuals, taking into account the context underlying their differences. Human dignity is harmed when individuals and groups are marginalized, ignored, or devalued, and is enhanced when laws recognize the full place of all individuals and groups within Canadian society. Human dignity within the meaning of the equality guarantee does not relate to the status or position of an individual in society per se, but rather concerns the manner in which a person legitimately feels when confronted with a 19

24 particular law. 37 Perhaps recognising the lack of clarity in his definition of dignity, Justice Iacobucci sought to supplement the definition with the four contextual factors 38, which were to provide guidance to the courts in determining whether the claimant s dignity had been harmed. Again, the contextual factors are (1) pre-existing disadvantage, vulnerability, stereotyping, or prejudice; (2) correspondence between the distinction and the actual needs, merits and circumstances of the members of the group affected by it; (3) whether the impugned provision has ameliorative purposes for a more disadvantaged group; and (4) the nature of the interest affected by the distinction. 39 To be sure, Justice Iacobucci did stress that these factors were neither necessary nor exhaustive in determining a violation of human dignity and cautioned against their use as a formal checklist. The connection between the contextual factors and the dignity interest, however, has never been specified and as a result, subsequent cases have done exactly what was advised against 40 that is, the contextual factors have been applied as a formal test and cases have been decided on the basis of one or more of these factors, rather than an overall analysis of the impact of legislation on dignity itself. Consequently, under the term dignity, the court unanimously dismissed Nancy Law s case. The court held, and with little evidence, that [r]elatively speaking, adults under the age of 45 have not been consistently and routinely subjected to the sorts of discrimination faced by some of Canada s discrete and insular minorities Law, supra note 8 at para. 53. (Emphasis added) 38 Law, supra note 8 at para Law, supra note 8, at para Réaume, supra note 9, at p. 17, Law, supra note 8, at para

25 II.1.4. Problems with Dignity in Law: An Emotion-Grounding Account Although the deployment of the idea of dignity in the Charter jurisprudence is in many ways ground-breaking in its recognition of the far-reaching impact of unequal treatment, the interpretation of dignity has some significant problems. In particular, the concept of dignity adopted in Law is chiefly focused on the emotions-grounding account of dignity, of which we saw earlier that is, on the subjective feelings of the claimant. Justice Iacobucci s associates human dignity with feelings of self-respect and self-worth and with physical and psychological integrity and empowerment ; thus, dignity becomes an evaluation of what the court determines a reasonable claimant would legitimately feel when treated in a certain way by the impugned law. Determining an affront on human dignity based on the feelings of the claimant amounts to treating an affront to dignity as an emotion or feeling. 42 Rather than reducing harm to dignity as a matter of hurt feelings, I would suggest, along with Denise Réaume, that the dignity interest should be understood as an independent objective harm. To be sure, discrimination will absolutely affect the personal subjective feelings of those adversely affected, but to reduce the section 15(1) Charter guarantee to a protection of emotional harm would be a trivial interpretation of the equality rights protected by the Charter. It is not the job of section 15(1) of the Charter to protect persons from humiliation. As Réaume suggests, Feelings of worthlessness may be a common symptom of disrespectful treatment and relevant diagnostically, but the evil to be prevented or remedied is the attribution of unworthiness. 43 Moreau adds that the real rationale for using the perspective of the reasonable person is to ensure that the 42 Réaume, Denise G., Law v. Canada (Minister of Employment and Immigration) (2006) 18 Can. J. Women L. 143, p Ibid. 21

26 courts assess not just whether the claimant has come to feel inferior, but whether this feeling is the direct result of unfair treatment. Herein lies the problem, Moreau contends: unfairness is not demonstrated simply by the individual s feelings but rather must appeal to some other substantive conception of what makes unequal treatment into a wrong against the individual. 44 What is more, this emotion-grounded account of dignity acts to reduce the value in dignity to an experiential good, 45 identifying inequality within the individual instead of in the broader coercive social structures of society. Indeed, it is the coercive social structure and the individual relations (and transactions) within the basic structure that have the most profound effects on the individual. 46 If section 15 s purpose of providing substantive equality 47 is to have any critical bite, the analysis must be focused towards identifying concrete, objective harm. It must look to unequal social structures of power and their impact on the needs, opportunities, flourishing and overall well-being of individuals in society. Section 15 of the Charter must protect every individual as objectively valuable and equally deserving of concern, respect and consideration. 48 The purpose is not to protect subjective feelings of empowerment and esteem. An impugned legislation may nonetheless have discriminatory effects regardless of whether the person who is adversely affected feels demeaned or devalued. Similarly, a law or policy may be 44 Moreau, supra note 3, p Ibid. 46 See: A Theory of Justice, Revised Edition (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1999), p. 7. The institutions that make up the basic structure, according to Rawls, include [t]he political constitution the legally recognized forms of property, and the structure of the economy as well as the family in some form (Justice as Fairness: A Restatement (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2001), p. 10). 47 The courts have stated that the purpose of section 15 is not to pursue formal equality, but substantive equality, a concept with has yet to be defined or enumerated by the courts. The courts acknowledgment of substantive equality only addresses the fact that treating likes alike can in fact produce inequalities and differential treatment will not always result in inequality. 48 Andrews v. Law Society of British Columbia,, supra note 2, at para

27 in violation of section 15(1) even if, as Réaume writes, it fails to bring the targets down in their own estimation. 49 Again, this is not to deny that objective wrongs will have a negative impact on personal feelings or that discriminatory treatment will generally involve feelings of lesser worth and a diminished sense of self-respect this most certainly will be true. My argument here, however, is simply that objective wrongs should not be determined on this basis. Eldridge v. British Columbia 50, a pre-law decision where legislation that failed to provide sign language interpreters to deaf persons in hospitals was found in violation of section 15(1), demonstrates my argument. Indeed denying an individual an effective voice to comprehend and then make decisions regarding their medical treatment would affect one s feelings of self-worth and respect. However, rather than focusing on how such treatment affects one s feelings, the Court directed their attention on the persistent social and economic disadvantage faced by the disabled. 51 The basis for finding a violation of section 15(1) in this case was that denying this service resulted in deaf persons receiving a lower standard of medical treatment. Thus, Eldridge provides a powerful illustration of why it is the objective conceptions of the wrong that must be determinative of the discrimination issues. Not only are feelings of self-worth and self-respect much too subjective to be meaningfully guarded by the law, but allowing the courts to play the role of the final arbitrator of claimants feelings is a risky business for it can imply that what is at issue is sensitivity on the part of the victim, rather than the violation of his or her rights. Even the 49 Réaume, supra note 45, p 162 at para Eldridge v. British Columbia (Attorney General), [1997] 3 S.C.R Ibid., at para

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory Western University Scholarship@Western 2015 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2015 Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory David Hakim Western University, davidhakim266@gmail.com

More information

90 South Cascade Avenue, Suite 1500, Colorado Springs, Colorado Telephone: Fax:

90 South Cascade Avenue, Suite 1500, Colorado Springs, Colorado Telephone: Fax: 90 South Cascade Avenue, Suite 1500, Colorado Springs, Colorado 80903-1639 Telephone: 719.475.2440 Fax: 719.635.4576 www.shermanhoward.com MEMORANDUM TO: FROM: Ministry and Church Organization Clients

More information

In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of

In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of Glasgow s Conception of Kantian Humanity Richard Dean ABSTRACT: In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of the humanity formulation of the Categorical Imperative.

More information

SANDEL ON RELIGION IN THE PUBLIC SQUARE

SANDEL ON RELIGION IN THE PUBLIC SQUARE SANDEL ON RELIGION IN THE PUBLIC SQUARE Hugh Baxter For Boston University School of Law s Conference on Michael Sandel s Justice October 14, 2010 In the final chapter of Justice, Sandel calls for a new

More information

Association of Justice Counsel v. Attorney General of Canada Request for Case Management Court File No. CV

Association of Justice Counsel v. Attorney General of Canada Request for Case Management Court File No. CV Andrew Lokan T 416.646.4324 Asst 416.646.7411 F 416.646.4323 E andrew.lokan@paliareroland.com www.paliareroland.com File 18211 June 15, 2011 Via Fax The Honourable Justice Duncan Grace Dear Justice Grace:

More information

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS SECOND SECTION by Immanuel Kant TRANSITION FROM POPULAR MORAL PHILOSOPHY TO THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS... This principle, that humanity and generally every

More information

Zdenko Kodelja HOW TO UNDERSTAND EQUITY IN HIGHER EDUCATION? (Draft)

Zdenko Kodelja HOW TO UNDERSTAND EQUITY IN HIGHER EDUCATION? (Draft) Zdenko Kodelja HOW TO UNDERSTAND EQUITY IN HIGHER EDUCATION? (Draft) The question How to understand equity in higher education? presupposes that it is not clear enough what exactly equity means. If this

More information

Freedom's Law: The Moral Reading of the American Constitution.

Freedom's Law: The Moral Reading of the American Constitution. Freedom's Law: The Moral Reading of the American Constitution. By Ronald Dworkin. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1996.389 pp. Kenneth Einar Himma University of Washington In Freedom's Law, Ronald

More information

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to: Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS MGT604 CHAPTER OBJECTIVES After exploring this chapter, you will be able to: 1. Explain the ethical framework of utilitarianism. 2. Describe how utilitarian

More information

DRAFT PAPER DO NOT QUOTE

DRAFT PAPER DO NOT QUOTE DRAFT PAPER DO NOT QUOTE Religious Norms in Public Sphere UC, Berkeley, May 2011 Catholic Rituals and Symbols in Government Institutions: Juridical Arrangements, Political Debates and Secular Issues in

More information

Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social

Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social position one ends up occupying, while John Harsanyi s version of the veil tells contractors that they are equally likely

More information

Positivism A Model Of For System Of Rules

Positivism A Model Of For System Of Rules Positivism A Model Of For System Of Rules Positivism is a model of and for a system of rules, and its central notion of a single fundamental test for law forces us to miss the important standards that

More information

Does law have to be effective in order for it to be valid?

Does law have to be effective in order for it to be valid? University of Birmingham Birmingham Law School Jurisprudence 2007-08 Assessed Essay (Second Round) Does law have to be effective in order for it to be valid? It is important to consider the terms valid

More information

PARTS I AND II OVERVIEW AND POSITION

PARTS I AND II OVERVIEW AND POSITION 1 PARTS I AND II OVERVIEW AND POSITION 1. While these cases stand to be decided on a Doré analysis, questions about the identity of the person(s) whose section 2(a) rights have been interfered with lurk

More information

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981). Draft of 3-21- 13 PHIL 202: Core Ethics; Winter 2013 Core Sequence in the History of Ethics, 2011-2013 IV: 19 th and 20 th Century Moral Philosophy David O. Brink Handout #14: Williams, Internalism, and

More information

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1 310 Book Review Book Review ISSN (Print) 1225-4924, ISSN (Online) 2508-3104 Catholic Theology and Thought, Vol. 79, July 2017 http://dx.doi.org/10.21731/ctat.2017.79.310 A Review on What Is This Thing

More information

Law and Authority. An unjust law is not a law

Law and Authority. An unjust law is not a law Law and Authority An unjust law is not a law The statement an unjust law is not a law is often treated as a summary of how natural law theorists approach the question of whether a law is valid or not.

More information

Aristotle's Theory of Friendship Tested. Syra Mehdi

Aristotle's Theory of Friendship Tested. Syra Mehdi Aristotle's Theory of Friendship Tested Syra Mehdi Is friendship a more important value than honesty? To respond to the question, consider this scenario: two high school students, Jamie and Tyler, who

More information

Dworkin on the Rufie of Recognition

Dworkin on the Rufie of Recognition Dworkin on the Rufie of Recognition NANCY SNOW University of Notre Dame In the "Model of Rules I," Ronald Dworkin criticizes legal positivism, especially as articulated in the work of H. L. A. Hart, and

More information

Equality, Fairness, and Responsibility in an Unequal World

Equality, Fairness, and Responsibility in an Unequal World Equality, Fairness, and Responsibility in an Unequal World Thom Brooks Abstract: Severe poverty is a major global problem about risk and inequality. What, if any, is the relationship between equality,

More information

Positivism, Natural Law, and Disestablishment: Some Questions Raised by MacCormick's Moralistic Amoralism

Positivism, Natural Law, and Disestablishment: Some Questions Raised by MacCormick's Moralistic Amoralism Valparaiso University Law Review Volume 20 Number 1 pp.55-60 Fall 1985 Positivism, Natural Law, and Disestablishment: Some Questions Raised by MacCormick's Moralistic Amoralism Joseph M. Boyle Jr. Recommended

More information

FREEDOM AND THE SOURCE OF VALUE: KORSGAARD AND WOOD ON KANT S FORMULA OF HUMANITY CHRISTOPHER ARROYO

FREEDOM AND THE SOURCE OF VALUE: KORSGAARD AND WOOD ON KANT S FORMULA OF HUMANITY CHRISTOPHER ARROYO Published by Blackwell Publishing Ltd, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK, and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA METAPHILOSOPHY Vol. 42, No. 4, July 2011 0026-1068 FREEDOM AND THE SOURCE OF

More information

Resolution adopted by the General Assembly. [on the report of the Third Committee (A/65/456/Add.2 (Part II))]

Resolution adopted by the General Assembly. [on the report of the Third Committee (A/65/456/Add.2 (Part II))] United Nations A/RES/65/211 General Assembly Distr.: General 30 March 2011 Sixty-fifth session Agenda item 68 (b) Resolution adopted by the General Assembly [on the report of the Third Committee (A/65/456/Add.2

More information

Rawls, rationality, and responsibility: Why we should not treat our endowments as morally arbitrary

Rawls, rationality, and responsibility: Why we should not treat our endowments as morally arbitrary Rawls, rationality, and responsibility: Why we should not treat our endowments as morally arbitrary OLIVER DUROSE Abstract John Rawls is primarily known for providing his own argument for how political

More information

Compendium of key international human rights agreements concerning Freedom of Religion or Belief

Compendium of key international human rights agreements concerning Freedom of Religion or Belief Compendium of key international human rights agreements concerning Freedom of Religion or Belief Contents Introduction... 2 United Nations agreements/documents... 2 The Universal Declaration of Human Rights,

More information

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS By MARANATHA JOY HAYES A THESIS PRESENTED TO THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF THE UNIVERSITY OF FLORIDA IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS

More information

PRESS DEFINITION AND THE RELIGION ANALOGY

PRESS DEFINITION AND THE RELIGION ANALOGY PRESS DEFINITION AND THE RELIGION ANALOGY RonNell Andersen Jones In her Article, Press Exceptionalism, 1 Professor Sonja R. West urges the Court to differentiate a specially protected sub-category of the

More information

Comment on Martha Nussbaum s Purified Patriotism

Comment on Martha Nussbaum s Purified Patriotism Comment on Martha Nussbaum s Purified Patriotism Patriotism is generally thought to require a special attachment to the particular: to one s own country and to one s fellow citizens. It is therefore thought

More information

A CONTRACTUALIST READING OF KANT S PROOF OF THE FORMULA OF HUMANITY. Adam Cureton

A CONTRACTUALIST READING OF KANT S PROOF OF THE FORMULA OF HUMANITY. Adam Cureton A CONTRACTUALIST READING OF KANT S PROOF OF THE FORMULA OF HUMANITY Adam Cureton Abstract: Kant offers the following argument for the Formula of Humanity: Each rational agent necessarily conceives of her

More information

They said WHAT!? A brief analysis of the Supreme Court of Canada s decision in S.L. v. Commission Scolaire des Chênes (2012 SCC 7)

They said WHAT!? A brief analysis of the Supreme Court of Canada s decision in S.L. v. Commission Scolaire des Chênes (2012 SCC 7) They said WHAT!? A brief analysis of the Supreme Court of Canada s decision in S.L. v. Commission Scolaire des Chênes (2012 SCC 7) By Don Hutchinson February 27, 2012 The Evangelical Fellowship of Canada

More information

This document consists of 10 printed pages.

This document consists of 10 printed pages. Cambridge International Examinations Cambridge International Advanced Level THINKING SKILLS 9694/43 Paper 4 Applied Reasoning MARK SCHEME imum Mark: 50 Published This mark scheme is published as an aid

More information

Rethinking Development: the Centrality of Human Rights

Rethinking Development: the Centrality of Human Rights Annabelle Wong Conflicting sentiments regarding the idea of development reflect the controversial aspects of development practices such as sweatshop labor and human trafficking. Development is commonly

More information

To link to this article:

To link to this article: This article was downloaded by: [University of Chicago Library] On: 24 May 2013, At: 08:10 Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office:

More information

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Author: Terence Rajivan Edward, University of Manchester. Abstract. In the sixth chapter of The View from Nowhere, Thomas Nagel attempts to identify a form of idealism.

More information

ON THE INCOMPATIBILITY BETWEEN ARISTOTLE S AND KANT S IMPERATIVES TO TREAT A MAN NOT AS A MEANS BUT AS AN END-IN- HIMSELF

ON THE INCOMPATIBILITY BETWEEN ARISTOTLE S AND KANT S IMPERATIVES TO TREAT A MAN NOT AS A MEANS BUT AS AN END-IN- HIMSELF 1 ON THE INCOMPATIBILITY BETWEEN ARISTOTLE S AND KANT S IMPERATIVES TO TREAT A MAN NOT AS A MEANS BUT AS AN END-IN- HIMSELF Extract pp. 88-94 from the dissertation by Irene Caesar Why we should not be

More information

Declaration on the Elimination of All Forms of Intolerance and of Discrimination Based on Religion or Belief

Declaration on the Elimination of All Forms of Intolerance and of Discrimination Based on Religion or Belief Declaration on the Elimination of All Forms of Intolerance and of Discrimination Based on Religion or Belief Proclaimed by General Assembly of the United Nations on 25 November 1981 (resolution 36/55)

More information

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp.

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp. 330 Interpretation and Legal Theory Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp. Reviewed by Lawrence E. Thacker* Interpretation may be defined roughly as the process of determining the meaning

More information

On the Rawlsian Anthropology and the "Autonomous" Account

On the Rawlsian Anthropology and the Autonomous Account University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor Critical Reflections Essays of Significance & Critical Reflections 2017 Mar 31st, 10:30 AM - 11:00 AM On the Rawlsian Anthropology and the "Autonomous" Account

More information

Article 31 under Part 3 on Fundamental Rights and Duties of current draft Constitution provides for Right to Religious freedom:

Article 31 under Part 3 on Fundamental Rights and Duties of current draft Constitution provides for Right to Religious freedom: HAUT-COMMISSARIAT AUX DROITS DE L HOMME OFFICE OF THE HIGH COMMISSIONER FOR HUMAN RIGHTS PALAIS DES NATIONS 1211 GENEVA 10, SWITZERLAND www.ohchr.org TEL: +41 22 917 9359 / +41 22 917 9407 FAX: +41 22

More information

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central TWO PROBLEMS WITH SPINOZA S ARGUMENT FOR SUBSTANCE MONISM LAURA ANGELINA DELGADO * In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central metaphysical thesis that there is only one substance in the universe.

More information

Practical Wisdom and Politics

Practical Wisdom and Politics Practical Wisdom and Politics In discussing Book I in subunit 1.6, you learned that the Ethics specifically addresses the close relationship between ethical inquiry and politics. At the outset, Aristotle

More information

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10. Introduction This book seeks to provide a metaethical analysis of the responsibility ethics of two of its prominent defenders: H. Richard Niebuhr and Emmanuel Levinas. In any ethical writings, some use

More information

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström From: Who Owns Our Genes?, Proceedings of an international conference, October 1999, Tallin, Estonia, The Nordic Committee on Bioethics, 2000. THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström I shall be mainly

More information

John Charvet - The Nature and Limits of Human Equality

John Charvet - The Nature and Limits of Human Equality John Charvet - The Nature and Limits of Human Equality Schuppert, F. (2016). John Charvet - The Nature and Limits of Human Equality. Res Publica, 22(2), 243-247. DOI: 10.1007/s11158-016-9320-7 Published

More information

Your signature doesn t mean you endorse the guidelines; your comments, when added to the Annexe, will only enrich and strengthen the document.

Your signature doesn t mean you endorse the guidelines; your comments, when added to the Annexe, will only enrich and strengthen the document. Ladies and Gentlemen, Below is a declaration on laicity which was initiated by 3 leading academics from 3 different countries. As the declaration contains the diverse views and opinions of different academic

More information

No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships

No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships In his book Practical Ethics, Peter Singer advocates preference utilitarianism, which holds that the right

More information

Freedom of Religion and Law Schools: Trinity Western University

Freedom of Religion and Law Schools: Trinity Western University University of Newcastle - Australia From the SelectedWorks of Neil J Foster January 23, 2013 Freedom of Religion and Law Schools: Trinity Western University Neil J Foster Available at: https://works.bepress.com/neil_foster/66/

More information

Individualism, Equality, and Rights: Reactions to Jackson, Priest, And Katz

Individualism, Equality, and Rights: Reactions to Jackson, Priest, And Katz University of Miami Law School Institutional Repository University of Miami Law Review 10-1-2013 Individualism, Equality, and Rights: Reactions to Jackson, Priest, And Katz Thomas Scanlon Follow this and

More information

Bishop s Report To The Judicial Council Of The United Methodist Church

Bishop s Report To The Judicial Council Of The United Methodist Church Bishop s Report To The Judicial Council Of The United Methodist Church 1. This is the form which the Judicial Council is required to provide for the reporting of decisions of law made by bishops in response

More information

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism Mathais Sarrazin J.L. Mackie s Error Theory postulates that all normative claims are false. It does this based upon his denial of moral

More information

Book Review: The Constitutional Protection of Freedom of Expression, by Richard Moon

Book Review: The Constitutional Protection of Freedom of Expression, by Richard Moon Osgoode Hall Law Journal Volume 40, Number 3/4 (Fall/Winter 2002) Article 9 Book Review: The Constitutional Protection of Freedom of Expression, by Richard Moon Jamie Cameron Osgoode Hall Law School of

More information

POLITICAL SECULARISM AND PUBLIC REASON. THREE REMARKS ON AUDI S DEMOCRATIC AUTHORITY AND THE SEPARATION OF CHURCH AND STATE

POLITICAL SECULARISM AND PUBLIC REASON. THREE REMARKS ON AUDI S DEMOCRATIC AUTHORITY AND THE SEPARATION OF CHURCH AND STATE SYMPOSIUM THE CHURCH AND THE STATE POLITICAL SECULARISM AND PUBLIC REASON. THREE REMARKS ON AUDI S DEMOCRATIC AUTHORITY AND THE SEPARATION OF CHURCH AND STATE BY JOCELYN MACLURE 2013 Philosophy and Public

More information

Chapter 2: Reasoning about ethics

Chapter 2: Reasoning about ethics Chapter 2: Reasoning about ethics 2012 Cengage Learning All Rights reserved Learning Outcomes LO 1 Explain how important moral reasoning is and how to apply it. LO 2 Explain the difference between facts

More information

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have served as the point of departure for much of the most interesting work that

More information

RELIGION OR BELIEF. Submission by the British Humanist Association to the Discrimination Law Review Team

RELIGION OR BELIEF. Submission by the British Humanist Association to the Discrimination Law Review Team RELIGION OR BELIEF Submission by the British Humanist Association to the Discrimination Law Review Team January 2006 The British Humanist Association (BHA) 1. The BHA is the principal organisation representing

More information

The Conflict Between Authority and Autonomy from Robert Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (1970)

The Conflict Between Authority and Autonomy from Robert Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (1970) The Conflict Between Authority and Autonomy from Robert Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (1970) 1. The Concept of Authority Politics is the exercise of the power of the state, or the attempt to influence

More information

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair FIRST STUDY The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair I 1. In recent decades, our understanding of the philosophy of philosophers such as Kant or Hegel has been

More information

Legal positivism represents a view about the nature of law. It states that

Legal positivism represents a view about the nature of law. It states that Legal Positivism A N I NTRODUCTION Polycarp Ikuenobe Legal positivism represents a view about the nature of law. It states that there is no necessary or conceptual connection between law and morality and

More information

Q2) The test of an ethical argument lies in the fact that others need to be able to follow it and come to the same result.

Q2) The test of an ethical argument lies in the fact that others need to be able to follow it and come to the same result. QUIZ 1 ETHICAL ISSUES IN MEDIA, BUSINESS AND SOCIETY WHAT IS ETHICS? Business ethics deals with values, facts, and arguments. Q2) The test of an ethical argument lies in the fact that others need to be

More information

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Version 1.1 Richard Baron 2 October 2016 1 Contents 1 Introduction 3 1.1 Availability and licence............ 3 2 Definitions of key terms 4 3

More information

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg 1 In Search of the Ontological Argument Richard Oxenberg Abstract We can attend to the logic of Anselm's ontological argument, and amuse ourselves for a few hours unraveling its convoluted word-play, or

More information

A Social Practice View of Natural Rights. Word Count: 2998

A Social Practice View of Natural Rights. Word Count: 2998 A Social Practice View of Natural Rights Word Count: 2998 Hume observes in the Treatise that the rules, by which properties, rights, and obligations are determin d, have in them no marks of a natural origin,

More information

From the ELCA s Draft Social Statement on Women and Justice

From the ELCA s Draft Social Statement on Women and Justice From the ELCA s Draft Social Statement on Women and Justice NOTE: This document includes only the Core Convictions, Analysis of Patriarchy and Sexism, Resources for Resisting Patriarchy and Sexism, and

More information

Student Engagement and Controversial Issues in Schools

Student Engagement and Controversial Issues in Schools 76 Dianne Gereluk University of Calgary Schools are not immune to being drawn into politically and morally contested debates in society. Indeed, one could say that schools are common sites of some of the

More information

Take Home Exam #2. PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert

Take Home Exam #2. PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert Name: Date: Take Home Exam #2 Instructions (Read Before Proceeding!) Material for this exam is from class sessions 8-15. Matching and fill-in-the-blank questions

More information

Apostasy and Conversion Kishan Manocha

Apostasy and Conversion Kishan Manocha Apostasy and Conversion Kishan Manocha In the context of a conference which tries to identify how the international community can strengthen its ability to protect religious freedom and, in particular,

More information

CANADIAN BROADCAST STANDARDS COUNCIL ONTARIO REGIONAL COUNCIL. CFRA-AM re the Lowell Green Show. (CBSC Decision 93/ ) Decided November 15, 1994

CANADIAN BROADCAST STANDARDS COUNCIL ONTARIO REGIONAL COUNCIL. CFRA-AM re the Lowell Green Show. (CBSC Decision 93/ ) Decided November 15, 1994 1 CANADIAN BROADCAST STANDARDS COUNCIL ONTARIO REGIONAL COUNCIL CFRA-AM re the Lowell Green Show (CBSC Decision 93/94-0276) Decided November 15, 1994 M. Barrie (Chair), R. Cohen (ad hoc), P. Fockler, R.

More information

EQUITY AND INCLUSIVE EDUCATION. The Catholic Community of Hamilton-Wentworth believes the learner will realize this fullness of humanity

EQUITY AND INCLUSIVE EDUCATION. The Catholic Community of Hamilton-Wentworth believes the learner will realize this fullness of humanity ADMINISTRATION HWCDSB 1. MISSION & VISION Mission The mission of Catholic Education in Hamilton-Wentworth, in union with our Bishop, is to enable all learners to realize the fullness of humanity of which

More information

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. The Physical World Author(s): Barry Stroud Source: Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, Vol. 87 (1986-1987), pp. 263-277 Published by: Blackwell Publishing on behalf of The Aristotelian

More information

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran Abstract In his (2015) paper, Robert Lockie seeks to add a contextualized, relativist

More information

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction 24 Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Abstract: In this paper, I address Linda Zagzebski s analysis of the relation between moral testimony and understanding arguing that Aquinas

More information

Religious Freedom Policy

Religious Freedom Policy Religious Freedom Policy 1. PURPOSE AND PHILOSOPHY 2 POLICY 1.1 Gateway Preparatory Academy promotes mutual understanding and respect for the interests and rights of all individuals regarding their beliefs,

More information

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Ralph Wedgwood 1 Two views of practical reason Suppose that you are faced with several different options (that is, several ways in which you might act in a

More information

PITTSBURGH. Issued: March 1993 Revised: October 2002 Updated: August 2003 Updated: August 2006 Updated: March 2008 Updated: April 2014

PITTSBURGH. Issued: March 1993 Revised: October 2002 Updated: August 2003 Updated: August 2006 Updated: March 2008 Updated: April 2014 Issued: March 1993 Revised: October 2002 Updated: August 2003 Updated: August 2006 Updated: March 2008 Updated: April 2014 CATHOLIC DIOCESE OF PITTSBURGH Clergy Sexual Misconduct The teaching of the Church,

More information

1/12. The A Paralogisms

1/12. The A Paralogisms 1/12 The A Paralogisms The character of the Paralogisms is described early in the chapter. Kant describes them as being syllogisms which contain no empirical premises and states that in them we conclude

More information

Hall (Litigation guardian of) v. Powers

Hall (Litigation guardian of) v. Powers Counsel: Hall (Litigation guardian of) v. Powers Between George Smitherman in his capacity as litigation guardian of Marc Hall, plaintiff, and Michael Powers and the Durham Catholic District School Board,

More information

A Contractualist Reply

A Contractualist Reply A Contractualist Reply The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Scanlon, T. M. 2008. A Contractualist Reply.

More information

Conditions of Fundamental Metaphysics: A critique of Jorge Gracia's proposal

Conditions of Fundamental Metaphysics: A critique of Jorge Gracia's proposal University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor Critical Reflections Essays of Significance & Critical Reflections 2016 Mar 12th, 1:30 PM - 2:00 PM Conditions of Fundamental Metaphysics: A critique of Jorge

More information

Habermas and Critical Thinking

Habermas and Critical Thinking 168 Ben Endres Columbia University In this paper, I propose to examine some of the implications of Jürgen Habermas s discourse ethics for critical thinking. Since the argument that Habermas presents is

More information

Hello again. Today we re gonna continue our discussions of Kant s ethics.

Hello again. Today we re gonna continue our discussions of Kant s ethics. PHI 110 Lecture 29 1 Hello again. Today we re gonna continue our discussions of Kant s ethics. Last time we talked about the good will and Kant defined the good will as the free rational will which acts

More information

TWO APPROACHES TO INSTRUMENTAL RATIONALITY

TWO APPROACHES TO INSTRUMENTAL RATIONALITY TWO APPROACHES TO INSTRUMENTAL RATIONALITY AND BELIEF CONSISTENCY BY JOHN BRUNERO JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY VOL. 1, NO. 1 APRIL 2005 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT JOHN BRUNERO 2005 I N SPEAKING

More information

The philosophy of human rights II: justifying HR. HUMR 5131 Fall 2017 Jakob Elster

The philosophy of human rights II: justifying HR. HUMR 5131 Fall 2017 Jakob Elster The philosophy of human rights II: justifying HR HUMR 5131 Fall 2017 Jakob Elster What do we justify? 1. The existence of moral human rights? a. The existence of MHR understood as «natual rights», i.e.

More information

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature Introduction The philosophical controversy about free will and determinism is perennial. Like many perennial controversies, this one involves a tangle of distinct but closely related issues. Thus, the

More information

What is the "Social" in "Social Coherence?" Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious Freedom in an Egalitarian Age

What is the Social in Social Coherence? Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious Freedom in an Egalitarian Age Journal of Civil Rights and Economic Development Volume 31 Issue 1 Volume 31, Summer 2018, Issue 1 Article 5 June 2018 What is the "Social" in "Social Coherence?" Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious

More information

The Role of Love in the Thought of Kant and Kierkegaard

The Role of Love in the Thought of Kant and Kierkegaard Philosophy of Religion The Role of Love in the Thought of Kant and Kierkegaard Daryl J. Wennemann Fontbonne College dwennema@fontbonne.edu ABSTRACT: Following Ronald Green's suggestion concerning Kierkegaard's

More information

Helpful Hints for doing Philosophy Papers (Spring 2000)

Helpful Hints for doing Philosophy Papers (Spring 2000) Helpful Hints for doing Philosophy Papers (Spring 2000) (1) The standard sort of philosophy paper is what is called an explicative/critical paper. It consists of four parts: (i) an introduction (usually

More information

"Book Review: FRANKFURT, Harry G. On Inequality. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press, 2015, 102 pp., $14.95 (hbk), ISBN

Book Review: FRANKFURT, Harry G. On Inequality. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press, 2015, 102 pp., $14.95 (hbk), ISBN "Book Review: FRANKFURT, Harry G. On Inequality. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press, 2015, 102 pp., $14.95 (hbk), ISBN 9780691167145." 1 Andrea Luisa Bucchile Faggion Universidade Estadual

More information

Promoting. a safer church Safeguarding policy statement for children, young people and adults

Promoting. a safer church Safeguarding policy statement for children, young people and adults Promoting a safer church Safeguarding policy statement for children, young people and adults The Archbishops Council 2017 Published in 2017 for the House of Bishops of the General Synod of the Church of

More information

Spinoza, the No Shared Attribute thesis, and the

Spinoza, the No Shared Attribute thesis, and the Spinoza, the No Shared Attribute thesis, and the Principle of Sufficient Reason * Daniel Whiting This is a pre-print of an article whose final and definitive form is due to be published in the British

More information

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002 1 Symposium on Understanding Truth By Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002 2 Precis of Understanding Truth Scott Soames Understanding Truth aims to illuminate

More information

Deontology, Rationality, and Agent-Centered Restrictions

Deontology, Rationality, and Agent-Centered Restrictions Florida Philosophical Review Volume X, Issue 1, Summer 2010 75 Deontology, Rationality, and Agent-Centered Restrictions Brandon Hogan, University of Pittsburgh I. Introduction Deontological ethical theories

More information

EQUAL EMPLOYMENT OPPORTUNITY GUIDELINES PRESBYTERY OF NORTHERN KANSAS COMMITTEE ON MINISTRY

EQUAL EMPLOYMENT OPPORTUNITY GUIDELINES PRESBYTERY OF NORTHERN KANSAS COMMITTEE ON MINISTRY EQUAL EMPLOYMENT OPPORTUNITY GUIDELINES PRESBYTERY OF NORTHERN KANSAS COMMITTEE ON MINISTRY EEO GUIDELINES FOR COMMITTEE ON MINISTRY The Book of Order (G-11.05021) places responsibility with the Committee

More information

Virtuous act, virtuous dispositions

Virtuous act, virtuous dispositions virtuous act, virtuous dispositions 69 Virtuous act, virtuous dispositions Thomas Hurka Everyday moral thought uses the concepts of virtue and vice at two different levels. At what I will call a global

More information

LESSON 1: ESTABLISHING CLASSROOM RULES, RIGHTS, AND RESPONSIBILITIES

LESSON 1: ESTABLISHING CLASSROOM RULES, RIGHTS, AND RESPONSIBILITIES UNIT I: INTRODUCTION TO RIGHTS AND RESPONSIBILITIES LESSON 1: ESTABLISHING CLASSROOM RULES, RIGHTS, AND RESPONSIBILITIES OBJECTIVES: To establish rules that ensure a safe, respectful classroom environment

More information

STATEMENT OF EXPECTATION FOR GRAND CANYON UNIVERSITY FACULTY

STATEMENT OF EXPECTATION FOR GRAND CANYON UNIVERSITY FACULTY STATEMENT OF EXPECTATION FOR GRAND CANYON UNIVERSITY FACULTY Grand Canyon University takes a missional approach to its operation as a Christian university. In order to ensure a clear understanding of GCU

More information

Philosophical Review.

Philosophical Review. Philosophical Review Review: [untitled] Author(s): John Martin Fischer Source: The Philosophical Review, Vol. 98, No. 2 (Apr., 1989), pp. 254-257 Published by: Duke University Press on behalf of Philosophical

More information

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z.   Notes ETHICS - A - Z Absolutism Act-utilitarianism Agent-centred consideration Agent-neutral considerations : This is the view, with regard to a moral principle or claim, that it holds everywhere and is never

More information

Question : Reform's Position On...Homosexuality

Question : Reform's Position On...Homosexuality Single Page Top Document: soc.culture.jewish FAQ: Reform Judaism (10/12) Previous Document: Question 18.3.7: Reform's Position On...Other Jewish movements? Next Document: Question 18.3.9: Reform's Position

More information

Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1

Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1 Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1 By Bernard Gert (1934-2011) [Page 15] Analogy between Morality and Grammar Common morality is complex, but it is less complex than the grammar of a language. Just

More information

The title of this collection of essays is a question that I expect many professional philosophers have

The title of this collection of essays is a question that I expect many professional philosophers have What is Philosophy? C.P. Ragland and Sarah Heidt, eds. New Haven and London: Yale University Press, 2001, vii + 196pp., $38.00 h.c. 0-300-08755-1, $18.00 pbk. 0-300-08794-2 CHRISTINA HENDRICKS The title

More information