Practical Wisdom & The Unity of Virtue in Nicomachean Ethics VI.12-13

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Practical Wisdom & The Unity of Virtue in Nicomachean Ethics VI.12-13"

Transcription

1 Practical Wisdom & The Unity of Virtue in Nicomachean Ethics VI C.G. Healow December 15, 2015 Abstract In the N icomachean Ethics VI, Aristotle commits himself to the rather strong claim that an agent having practical wisdom is both a sufficient and necessary condition for that agent s having each of the moral virtues. He then uses this claim to argue for the further position that an agent has one of the moral virtues if and only if he has them all. Despite the fact that some scholars have suggested that Aristotle s arguments don t (or even can t) succeed, I intend to argue that once properly understood, the idea that practical wisdom implies, and is implied by, the unity of virtue is a defensible hypothesis which provides a useful goal to all who seek to attain a virtuous character. In section 1 I provide an outline of the theses Aristotle supports and provide a brief sketch of some prima facie reasons why his theses might be doubtfully true. Then, in section 2, I recount the arguments Aristotle gives in support of his controversial theses. Lastly, in section 3 I examine two objections scholars have made against his arguments, while detailing some of the other features of Aristotle s ethical theory which may provide the resources to respond to these objections. 1 Introduction In the chapters 12 and 13 of book VI of the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle seeks to provide responses to some of the likely objections that might be raised against the account of virtue he proposes. These objections range from the question of whether practical wisdom is an essential characteristic of the virtuous agent and whether practical wisdom could itself be useful given that our dispositions are responsible for our actions, to the question of what the relation is between intellectual and practical wisdom. These various concerns are dispatched with varying degrees of detail and effectiveness. But what makes these chapters especially noteworthy is the fact that it is here that Aristotle reveals his commitment to, and arguments in favor of, two remarkable positions. One of these positions is what I ll call the Practical Wisdom 1

2 Thesis (PW). It supposes that practical wisdom (φρον ησις) is intimately related to virtue (ρετ η), such that having practical wisdom is both a sufficient and necessary condition for having any of the moral virtues Aristotle describes in earlier books of the Nicomachean Ethics. Practical Wisdom Thesis (PW): For any agent, a, a has practical wisdom if and only if a possesses moral virtue. Additionally, Aristotle believes that (PW) provides adequate reason to accept what I ll call the Unity of Virtue Thesis (UV), which supposes that anyone who has one moral virtue must have all the others as well. Unity of Virtue Thesis (UV): For any agent, a, arbitraryvirtue,v x and full set of virtues, (where v x ), a has v x if and only if a has. Initially, neither (PW) nor (UV) seem to be very plausible theses. For instance, take (PW); it seems highly suspicious to claim that practical wisdom requires that one be virtuous. After all, aren t there frighteningly many examples of intelligent people who are quite skilled at attaining ends that are of questionable moral value? Similarly, isn t it conceivable that we might find ignorant people who more often than not behave properly, but do so unintentionally? Each of these would seem to be counterexamples to (PW). There also appear to be straightforward counterexamples to (UV). Of course, one aspect of (UV) seems trivially true (e.g. if there are only three virtues say, v 1, v 2, v 3 and a person has all the virtues, obviously she will have each virtue independently). But it seems totally outrageous to claim that one cannot be, say, generous, without also being courageous, proud, temperate, etc. With this in mind, (UV) appears rather dubious at the outset. Still, regardless of their initial implausibility, Aristotle does give arguments in favor of both theses and each of these arguments clearly draws on the account of virtue Aristotle devotes the majority of the N icomachean Ethics to elucidating. It is my belief that analysis of some of Aristotle s other claims in this work go a long way towards vindicating his arguments in support of (PW) and (UV). Clarifying Aristotle s arguments and analyzing their success is the topic of this paper. In section 2, I ll examine Aristotle s arguments in isolation from the rest of the Nicomachean Ethics. Then, in section 3, I ll examine some of the more threatening 2

3 objections that have been leveled against (PW) and (UV) while outlining broader themes in Aristotle s ethical theory that bear on the evaluation of such objections. 2 Aristotle s Arguments for (PW) and (UV) 2.1 Having Practical Wisdom Implies Being Virtuous In order to establish the truth of the biconditional represented by (PW), Aristotle recognized the need to establish both that (i) the presence of practical wisdom implies the presence of virtue, and that (ii) the presence of virtue implies the presence of practical wisdom. He opts to prove (i) first. Practical Wisdom Thesis 1 (PW 1 ): For any agent, a, ifa has practical wisdom, then a possesses virtue. Perhaps unsurprisingly, Aristotle indicates that wisdom itself has a normative connotation, which makes it similar to a virtue. Wisdom is a species of a more general skill called cleverness, (δεινότης) which can be either positive or negative depending on the use to which it is put. His idea appears to be that it is, of course, possible for someone to be effective at securing her ends even if the ends she chooses to pursue are improper in the sense that they are not the ends that a person mindful of goodness would choose. It seems peculiar to say this person is unwise in the sense that she is not able to bring about her ends, but it does seem appropriate to say this person is unwise in the sense that she is choosing ends that run contrary to what is naturally good for her qua human being. Thus, Aristotle offers the distinction between cleverness and wisdom; cleverness is required in order for one to be practically wise, but the only way one can truly be practically wise is for her to have a proper starting point, avaluefromwhichagoalcanbederivedsuchthathereffortscanbeeffectivelyused to secure an appropriate end. But it is still possible to be clever that is, skilled at achieving your ends even if you don t know how to select ends properly. This eye of the soul [cleverness] does not come to be in its proper condition without excellence (ρετ η),... for chains of practical reasoning have astartingpoint... andthisisnotevidentexcepttothepersonwho possesses excellence, since badness distorts a person and causes him to be deceived about the starting points of action. So it is evident that it is 3

4 impossible to be wise (φρον ησις) without possessing excellence (ρετ η). 1 N icomachean Ethics VI a30-b1 So, it looks like Aristotle s argument for (PW 1 )takesthefollowingform: (1) Cleverness is the ability to secure one s ends. (2) This ability is praiseworthy when one s ends are noble, but is blameworthy when they are not. (3) Those who have a praiseworthy cleverness are practically wise, while those who have a blameworthy cleverness are unscrupulous. (4) Virtue (or the lack of it) is what explains a person s being drawn to noble (or base) ends. (5) So if one is not virtuous, one doesn t have practical wisdom, or (6) If one has practical wisdom, then one is virtuous. By arriving at (6), Aristotle has proven (PW 1 ) and derived the first conditional needed in order to establish (PW). 2.2 Being Virtuous Implies Having Practical Wisdom Aristotle has a similar argument to prove the other conditional, (PW 2 ), which is needed to establish (PW): Practical Wisdom Thesis 2 (PW 2 ): For any agent, a, if a possesses virtue, then a has practical wisdom. Indeed the argument for (PW 2 )isforeshadowedinapassagethatappearsbeforethe argument for (PW 1 ). Just as we say that in some cases people do what is just without being just themselves... so, it seems, it is possible to do the various sorts of things from a certain disposition, so as actually to be a good person: I mean e.g. doing them because of decision, and for the sake of the things 1 All Aristotle passages in this paper are from the S. Broadie and C. Rowe translation of Nicomachean Ethics (2002). 4

5 being done themselves. The decision, then, is made correct by excellence (ρετ η), but the doing of whatever by the nature of things has to be done to realize that decision is not the business of excellence but of another ability [i.e. practical wisdom]. N icomachean Ethics VI a14-22 Here Aristotle recognizes the reciprocal relationship between practical wisdom and virtue. At the same time, he also notes that virtue itself will not be identifiable merely by noticing the dispositions people seem to be utilizing when they act. His point seems to be that, you might have two different people with seemingly the same disposition, each of which are inclined to do the right thing. But if one of them is so inclined because the action is right and the other because the action is required by law, Aristotle wishes to claim that only the former is truly virtuous. This constitutes the starting point for his argument supporting (PW 2 ). Just as one needs to distinguish between cleverness and practical wisdom, so too does one need to distinguish in the case of virtues between natural virtues and primary virtues. The latter category will be those which we properly understand to correspond to virtue in the traditional sense and Aristotle wishes to claim primary virtue will only come about with the aid of practical wisdom, as this quote reveals: [S]o with the character-bearing part [of the soul] there are also two, one being natural excellence and the other excellence in the primary sense and of these, the latter does not come about unless accompanied by wisdom. N icomachean Ethics VI b15-8 Natural virtues are those innate dispositions which would determine our actions if we were left without any moral education or social conditioning. The suggestion appears to be that these dispositions may result in our performing actions, and these actions might even occasionally be those which would be performed by the wise and virtuous person. However, no one truly thinks (in Aristotle s estimation) that such a person left to their own devices could be truly virtuous. Or, to put it another way, when we note that a person is virtuous presumably we are not seeking to praise her innate and untempered dispositions. Rather, we seek to reinforce those which she has cultivated over time with the aid of reflection on those actions which are good. Apparently, then, everyone seems somehow to divine the truth that this sort of disposition [the sort in accordance with the correct prescription] is excellence (ρετ η), i.e. the one in accordance with wisdom (φρον ησις). But one must go a little further on than this: it is not just the disposition 5

6 according to the correct prescription, but the disposition accompanied by the correct prescription, that constitutes excellence; and it is wisdom that correctly prescribes in contexts of this sort. N icomachean Ethics 1144b24-9 Consequently, Aristotle is convinced that everyone will endorse the notion that primary virtue requires practical wisdom, as this is tantamount to saying that we should follow whatever the correct prescription (ρθός λόγος) is and following the correct prescription is what we are doing when we are exercising our practical wisdom. That is, primary virtue consists in utilizing our rational capacity to gauge a particular situation and determine what course of action is called for, rather than blindly doing whatever our fallible natural dispositions would compel us to do. Picking up where the argument for (PW 1 ) left off, Aristotle s argument for (PW 2 ) proceeds as follows: (7) There are natural and primary virtues. (8) Natural virtues are the sort with which animals are naturally vested, but which are unwieldy and can often lead to harm. (9) Primary virtues are the sort which arise from practice and don t lead to harm. (10) Being virtuous in the primary sense means following the correct prescription in each case. (11) Following the correct prescription is a matter of exercising practical wisdom. (12) It is not possible to be virtuous (in the primary sense) without having practical wisdom, or (13) If one is virtuous, then one has practically wisdom. Having reached (13), Aristotle has derived (PW 2 ). Thus, he takes himself to have established (PW) conclusively: It is clear, then, from what has been said that it is not possible to possess excellence in the primary sense without wisdom, nor to be wise without excellence of character. N icomachean Ethics 1144b31-3 6

7 2.3 The Unity of Virtue Immediately after completing his argument for (PW), Aristotle moves on to the consideration of (UV). The argument is not as clear as one might hope, but it seems to be something like the following. If we suppose that an individual has a single virtue, but lacks the others, this is an untenable position because, if one accepts (PW 2 ), this implies that the individual has practical wisdom and has the single virtue. But then, contrary to the assumption, having practical wisdom and accepting (PW 1 )impliesthattheindividualhasallthe other virtues. So, given (PW), the agent having a single virtue implies that the agent has the single virtue and all the virtues. Considering the contradiction that results from assuming that an agent can have a single virtue, we re therefore forced to conclude that (UV) follows from (PW). 2 In other words: Take an agent, a, asinglevirtue,v x,thefullsetofvirtues,,(wherev x ), and practical wisdom, P, (14) Suppose that a has v x,and (15) a does not have. (16) From (13) and (14), it follows that a has P. (17) One can t be partially practically wise, for practical wisdom is one. 3 (18) But if a has P,itfollowsfrom(6)and(16)thata has. (19) But then, by assumption, a does and does not have, which is absurd. 2 Up to this point in the argument, its possible to misconceive of the nature of practical wisdom quite easily, such that this move seems unmotivated and far too strong. Indeed, Aristotle never goes into great detail in his discussion of practical wisdom s scope or particular characteristics. However, by making the argument for (UV), Aristotle reveals that his notion of practical wisdom which he has been discussing is a rather robust all or nothing quality that all virtuous people have and which enable them to deliberate and execute their plans effectively. So, for example, when it was noted in (PW 1 ) and (PW 2 ) that practical wisdom and virtue mutually imply one another, he didn t mean to suggest that an agent has whatever particular bit of practical wisdom pertains to decisions one must in order to have one specific virtue. Rather, when Aristotle assumed (or rather, tried to establish by argument) that an agent had practical wisdom, he meant to claim that the agent possessed all the expertise required to make proper decisions with respect to every virtue she might potentially have. With this understanding of practical wisdom in mind, the move from (PW) to (UV) becomes much more explicable (notwithstanding the fact that such an inference might still appear illegitimate for various reasons). 3 Aristotle s commitment to this premise is demonstrated by the following obscure (and perhaps highly questionable) quote: [I]f wisdom, which is one, is present, they [the virtues] will all be present along with it. N icomachean EthicsVI a2-3 7

8 (20) Therefore, if a has v x,thenahas. (21) It s trivially true that if v x andahas that a has v x. (22) Therefore, a has v x if and only if a has. Given the inherent implausibility of this conclusion, many have decided that the arguments which lead to (PW) and (UV) must involve some illicit steps. In the next section I ll consider a few of the stronger objections that I know of which have been raised against Aristotle s arguments for (PW) and (UV). Along the way, I ll try to lend greater clarity to some of the specific details of Aristotle s theory of virtue in an attempt to meet the challenges posed by these objections. 3 Objections & Replies 3.1 Objection 1 Elizabeth Telfer has argued that the (UV) is doomed to failure because of the fact that (PW) cannot be sensibly upheld. 4 Her main line of critique proceeds by noting that one needs to utilize different notions of practical wisdom in the arguments for (PW 1 )and(pw 2 )inorderforboththesestobeplausible. Forinstance,byher reckoning (PW 2 ) appears totally implausible if one supposes that practical wisdom means that one must have complete understanding and expertise as to how a person can accomplish any aims she might have. Indeed, it seems much more reasonable to suppose that the meaning of practical wisdom utilized in (PW 2 )isa capacityto know what actions are required by the virtues in question. 5 On the other hand, if one is examining (PW 1 ), and suggesting that one s having practical wisdom is sufficient for her to have any or all of the virtues, then surely the notion of practical wisdom being considered will have to be robust enough to cover the vast array of considerations a person will need to be sensitive to in order to manifest all of the virtues Aristotle discusses. So, Telfar concludes, given that neither of the conceptions of practical wisdom used to establish (PW 1 ) and (PW 2 )canbe used to establish the other, the result is that neither (PW) nor (UV) are properly supported theses and so both ought to be rejected. 4 Telfer ( ) The Unity of the Moral Virtues in Aristotle s Nicomachean Ethics. 5 Telfer ( ), p

9 3.2 Reply 1 Aside from the fact that Telfer doesn t do much to address the specific arguments Aristotle provides in support of (PW) and (UV), it seems to me that her argument crucially depends on an impoverished notion of virtue. Telfer herself draws attention to Sorabji s reading of Aristotle in which he notes that virtue is a complex disposition. Telfer s arguments suggest that, in actuality, doing the virtuous thing and being a virtuous person could involve an agent having only a single virtue and having the skill set and moral knowledge necessary to only perform virtuous actions which that one virtue requires. However, as Sorabji (and Aristotle himself) make quite clear. Having the knowledge to do the virtuous thing, such that one can be virtuous, is not limited to being sensitive to a small and specific set of concerns, but necessarily involves one s having an understanding of, and attraction to performing actions which promote, goodness. Accordingly, doing actions in ignorance, or even without full knowledge of what all the goods are which must be weighed as one deliberates what action to perform, is anathema to being a virtuous person. John M. Cooper s explanation of the intimate role that practical wisdom plays in virtue is instructive in this regard. So, for them [Plato and Aristotle], though virtue is in no sense one condition no single state of mind and character the complex of conditions that makes it up is a single and unified cluster, formed around and dominated by the single virtue of wisdom (Plato) or practical wisdom (Aristotle)....That there is a knowledge component and, ultimately, this single one in every ethical virtue is established for Aristotle by the reflection that, properly understood, each of these virtues is a refined, intelligent, flexible mode of response, sensitive to every sort of nuance in a situation calling for action, in a way that no simple, non-knowledge-based way of feeling ever could be. 6 [Author s emphasis] In fact, since the virtuous action requires full knowledge of the situation and of what one s actions are, it could be argued that, by definition, the virtuous person will not perform an action blindly which might come at the expense of another good. 7 6 John M. Cooper (1999), pp That one s having the appropriate knowledge is one of the conditions for an agent being a virtuous agent agent is revealed by the following passage: Again, neither do the case of the skills and that of the excellences resemble each other: the things that come about through the agency of skills contain in themselves the mark of their being done well, so that it is enough if they turn out in a certain way, whereas the things that come about in accordance with the excellences count as done justly or 9

10 Since one only has a virtue insofar as she knows the situations in which acting in accordance with that a specific disposition would be called for, it can be argued that if one supposedly has only one virtue and the knowledge only to weigh whether an action is in accordance with that one virtue, then either this person will lack the knowledge necessary to appraise whether or not a situation calls for an action according to that virtue (in which case the agent s vantage point is too parochial and, as a result, the so-called virtue this agent possesses is no virtue at all), or that the knowledge this agent has is extensive enough to determine whether such a virtuous action of that kind is called for, in which case the agent must have practical wisdom. 3.3 Objection 2 Another incisive and potentially devastating objection to Aristotle s arguments for (PW) and (UV) is raised by Richard Kraut. 8 In the same paper in which he argues that there need not be inconsistency among the moral virtues Aristotle discusses in the Nicomachean Ethics, Kraut expresses skepticism about (UV). His worry is expressed in the following way: This [(UV)] strikes me as a thesis that is badly in need of support.... Even if we grant him the premiss that understanding one good requires understanding them all, we would still need to be persuaded that if one has successfully integrated certain emotions with one s reasoned conception of the good, then one has been equally successful with all of one s emotions. We can see how Aristotle arrives at the conclusion that one cannot be virtuous in one area and yet have a vice in a different area.... Perhaps this thesis (no one has both virtues and vices) is the core that lies behind [(UV)], and [(UV)] itself is a hasty generalization based on this core. 9 Kraut s objection is at once straightforward and powerful. His idea appears to be something like this. Suppose we take it for granted that there is a cognitive component to each of the virtues (which there certainly is). Suppose also that Aristotle is correct that one cannot have virtues and vices simultaneously, as this would seem to imply an moderately not merely because they themselves are of a certain kind, but also because of facts about the agent doing them first, if he does them knowingly, secondly if he decides to do them, and decides to do them for themselves, and thirdly if he does them from a firm and unchanging disposition. N icomachean Ethics II a27-b1 8 Richard Kraut (1988) Comments on Disunity in the Aristotelian Virtues, by T.H. Irwin. 9 Richard Kraut (1988), p

11 irrationality which is inconsistent with practical wisdom. Even in this case it seems justified to doubt whether the presence of full practical wisdom and a few virtues implies that all the other virtues must be present as well. If we ve stipulated that the agent has some virtues and doesn t perform any actions contrary to virtue, there s no reason to object that this agent isn t behaving in a virtue way, especially if she s reasoning properly with her practical wisdom, she s performing all the actions she should with respect to the virtues she has, and her virtuous actions don t run contrary to the virtues she lacks. If we recognize this possibility, however, it seems we have reason to suppose that an agent might have practical wisdom and individual virtues without having all of the moral virtues fully integrated into her conative attitudes that constitute her motivational set. But this is tantamount to the repudiation of (UV). So, on Kraut s appraisal, although Aristotle was correct to incorporate practical wisdom into his account of virtue and to give it a prominent explanatory role, the fact that one can have practical wisdom without all the virtues undermines (PW 1 ) and (UV) because virtues require people to have conative attitudes which practical wisdom is not sufficient to guarantee. 3.4 Reply 2 To a significant extent, I m inclined to agree with Kraut that there is cause for concern regarding this portion of Aristotle s theory. Even if we suppose that one s practical wisdom is functioning properly and is fully developed, and that one has the dispositional attachment to the property of certain actions being good, it does seem as though there is room to question whether the presence of practical wisdom is enough to guarantee that the particular individual in question has incorporated all the relevant dispositions into her motivational set to such an extent that she will have all the moral virtues. This is a salient observation, and it certainly does deserve further attention and consideration. By way of response, however, one might note that a large portion of this concern relates to the manner in which we conceive of the virtuous agents moral education. That is, Kraut s challenges question how is it that a person develops her favorable dispositions towards good actions such that she will be inclined to pursue other good actions. As a further step, it seems we need to ask whether practical wisdom conceived as the faculty which enables an agent to attain her ends rather than the one that determines them can have a role to play in filling out the dispositions and forming the individual virtues an agent has yet to establish? These are, of course, difficult and 11

12 highly relevant questions. For the time being, I will simply begin to sketch an answer to them in the hope that they might go some distance towards lessening the force of the objection that Kraut raises. To begin with, it s vital to note that Aristotle thinks virtuous actions are those that are done for themselves, as they are inherently good. This is revealed both by passages which note that these actions are chosen for their own sakes (N icomachean Ethics II a27-b1, IV a23-4) and by passages which reveal that there is a certain kind of noble pleasure that arises from performing virtuous actions (N icomachean Ethics I a But, as Myles Burnyeat argues in his highly insightful piece which examines Aristotle s views on moral education, there appears to be good reason to suppose that doing the virtuous thing and developing the dispositions that will ultimately constitute our moral characters is a gradual process. He thinks that this process of habituation is not only effective because it results in people behaving properly externally, but that it also results in people having access to the noble pleasures mentioned above and the property of goodness that brings it about. For, as Aristotle himself notes on numerous occasions, the virtuous person will take pleasure from doing the right thing, but this pleasure will not be what explains why she chooses to do what she does. On this view, therefore, there is a aspect of practical wisdom that is itself only gained by way of habituation people can only do the proper actions as they come to understand the property of goodness that their actions promote. Correlatively, as one continues to bolster her understanding of this property, the more effectively the agent will be able to observe greater varieties of diverse situations in which virtuous actions could be done. [I]f learning to do and to take (proper) enjoyment in doing just actions is learning to do and to enjoy them for their own sake, for what they are, namely, just, and this is not to be distinguished from learning that they are enjoyable for themselves and their intrinsic value, namely, their justice and nobility, then perhaps we can give intelligible sense to the thesis that practice leads to knowledge, as follows. I may be told, and may believe, that such and such actions are just and noble, but I have not really learned for myself (taken to heart, made second nature to me) that they have this intrinsic value until I have learned to value (love) them for it, with the consequence that I take pleasure in doing them. 10 Perhaps these insights can have the effect of making Kraut s objection seems much 10 Myles Burnyeat (1980) Aristotle on Learning to Be Good. 12

13 weaker than it initially appeared. Since his objection presupposed the existence of a significant gap between an action s being correct according to practical wisdom and its being appropriately tied to the conative attitudes that inspire action, and if we ve shown that no such significant gap exists in Aristotle s conception, then it would seem Kraut s argument is somewhat mollified. The conative attitudes most salient to the virtuous person with practical wisdom are those that are associated with virtuous action, and so there is little reason to suspect that a person with practical wisdom will fail to incorporate the insights this attribute reveals into her motivational set. However, even if this response is correct and Kraut s argument is somewhat undermined, there is still a real problem here, as it s not entirely clear at what point in a person s moral development we should say that she has become virtuous. That is, one of the ways in which one might understand this response to Kraut is by taking it to be saying that, in fact, the person he describes is at a stage of moral development where she is not entirely virtuous nor is she (contrary to Kraut s assumption) practically wise. But, it might be said, this is simply to suggest that the standards one must reach in order to be a truly virtuous person are so lofty as to be almost entirely unattainable. Again, I think there is something to this insight, as, without further direction from Aristotle, it seems we must say either that being a virtuous person is goal unattainable for the vast majority of people (maybe everyone), or that Aristotle was mistaken to believe in (PW) and (UV) since, if virtue and practical wisdom are commonplace, there is no reason to suppose that one need imply the other. In my mind, the former option is clearly the more desirable of the two, since it preserves (PW) and (UV), but it does seem to come at a high cost J.L. Ackrill (1981) seems to appreciate this dilemma when he writes the following passage: This idea of the unity of virtue is at first sight very strange. In real life people have some virtues and not others. However, this is because in real life we are not dealing with perfect examples of any virtue.... If, for theoretical purposes, we are to explain what would be involved in the perfect possession of any one virtue, we find that we cannot allow defects anywhere in the character: all desires and feelings and tendencies must have been brought (by training) into a proper balance. For otherwise a defect in one area would always be liable to interfere with the proper operation of a virtue elsewhere.... Thus at the level of theoretical analysis, if one is talking about ideal moral virtues, the thesis that they necessarily go together can be defended. And at the practical level it does have something important to teach us. It is a reminder of the tragic fact that a person with many excellent qualities can do terrible things and cause immense suffering because of a fatal flaw somewhere else in his character. So one should aim at achieving a certain balance and harmony among one s various desires and feelings, and not let any of them become much too strong or much too weak, lest this should have disastrous consequences for one s whole life. [Author s emphasis] (pp.137-8) 13

14 References Ackrill, J.L. (1981) Aristotle the Philosopher (New York: Oxford University Press). Aristotle (2002) Nicomachean Ethics, translated by Broadie, S. & Rowe, C. (New York: Oxford University Press). Badhwar, N.K. (1996) The Limited Unity of Virtue, Noûs, Vol. 30, No. 3, pp Burnyeat, M. (1980) Aristotle on Learning to Be Good, in Rorty, A.O. (ed.) Essays on Aristotle s Ethics (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1980), pp Cooper, J.M. (1999) The Unity of Virtue, in Reason and Emotion (Princeton: Princeton University Press), pp Irwin, T. (1988) Disunity in the Aristotelian Virtues, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, SupplementaryVol.,pp (1988) Disunity in the Aristotelian Virtues: A Reply to Richard Kraut, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, SupplementaryVol.,pp (1980) The Metaphysical and Psychological Basis of Aristotle s Ethics, in Rorty, A.O. (ed.) Essays on Aristotle s Ethics (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1980), pp Kraut, R. (1988) Comments on Disunity in the Aristotelean Virtues, by T.H. Irwin, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, SupplementaryVol.,pp Sorabji, Richard (1980) Aristotle on the Role of Intellect in Virtue, in Rorty, A.O. (ed.) Essays on Aristotle s Ethics (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1980), pp Telfer, Elizabeth ( ) The Unity of the Moral Virtues in Aristotle s N icomachean Ethics, Proceedings of the Aristotelean Society, Vol.90,pp

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren Abstracta SPECIAL ISSUE VI, pp. 33 46, 2012 KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST Arnon Keren Epistemologists of testimony widely agree on the fact that our reliance on other people's testimony is extensive. However,

More information

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS By MARANATHA JOY HAYES A THESIS PRESENTED TO THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF THE UNIVERSITY OF FLORIDA IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS

More information

REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET. Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary

REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET. Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary 1 REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary Abstract: Christine Korsgaard argues that a practical reason (that is, a reason that counts in favor of an action) must motivate

More information

Practical Wisdom and Politics

Practical Wisdom and Politics Practical Wisdom and Politics In discussing Book I in subunit 1.6, you learned that the Ethics specifically addresses the close relationship between ethical inquiry and politics. At the outset, Aristotle

More information

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords ISBN 9780198802693 Title The Value of Rationality Author(s) Ralph Wedgwood Book abstract Book keywords Rationality is a central concept for epistemology,

More information

Phil Aristotle. Instructor: Jason Sheley

Phil Aristotle. Instructor: Jason Sheley Phil 290 - Aristotle Instructor: Jason Sheley To sum up the method 1) Human beings are naturally curious. 2) We need a place to begin our inquiry. 3) The best place to start is with commonly held beliefs.

More information

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

PHI 1700: Global Ethics PHI 1700: Global Ethics Session 8 March 1 st, 2016 Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics 1 Ø Today we begin Unit 2 of the course, focused on Normative Ethics = the practical development of standards for right

More information

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981). Draft of 3-21- 13 PHIL 202: Core Ethics; Winter 2013 Core Sequence in the History of Ethics, 2011-2013 IV: 19 th and 20 th Century Moral Philosophy David O. Brink Handout #14: Williams, Internalism, and

More information

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory Western University Scholarship@Western 2015 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2015 Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory David Hakim Western University, davidhakim266@gmail.com

More information

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Ralph Wedgwood 1 Two views of practical reason Suppose that you are faced with several different options (that is, several ways in which you might act in a

More information

Philosophy Conference University of Patras, Philosophy Department 4-5 June, 2015

Philosophy Conference University of Patras, Philosophy Department 4-5 June, 2015 Philosophy Conference University of Patras, Philosophy Department 4-5 June, 2015 Ethical and Political Intentionality; The Individual and the Collective from Plato to Hobbes and onwards Abstracts Hans

More information

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006 In Defense of Radical Empiricism Joseph Benjamin Riegel A thesis submitted to the faculty of the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of

More information

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements ANALYSIS 59.3 JULY 1999 Moral requirements are still not rational requirements Paul Noordhof According to Michael Smith, the Rationalist makes the following conceptual claim. If it is right for agents

More information

WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY

WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY Miłosz Pawłowski WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY In Eutyphro Plato presents a dilemma 1. Is it that acts are good because God wants them to be performed 2? Or are they

More information

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Author: Terence Rajivan Edward, University of Manchester. Abstract. In the sixth chapter of The View from Nowhere, Thomas Nagel attempts to identify a form of idealism.

More information

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between Lee Anne Detzel PHI 8338 Revised: November 1, 2004 The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between philosophy

More information

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Olav Gjelsvik, University of Oslo The thesis. Among people writing about rationality, few people are more rational than Wlodek Rabinowicz. But are there reasons for being

More information

Fourth Meditation: Truth and falsity

Fourth Meditation: Truth and falsity Fourth Meditation: Truth and falsity In these past few days I have become used to keeping my mind away from the senses; and I have become strongly aware that very little is truly known about bodies, whereas

More information

Aristotle s Virtue Ethics

Aristotle s Virtue Ethics Aristotle s Virtue Ethics Aristotle, Virtue Ethics Every art and every inquiry, and similarly every action and pursuit, is thought to aim at some good; and for this reason the good has rightly been declared

More information

Nichomachean Ethics. Philosophy 21 Fall, 2004 G. J. Mattey

Nichomachean Ethics. Philosophy 21 Fall, 2004 G. J. Mattey Nichomachean Ethics Philosophy 21 Fall, 2004 G. J. Mattey The Highest Good The good is that at which everything aims Crafts, investigations, actions, decisions If one science is subordinate to another,

More information

Comments on Nicholas Gier s Aristotle, Confucius, and Practical Reason

Comments on Nicholas Gier s Aristotle, Confucius, and Practical Reason Comments on Nicholas Gier s Aristotle, Confucius, and Practical Reason I know quite a bit about Aristotle s ethics, but only a little about Confucianism; I have read and taught enough of the latter to

More information

Scanlon on Double Effect

Scanlon on Double Effect Scanlon on Double Effect RALPH WEDGWOOD Merton College, University of Oxford In this new book Moral Dimensions, T. M. Scanlon (2008) explores the ethical significance of the intentions and motives with

More information

Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is

Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is The Flicker of Freedom: A Reply to Stump Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is scheduled to appear in an upcoming issue The Journal of Ethics. That

More information

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst [Forthcoming in Analysis. Penultimate Draft. Cite published version.] Kantian Humility holds that agents like

More information

Aristotle s Doctrine of the Mean and the Circularity of Human Nature

Aristotle s Doctrine of the Mean and the Circularity of Human Nature KRITIKE VOLUME TEN NUMBER TWO (DECEMBER 2016) 122-131 ARTICLE Thoughts on Classical Philosophy Aristotle s Doctrine of the Mean and the Circularity of Human Nature Nahum Brown Abstract: Aristotle's famous

More information

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism Mathais Sarrazin J.L. Mackie s Error Theory postulates that all normative claims are false. It does this based upon his denial of moral

More information

The stated objective of Gloria Origgi s paper Epistemic Injustice and Epistemic Trust is:

The stated objective of Gloria Origgi s paper Epistemic Injustice and Epistemic Trust is: Trust and the Assessment of Credibility Paul Faulkner, University of Sheffield Faulkner, Paul. 2012. Trust and the Assessment of Credibility. Epistemic failings can be ethical failings. This insight is

More information

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality. On Modal Personism Shelly Kagan s essay on speciesism has the virtues characteristic of his work in general: insight, originality, clarity, cleverness, wit, intuitive plausibility, argumentative rigor,

More information

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY DISCUSSION NOTE BY JONATHAN WAY JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE DECEMBER 2009 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT JONATHAN WAY 2009 Two Accounts of the Normativity of Rationality RATIONALITY

More information

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen Stance Volume 6 2013 29 Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen Abstract: In this paper, I will examine an argument for fatalism. I will offer a formalized version of the argument and analyze one of the

More information

A Coherent and Comprehensible Interpretation of Saul Smilansky s Dualism

A Coherent and Comprehensible Interpretation of Saul Smilansky s Dualism A Coherent and Comprehensible Interpretation of Saul Smilansky s Dualism Abstract Saul Smilansky s theory of free will and moral responsibility consists of two parts; dualism and illusionism. Dualism is

More information

What Part of the Soul Does Justice Perfect? Shane Drefcinski Department of Humanities/Philosophy University of Wisconsin Platteville

What Part of the Soul Does Justice Perfect? Shane Drefcinski Department of Humanities/Philosophy University of Wisconsin Platteville What Part of the Soul Does Justice Perfect? Shane Drefcinski Department of Humanities/Philosophy University of Wisconsin Platteville Interpreters of Aristotle generally agree that each of the particular

More information

Virtue Ethics. A Basic Introductory Essay, by Dr. Garrett. Latest minor modification November 28, 2005

Virtue Ethics. A Basic Introductory Essay, by Dr. Garrett. Latest minor modification November 28, 2005 Virtue Ethics A Basic Introductory Essay, by Dr. Garrett Latest minor modification November 28, 2005 Some students would prefer not to study my introductions to philosophical issues and approaches but

More information

The Future of Practical Philosophy: a Reply to Taylor

The Future of Practical Philosophy: a Reply to Taylor The Future of Practical Philosophy: a Reply to Taylor Samuel Zinaich, Jr. ABSTRACT: This response to Taylor s paper, The Future of Applied Philosophy (also included in this issue) describes Taylor s understanding

More information

- 1 - Outline of NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, Book I Book I--Dialectical discussion leading to Aristotle's definition of happiness: activity in accordance

- 1 - Outline of NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, Book I Book I--Dialectical discussion leading to Aristotle's definition of happiness: activity in accordance - 1 - Outline of NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, Book I Book I--Dialectical discussion leading to Aristotle's definition of happiness: activity in accordance with virtue or excellence (arete) in a complete life Chapter

More information

Buck-Passers Negative Thesis

Buck-Passers Negative Thesis Mark Schroeder November 27, 2006 University of Southern California Buck-Passers Negative Thesis [B]eing valuable is not a property that provides us with reasons. Rather, to call something valuable is to

More information

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become Aporia vol. 24 no. 1 2014 Incoherence in Epistemic Relativism I. Introduction In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become increasingly popular across various academic disciplines.

More information

Wisdom in Aristotle and Aquinas From Metaphysics to Mysticism Edmond Eh University of Saint Joseph, Macau

Wisdom in Aristotle and Aquinas From Metaphysics to Mysticism Edmond Eh University of Saint Joseph, Macau Volume 12, No 2, Fall 2017 ISSN 1932-1066 Wisdom in Aristotle and Aquinas From Metaphysics to Mysticism Edmond Eh University of Saint Joseph, Macau edmond_eh@usj.edu.mo Abstract: This essay contains an

More information

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran Abstract In his (2015) paper, Robert Lockie seeks to add a contextualized, relativist

More information

Virtuous act, virtuous dispositions

Virtuous act, virtuous dispositions virtuous act, virtuous dispositions 69 Virtuous act, virtuous dispositions Thomas Hurka Everyday moral thought uses the concepts of virtue and vice at two different levels. At what I will call a global

More information

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE Practical Politics and Philosophical Inquiry: A Note Author(s): Dale Hall and Tariq Modood Reviewed work(s): Source: The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 29, No. 117 (Oct., 1979), pp. 340-344 Published by:

More information

Aristotle s Ethics Philosophy 207z Fall 2013

Aristotle s Ethics Philosophy 207z Fall 2013 Aristotle s Ethics Philosophy 207z Fall 2013 Chris Korsgaard 205 Emerson Hall 495-3916 christine_korsgaard@harvard.edu Office Hours: Thursdays, 2:00-4:00, and by appointment I. Required Texts Aristotle.

More information

Deontology, Rationality, and Agent-Centered Restrictions

Deontology, Rationality, and Agent-Centered Restrictions Florida Philosophical Review Volume X, Issue 1, Summer 2010 75 Deontology, Rationality, and Agent-Centered Restrictions Brandon Hogan, University of Pittsburgh I. Introduction Deontological ethical theories

More information

The unity of the normative

The unity of the normative The unity of the normative The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Scanlon, T. M. 2011. The Unity of the Normative.

More information

New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon

New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon Powers, Essentialism and Agency: A Reply to Alexander Bird Ruth Porter Groff, Saint Louis University AUB Conference, April 28-29, 2016 1. Here s the backstory. A couple of years ago my friend Alexander

More information

Warren. Warren s Strategy. Inherent Value. Strong Animal Rights. Strategy is to argue that Regan s strong animals rights position is not persuasive

Warren. Warren s Strategy. Inherent Value. Strong Animal Rights. Strategy is to argue that Regan s strong animals rights position is not persuasive Warren Warren s Strategy A Critique of Regan s Animal Rights Theory Strategy is to argue that Regan s strong animals rights position is not persuasive She argues that one ought to accept a weak animal

More information

Philosophical Review.

Philosophical Review. Philosophical Review Review: [untitled] Author(s): John Martin Fischer Source: The Philosophical Review, Vol. 98, No. 2 (Apr., 1989), pp. 254-257 Published by: Duke University Press on behalf of Philosophical

More information

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1 310 Book Review Book Review ISSN (Print) 1225-4924, ISSN (Online) 2508-3104 Catholic Theology and Thought, Vol. 79, July 2017 http://dx.doi.org/10.21731/ctat.2017.79.310 A Review on What Is This Thing

More information

Logical Mistakes, Logical Aliens, and the Laws of Kant's Pure General Logic Chicago February 21 st 2018 Tyke Nunez

Logical Mistakes, Logical Aliens, and the Laws of Kant's Pure General Logic Chicago February 21 st 2018 Tyke Nunez Logical Mistakes, Logical Aliens, and the Laws of Kant's Pure General Logic Chicago February 21 st 2018 Tyke Nunez 1 Introduction (1) Normativists: logic's laws are unconditional norms for how we ought

More information

Reasons With Rationalism After All MICHAEL SMITH

Reasons With Rationalism After All MICHAEL SMITH book symposium 521 Bratman, M.E. Forthcoming a. Intention, belief, practical, theoretical. In Spheres of Reason: New Essays on the Philosophy of Normativity, ed. Simon Robertson. Oxford: Oxford University

More information

Responsibility and Normative Moral Theories

Responsibility and Normative Moral Theories Jada Twedt Strabbing Penultimate Version forthcoming in The Philosophical Quarterly Published online: https://doi.org/10.1093/pq/pqx054 Responsibility and Normative Moral Theories Stephen Darwall and R.

More information

Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination

Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination MP_C13.qxd 11/23/06 2:29 AM Page 110 13 Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination [Article IV. Concerning Henry s Conclusion] In the fourth article I argue against the conclusion of [Henry s] view as follows:

More information

Reading the Nichomachean Ethics

Reading the Nichomachean Ethics 1 Reading the Nichomachean Ethics Book I: Chapter 1: Good as the aim of action Every art, applied science, systematic investigation, action and choice aims at some good: either an activity, or a product

More information

Hume s Law Violated? Rik Peels. The Journal of Value Inquiry ISSN J Value Inquiry DOI /s

Hume s Law Violated? Rik Peels. The Journal of Value Inquiry ISSN J Value Inquiry DOI /s Rik Peels The Journal of Value Inquiry ISSN 0022-5363 J Value Inquiry DOI 10.1007/s10790-014-9439-8 1 23 Your article is protected by copyright and all rights are held exclusively by Springer Science +Business

More information

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction 24 Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Abstract: In this paper, I address Linda Zagzebski s analysis of the relation between moral testimony and understanding arguing that Aquinas

More information

A CONTRACTUALIST READING OF KANT S PROOF OF THE FORMULA OF HUMANITY. Adam Cureton

A CONTRACTUALIST READING OF KANT S PROOF OF THE FORMULA OF HUMANITY. Adam Cureton A CONTRACTUALIST READING OF KANT S PROOF OF THE FORMULA OF HUMANITY Adam Cureton Abstract: Kant offers the following argument for the Formula of Humanity: Each rational agent necessarily conceives of her

More information

Other Recommended Books (on reserve at library):

Other Recommended Books (on reserve at library): Ethics, Fall 2015 TTH 11:30-12:50, GRHM 2302 Instructor: John, Ph.D. Office: Mackinnon 330 Office Hrs: TTH 1:00-2:00 and by appointment Phone Ext.: 56765 Email: jhackerw@uoguelph.ca OVERVIEW This course

More information

Skepticism and Internalism

Skepticism and Internalism Skepticism and Internalism John Greco Abstract: This paper explores a familiar skeptical problematic and considers some strategies for responding to it. Section 1 reconstructs and disambiguates the skeptical

More information

Aquinas on Spiritual Change. In "Is an Aristotelian Philosophy of Mind Still Credible? (A draft)," Myles

Aquinas on Spiritual Change. In Is an Aristotelian Philosophy of Mind Still Credible? (A draft), Myles Aquinas on Spiritual Change In "Is an Aristotelian Philosophy of Mind Still Credible? (A draft)," Myles Burnyeat challenged the functionalist interpretation of Aristotle by defending Aquinas's understanding

More information

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument 1. The Scope of Skepticism Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument The scope of skeptical challenges can vary in a number

More information

CONSCIOUSNESS, INTENTIONALITY AND CONCEPTS: REPLY TO NELKIN

CONSCIOUSNESS, INTENTIONALITY AND CONCEPTS: REPLY TO NELKIN ----------------------------------------------------------------- PSYCHE: AN INTERDISCIPLINARY JOURNAL OF RESEARCH ON CONSCIOUSNESS ----------------------------------------------------------------- CONSCIOUSNESS,

More information

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible? Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible? Anders Kraal ABSTRACT: Since the 1960s an increasing number of philosophers have endorsed the thesis that there can be no such thing as

More information

J.f. Stephen s On Fraternity And Mill s Universal Love 1

J.f. Stephen s On Fraternity And Mill s Universal Love 1 Τέλος Revista Iberoamericana de Estudios Utilitaristas-2012, XIX/1: (77-82) ISSN 1132-0877 J.f. Stephen s On Fraternity And Mill s Universal Love 1 José Montoya University of Valencia In chapter 3 of Utilitarianism,

More information

7AAN2027 Greek Philosophy II: Aristotle Syllabus Academic year 2012/3

7AAN2027 Greek Philosophy II: Aristotle Syllabus Academic year 2012/3 School of Arts & Humanities Department of Philosophy 7AAN2027 Greek Philosophy II: Aristotle Syllabus Academic year 2012/3 Basic information Credits: 20 Module Tutor: Dr. Raphael Woolf Office: 712 Consultation

More information

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have served as the point of departure for much of the most interesting work that

More information

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible ) Philosophical Proof of God: Derived from Principles in Bernard Lonergan s Insight May 2014 Robert J. Spitzer, S.J., Ph.D. Magis Center of Reason and Faith Lonergan s proof may be stated as follows: Introduction

More information

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE Diametros nr 29 (wrzesień 2011): 80-92 THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE Karol Polcyn 1. PRELIMINARIES Chalmers articulates his argument in terms of two-dimensional

More information

From: Michael Huemer, Ethical Intuitionism (2005)

From: Michael Huemer, Ethical Intuitionism (2005) From: Michael Huemer, Ethical Intuitionism (2005) 214 L rsmkv!rs ks syxssm! finds Sally funny, but later decides he was mistaken about her funniness when the audience merely groans.) It seems, then, that

More information

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW DISCUSSION NOTE BY CAMPBELL BROWN JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE MAY 2015 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT CAMPBELL BROWN 2015 Two Versions of Hume s Law MORAL CONCLUSIONS CANNOT VALIDLY

More information

7AAN2027 Greek Philosophy II: Aristotle Syllabus Academic year 2013/4

7AAN2027 Greek Philosophy II: Aristotle Syllabus Academic year 2013/4 School of Arts & Humanities Department of Philosophy 7AAN2027 Greek Philosophy II: Aristotle Syllabus Academic year 2013/4 Basic information Credits: 20 Module Tutor: Dr. Raphael Woolf, raphael.g.woolf@kcl.ac.uk

More information

Harman s Moral Relativism

Harman s Moral Relativism Harman s Moral Relativism Jordan Wolf March 17, 2010 Word Count: 2179 (including body, footnotes, and title) 1 1 Introduction In What is Moral Relativism? and Moral Relativism Defended, 1 Gilbert Harman,

More information

The Need for Metanormativity: A Response to Christmas

The Need for Metanormativity: A Response to Christmas The Need for Metanormativity: A Response to Christmas Douglas J. Den Uyl Liberty Fund, Inc. Douglas B. Rasmussen St. John s University We would like to begin by thanking Billy Christmas for his excellent

More information

Does the Third Man Argument refute the theory of forms?

Does the Third Man Argument refute the theory of forms? Does the Third Man Argument refute the theory of forms? Fine [1993] recognises four versions of the Third Man Argument (TMA). However, she argues persuasively that these are similar arguments with similar

More information

HOW TO BE (AND HOW NOT TO BE) A NORMATIVE REALIST:

HOW TO BE (AND HOW NOT TO BE) A NORMATIVE REALIST: 1 HOW TO BE (AND HOW NOT TO BE) A NORMATIVE REALIST: A DISSERTATION OVERVIEW THAT ASSUMES AS LITTLE AS POSSIBLE ABOUT MY READER S PHILOSOPHICAL BACKGROUND Consider the question, What am I going to have

More information

The view that all of our actions are done in self-interest is called psychological egoism.

The view that all of our actions are done in self-interest is called psychological egoism. Egoism For the last two classes, we have been discussing the question of whether any actions are really objectively right or wrong, independently of the standards of any person or group, and whether any

More information

AN ACTUAL-SEQUENCE THEORY OF PROMOTION

AN ACTUAL-SEQUENCE THEORY OF PROMOTION BY D. JUSTIN COATES JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE JANUARY 2014 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT D. JUSTIN COATES 2014 An Actual-Sequence Theory of Promotion ACCORDING TO HUMEAN THEORIES,

More information

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999):

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999): Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999): 47 54. Abstract: John Etchemendy (1990) has argued that Tarski's definition of logical

More information

Selections of the Nicomachean Ethics for GGL Unit: Learning to Live Well Taken from classic.mit.edu archive. Translated by W.D. Ross I.

Selections of the Nicomachean Ethics for GGL Unit: Learning to Live Well Taken from classic.mit.edu archive. Translated by W.D. Ross I. Selections of the Nicomachean Ethics for GGL Unit: Learning to Live Well Taken from classic.mit.edu archive. Translated by W.D. Ross I.7 Let us again return to the good we are seeking, and ask what it

More information

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Chapter 98 Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Lars Leeten Universität Hildesheim Practical thinking is a tricky business. Its aim will never be fulfilled unless influence on practical

More information

Adapted from The Academic Essay: A Brief Anatomy, for the Writing Center at Harvard University by Gordon Harvey. Counter-Argument

Adapted from The Academic Essay: A Brief Anatomy, for the Writing Center at Harvard University by Gordon Harvey. Counter-Argument Adapted from The Academic Essay: A Brief Anatomy, for the Writing Center at Harvard University by Gordon Harvey Counter-Argument When you write an academic essay, you make an argument: you propose a thesis

More information

Citation for the original published paper (version of record):

Citation for the original published paper (version of record): http://www.diva-portal.org Postprint This is the accepted version of a paper published in Utilitas. This paper has been peerreviewed but does not include the final publisher proof-corrections or journal

More information

Henry of Ghent on Divine Illumination

Henry of Ghent on Divine Illumination MP_C12.qxd 11/23/06 2:29 AM Page 103 12 Henry of Ghent on Divine Illumination [II.] Reply [A. Knowledge in a broad sense] Consider all the objects of cognition, standing in an ordered relation to each

More information

EXTERNALISM AND THE CONTENT OF MORAL MOTIVATION

EXTERNALISM AND THE CONTENT OF MORAL MOTIVATION EXTERNALISM AND THE CONTENT OF MORAL MOTIVATION Caj Strandberg Department of Philosophy, Lund University and Gothenburg University Caj.Strandberg@fil.lu.se ABSTRACT: Michael Smith raises in his fetishist

More information

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013 Reply to Kit Fine Theodore Sider July 19, 2013 Kit Fine s paper raises important and difficult issues about my approach to the metaphysics of fundamentality. In chapters 7 and 8 I examined certain subtle

More information

TWO APPROACHES TO INSTRUMENTAL RATIONALITY

TWO APPROACHES TO INSTRUMENTAL RATIONALITY TWO APPROACHES TO INSTRUMENTAL RATIONALITY AND BELIEF CONSISTENCY BY JOHN BRUNERO JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY VOL. 1, NO. 1 APRIL 2005 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT JOHN BRUNERO 2005 I N SPEAKING

More information

7AAN2027 Greek Philosophy II: Aristotle Syllabus Academic year 2015/16

7AAN2027 Greek Philosophy II: Aristotle Syllabus Academic year 2015/16 School of Arts & Humanities Department of Philosophy 7AAN2027 Greek Philosophy II: Aristotle Syllabus Academic year 2015/16 Basic information Credits: 20 Module Tutor: Dr Joachim Aufderheide Office: Room

More information

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10. Introduction This book seeks to provide a metaethical analysis of the responsibility ethics of two of its prominent defenders: H. Richard Niebuhr and Emmanuel Levinas. In any ethical writings, some use

More information

SCHAFFER S DEMON NATHAN BALLANTYNE AND IAN EVANS

SCHAFFER S DEMON NATHAN BALLANTYNE AND IAN EVANS SCHAFFER S DEMON by NATHAN BALLANTYNE AND IAN EVANS Abstract: Jonathan Schaffer (2010) has summoned a new sort of demon which he calls the debasing demon that apparently threatens all of our purported

More information

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law Marianne Vahl Master Thesis in Philosophy Supervisor Olav Gjelsvik Department of Philosophy, Classics, History of Arts and Ideas UNIVERSITY OF OSLO May

More information

On happiness in Locke s decision-ma Title being )

On happiness in Locke s decision-ma Title being ) On happiness in Locke s decision-ma Title (Proceedings of the CAPE Internatio I: The CAPE International Conferenc being ) Author(s) Sasaki, Taku Citation CAPE Studies in Applied Philosophy 2: 141-151 Issue

More information

THINKING ANIMALS AND EPISTEMOLOGY

THINKING ANIMALS AND EPISTEMOLOGY THINKING ANIMALS AND EPISTEMOLOGY by ANTHONY BRUECKNER AND CHRISTOPHER T. BUFORD Abstract: We consider one of Eric Olson s chief arguments for animalism about personal identity: the view that we are each

More information

THE NATURE OF NORMATIVITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC REBECCA V. MILLSOP S

THE NATURE OF NORMATIVITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC REBECCA V. MILLSOP S THE NATURE OF NORMATIVITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC REBECCA V. MILLSOP S I. INTRODUCTION Immanuel Kant claims that logic is constitutive of thought: without [the laws of logic] we would not think at

More information

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS SECOND SECTION by Immanuel Kant TRANSITION FROM POPULAR MORAL PHILOSOPHY TO THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS... This principle, that humanity and generally every

More information

Truth and Molinism * Trenton Merricks. Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, 2011.

Truth and Molinism * Trenton Merricks. Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, 2011. Truth and Molinism * Trenton Merricks Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, 2011. According to Luis de Molina, God knows what each and every possible human would

More information

Korsgaard and Non-Sentient Life ABSTRACT

Korsgaard and Non-Sentient Life ABSTRACT 74 Between the Species Korsgaard and Non-Sentient Life ABSTRACT Christine Korsgaard argues for the moral status of animals and our obligations to them. She grounds this obligation on the notion that we

More information

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1 Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford 0. Introduction It is often claimed that beliefs aim at the truth. Indeed, this claim has

More information

Virtue Ethics without Character Traits

Virtue Ethics without Character Traits Virtue Ethics without Character Traits Gilbert Harman Princeton University August 18, 1999 Presumed parts of normative moral philosophy Normative moral philosophy is often thought to be concerned with

More information

A Contractualist Reply

A Contractualist Reply A Contractualist Reply The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Scanlon, T. M. 2008. A Contractualist Reply.

More information

R. M. Hare (1919 ) SINNOTT- ARMSTRONG. Definition of moral judgments. Prescriptivism

R. M. Hare (1919 ) SINNOTT- ARMSTRONG. Definition of moral judgments. Prescriptivism 25 R. M. Hare (1919 ) WALTER SINNOTT- ARMSTRONG Richard Mervyn Hare has written on a wide variety of topics, from Plato to the philosophy of language, religion, and education, as well as on applied ethics,

More information

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill Forthcoming in Thought please cite published version In

More information