New Essays on the Knowability Paradox

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "New Essays on the Knowability Paradox"

Transcription

1 New Essays on the Knowability Paradox Edited by JOE SALERNO 1

2 Contents List of Contributors Acknowledgements x xii Introduction 1 Joe Salerno PART I: EARLY HISTORY 1. Referee Reports on Fitch s A Definition of Value 13 Alonzo Church 2. A Logical Analysis of Some Value Concepts 21 Frederic B. Fitch 3. Knowability Noir: Joe Salerno PART II: DUMMETT S CONSTRUCTIVISM 4. Fitch s Paradox of Knowability 51 Michael Dummett 5. The Paradox of Knowability and the Mapping Objection 53 Stig Alstrup Rasmussen 6. Truth, Indefinite Extensibility, and Fitch s Paradox 76 José Luis Bermúdez PART III: PARACONSISTENCY AND PARACOMPLETENESS 7. Beyond the Limits of Knowledge 93 Graham Priest 8. Knowability and Possible Epistemic Oddities 105 Jc Beall

3 viii Contents PART IV: EPISTEMIC AND TEMPORAL OPERATORS: ACTIONS, TIMES AND TYPES 9. Actions That Make Us Know 129 Johan van Benthem 10. Can Truth Out? 147 John Burgess 11. Logical Types in Some Arguments about Knowability and Belief 163 Bernard Linsky PART V: CARTESIAN RESTRICTED TRUTH 12. Tennant s Troubles 183 Timothy Williamson 13. Restriction Strategies for Knowability: Some Lessons in False Hope 205 Jonathan L. Kvanvig 14. Revamping the Restriction Strategy 223 Neil Tennant PART VI: MODAL AND MATHEMATICAL FICTIONS 15. On Keeping Blue Swans and Unknowable Facts at Bay: A Case Study on Fitch s Paradox 241 Berit Brogaard 16. Fitch s Paradox and the Philosophy of Mathematics 252 Otávio Bueno PART VII: KNOWABILITY RECONSIDERED 17. Performance and Paradox 283 Michael Hand 18. The Mystery of the Disappearing Diamond 302 C. S. Jenkins 19. Invincible Ignorance 320 W. D. Hart

4 Contents ix 20. Two Deflationary Approaches to Fitch-Style Reasoning 324 Christoph Kelp and Duncan Pritchard 21. Not Every Truth Can Be Known (at least, not all at once) 339 Greg Restall Bibliography 355 Index 367

5 Introduction Joe Salerno The Knowability Paradox In his seminal paper A Logical Analysis of Some Value Concepts (1963; reprinted, Chapter 2 of this volume), Frederic Fitch articulates an argument that threatens to collapse a number of modal epistemic distinctions. Most directly, it threatens to collapse the existence of fortuitous ignorance into the existence of necessary unknowability. For it shows that there is an unknown truth, only if there is a logically unknowable truth. Fitch called this Theorem 5, which usually is represented formally as follows: (Theorem 5) p(p & Kp) p(p & Kp), where p holds a place for sentence letters; is normal possibility, read it is possible that ; and K is the epistemic operator, it is known (by someone [like us] by some means or other at some time) that. The theorem rests on tremendously modest modal epistemic principles, which we will turn to shortly. The converse of Theorem 5 is modest as well. So Theorem 5 does the interesting work in erasing the logical difference between there being truths forever unknown and there being truths logically unknowable. The contrapositive of Theorem 5 is better known as the knowability paradox: (Knowability Paradox) p(p Kp) p(p Kp). If each truth is knowable in principle, then it follows logically that each truth is at some time known. That s the result. It is thought to be paradoxical for a number of related reasons. First, it refutes all too easily interesting brands of anti-realism which are committed to the knowability principle, p(p Kp).Itrefutesthem since the knowability principle entails the obviously false omniscience principle, p(p Kp). The knowability principle has been claimed for a number of historic non-realisms, among them Michael Dummett s semantic anti-realism, Hilary Putnam s internal realism, the logical positivisms of the Berlin and Vienna Circles, Peirce s pragmatism, Kant s transcendental idealism, and Berkeley s metaphysical

6 2 Joe Salerno idealism. How strange that the knowability principle, and every brand of nonrealism that avows it, are only as plausible as the exceedingly implausible, and obviously false, omniscience principle. An extension of Fitch s result, found in Williamson (1992: 68), shows that a traditional strengthening of the knowability principle forecloses on the very distinction between what is possible and what is actual. Roughly, if truth is possible knowledge then possibility is actuality.¹ The paradoxicality is that sophisticated forms of anti-realism could be so easily refuted. A second reason to regard the proof as paradoxical is that it threatens to erase the logical distinction between the knowability principle and the omniscience principle. More specifically, the proof logically collapses the relatively moderate and plausible claim that each truth can be known into the apparently stronger and unbelievable claim that each truth is in fact known. The claims seem to carry distinct logical commitments, but they do not if Fitch s result is valid. Fitch s result presupposes the following principles. Knowing a conjunction requires knowing each of the conjuncts: (A) K (p & q) Kp & Kq Knowing entails truth: (B) Kp p Theorems are necessarily true: (C) If p,then p And, a necessarily false proposition is impossible: (D) p p The proof may be characterized this way: Atthetopofthetreewesupposeforreductio that the Fitch-conjunction, p & Kp, is known. By (A), it follows that each conjunct is known. The third line demonstrates an application of factivity, (B), to the right conjunct of the second line. In the face of the ensuing contradiction, we discharge and deny our only assumption. By necessitation, (C), and then by (D), we conclude with the impossibility of our initial assumption giving, K (p & Kp). Now suppose the knowability principle, p(p Kp), and take the following instance: (p & Kp) K (p & Kp). This together with the above ¹ More carefully, Williamson shows this: if necessarily something is true if and only if it is knowable, then necessarily p is possible if and only if p.

7 Introduction 3 theorem, K (p & Kp), entails (p & Kp), which may be generalized to p (p & Kp). The classical equivalent is the omniscience principle, p(p Kp). At a glance: In sum, if all truths are knowable, then all truths are known: p(p Kp) p(p Kp). The Generalized Paradox Fitch generalized the knowability result, showing that any operator O that is both factive and closed under conjunction-elimination, generates the following aporia: p(p Op) p(p & Op) }{{}. To prove this Fitch begins with Theorem 1, which holds of any factive operator O that is closed under conjunction-elimination: (Theorem 1) O(p & Op). Theorem 1 generates the above aporia.² Others have noted that it is not just factive, conjunction-distributive operators that validate Theorem 1 and generate the aporia. Belief, for instance, is closed under conjunction-elimination but is not factive. Yet arguably a belief-instance of Theorem 1 is provable, giving B(p & Bp).³ In this way the corresponding aporia is generated for the belief operator: p(p Bp) p(p & Bp) }{{}. ² To see how, substitute p & Op for p in p(p Op). By Theorem 1, it follows that (p & Op). This in turn may be may be generalized, giving p (p & Op), or equivalently p(p & Op). ³ See, for instance, Linsky (1986; and Ch. 11 of this volume).

8 4 Joe Salerno That is, the plausible notion that any truth could be believed is inconsistent with the truism that some truths are not ever believed. Such proofs about belief avoid unrestricted factivity principles in favor of restricted principles about the transparency of beliefs about one s own beliefs. To take another example, a knowledge-version of the result may be derived without the conjunctiondistributivity principle (Williamson 1993). Most generally, then, a Fitch-aporia, or Fitch paradox, is generated for any operator O just when 1. The conjunction p & Op is un-o-able: p O(p & Op); 2. The O-ability principle, p(p Op), is plausible; and 3. Clearly, some truths are un-o-ed: p(p & Op). Operators that seem to generate Fitch-aporias include It is written truthfully on the board that Somebody brought it about that God brought it about that The laws of nature made it the case that It is believed that It is thought that So, for instance, the paradox of omnipotence may be seen, logically, as a special case of Fitch s paradox. It says, roughly, that God can do anything that is in fact done, but only if God does in fact do everything. Another example: any truth can in principle be thought, but only if every truth is (at some time) thought. This latter result, like the result about belief, requires (in lieu of factivity) a principle that avows some minimal transparency of one s thoughts about one s thoughts. The Volume, Contributions and Literature We here turn to some traditional and developing treatments of the paradox. The earliest version of the knowability proof appears in a 1945 referee report for the Journal of Symbolic Logic (printed here as Chapter 1). Its author, Alonzo Church, anonymously conveyed the proof to Fitch. The proof had the effect of undermining a certain definition of value that Fitch was articulating a definition that is trivialized if there are unknowable truths. So the proof originates in a context that is very different from the one in which we discuss the proof today. We think of the knowability paradox today either as an all-too-quick refutation of anti-realism or as a logical collapse of apparently distinct philosophical commitments. More on the more recent debate in a moment. Church offers a number of potentially promising ways to block the proof. He is most sympathetic to a rejection of closure principles for knowledge and belief, and a fortiori

9 Introduction 5 the principle that knowledge is closed under conjunction-elimination. This is principle (A) in our earlier presentation of the proof. So Church ultimately takes the knowability proof to be invalid dare I say, paradoxical. However, Church s proposal does not help Fitch, since Fitch is deeply committed to necessary logical connections between the relevant propositional attitudes. Church considers that one may alternatively appeal to Russell s theory of logical types, which would have the effect of blocking special instances of the conjunctive distributivity principle principle (A). The appeal to types foreshadows Linsky (Chapter 11 of this volume) and Hart (Chapter 19 of this volume). However, Church notes that the type-theoretic approach, like the rejection of closure principles, is antithetical to the goals of Fitch s manuscript. Fitch had a very different kind of reply in mind. He responds to the referee report with a letter to the editor, in which he restricts the relevant class of true propositions to ones that it is empirically possible to know. Fitch s definition of value is thus resuscitated. His restriction strategy foreshadows Neil Tennant (1997), where we find an analogous restriction to the class of true propositions that it is logically possible for somebody to know. We will discuss Tennant s restriction in a moment. It should be noted here that Church was unimpressed with Fitch s restriction strategy, and in a subsequent referee report (also in Chapter 1) attempted a version of the knowability proof that respects Fitch s restriction. The debate between Fitch and Church is tracked in Salerno (Chapter 3). Church s argument against Fitch s restriction strategy, I argue, is critically flawed. Part I of the volume is dedicated to this, the early history of the Church Fitch paradox of knowability. Chapter 1 is the pair of referee reports from They record one side of a dialog between Fitch and the referee regarding the paper submitted by Fitch to JSL. Chapter 2 is Fitch s seminal 1963 paper, shaped in no small part by those reports. Fitch s paper has been the logical fuel or foil for the literature on the knowability paradox. Essay 3 is my understanding of the first two essays. It offers an account of why Fitch included the knowability result in the 1963 paper. Part II is about Michael Dummett s semantic anti-realism. The first wave of reactions to Fitch s 1963 paper, including Hart and McGinn (1976), Hart (1979), Mackie (1980), and Routley (1981), had a common theme. They all aimed to use Fitch s proof to discredit various forms of verificationism, the view that all meaningful statements (and so all truths) are knowable.⁴ The knowability principle is commonly taken throughout the literature as a particularly clear expression of Hilary Putnam s internal realism (1981) and Michael Dummett s ⁴ An exception is Walton (1976), whose aim was to draw lessons in the philosophy of religion. For related discussion, see Plantinga (1982); Humberstone (1985); MacIntosh (1991); Kvanvig (1995, and 2006); Rea (2000); Wright (2000); Cogburn (2004); Bigelow (2005); Brogaard and Salerno (2005); and Moretti (2008).

10 6 Joe Salerno anti-realism (1959b; 1973, and elsewhere). The Fitch paper then threatens these forms of anti-realism. Since Williamson (1982) and Rasmussen and Ravinkilde (1982), however, we find various proposals to vindicate at least Dummettian anti-realism. Fitch s reasoning is classically, but not intuitionistically, valid. Specifically, the move from (p & Kp) top Kp (i.e., the final step in our version of the proof) is intuitionistically unacceptable, since it harbors an application of double-negation elimination i.e., p p. Leading developments in Dummettian anti-realism favor intuitionistic revisions to classical logic.⁵ As such, Dummettian anti-realism is said to evade the unwelcome classical consequences of Fitch. The proposal is further developed in Williamson (1988b; 1990; and 1992). An objection to the intuitionistic strategy is found in the view that the intuitionistic consequences of Fitch s reasoning are as bad, or almost as bad, as the classical consequences. The objection is developed in Percival (1990).⁶ The main intuitionistic consequence is p Kp, which says that no truths are forever unknown. Some equivalent formulas include (p & Kp), which denies that there are unknown truths,and Kp p, which says that anything forever unknown is false, and ( Kp & K p), which denies that there are any forever undecided statements. The potentially irksome consequence, which is a focus of Wright (1993a: 426 7) and Williamson (1994a), can be put this way. The intuitionistic anti-realist lacks the resources to express the apparent truism that there may be truths that never in fact will be known, formally p(p & Kp). That is because the inconsistency derivable from the joint acceptance of the knowability principle and p(p & Kp) is intuitionistically acceptable. In Chapter 4 Dummett embraces the intuitionistic consequences without regret. The paper defends p Kp as the best expression of semantic antirealism.⁷ In a letter to the editor of this volume, Dummett explains that the intuitionistic anti-realist as I conceive of him or her, does not think it irksome that the notion never in fact cannot be expressed by the use of the intuitionistic logical constants. Rather he or she thinks that the only meaning that can be given to never is that expressible by the intuitionistic logical constants. So there is no worry and no frustration. (Letter: September 27, 2005) For insightful discussion of the intuitionistic use of never, see Williamson (1994a). Incidently, Dummett does not endorse the position articulated in his (2001), which proposes a restriction of the knowability principle to basic or atomic ⁵ For alternative formulations of the anti-realist argument against classical logic, see Tennant (2000); Salerno (2000); and Wright (2001). ⁶ Important further discussion and a reply appears in DeVidi and Solomon (2001). ⁷ Cf., DeVidi and Solomon (2001), which offers a defense of this very position on behalf of the Dummettian anti-realist. Dummett embraces the truth of p Kp in much earlier work, including (1977: 339 [2000: 236]).

11 Introduction 7 sentences. Dummett tells me that he wrote that paper to dispel the myth that Fitch s paradox is an objection to any form of anti-realism. In Chapter 5 Stig Rasmussen further investigates and defends Dummett s newly favored knowability principle, p Kp. The centerpiece of the discussion is the mapping objection, which points out that Gödel s 1933 mapping of intuitionistic logic into S4 fails to preserve the original formulation of the knowability principle, and that this fact counts against the original formulation as an expression of intuitionistic anti-realism. In Chapter 6 José Bermúdez argues that the Dummett (2001) position is well-motivated. The position restricts the knowability principle to atomic statements, and defines intuitionistic truth inductively from there. Bermúdez offers an instructive account of Dummett s development in (1990) and (1996). There Dummett attempts to clarify the notion of indefinite extensibility of such concepts as set, natural number, and real number, and argues that only intuitionistic logic can illuminate a proper understanding of the notion. It is argued that if this is correct, then the Dummett (2001) theory of truth is well-motivated, and so, we have a principled solution to the knowability paradox. Part III is dedicated to paraconsistency and paracompleteness. The paraconsistent approach to the paradox is first suggested in Richard Routley (1981). While considering the liar ( This very statement is not true ), the knower ( This very statement is not known ) and Fitch s proposition, K (p & Kp), Routley entertains, but does not endorse, a uniform treatment: What the hardened paraconsistentist says is that [the liar] and K (p & Kp), though inconsistent, are nonetheless coherent, that this is how things are: some (but not too many) inconsistencies hold true. (1981: 112, n. 26) Routley does not endorse the approach. His actual position is that Fitch s result is valid and that it indicates a necessary limitation of human knowledge. Fitch s result shows us that if there is in fact an unknown truth then there is a logically unknowable truth. On the assumption that our actual ignorance is a contingent matter, it is unclear whether the resulting unknowability is contingent or necessary. However, if necessarily we actually fail to know some truths, as Routley argues, then it follows by Fitch s main argument and the closure of necessity (over necessary implication) that, necessarily, some truths are unknowable. The passing insight about paraconsistency emerges in the context of Routley s more central discussion of the necessary limits of knowledge. The paraconsistent approach is first defended in Beall (2000), where it is argued that the knower sentence provides independent evidence that knowledge is inconsistent. For the concept entails that Kp & Kp, forsomep. Further,it is argued that without a solution to the knower we should accept contradictions of this form and go paraconsistent. To this end Wansing (2002) defines a paraconsistent, constructive, relevant, modal, epistemic logic that evades Fitch.

12 8 Joe Salerno The section of this volume on paraconsistency constitutes the most recent developments of the paraconsistent treatment of the problem. In Chapter 7, Graham Priest develops the Routley/Beall proposal by countenancing the mere possibility of truth-value gluts and appealing to a paraconsistent logic with excluded middle. Beall, in Chapter 8, compliments the development by exploring alternatives, some of which avoid the epistemic oddities of Priest s framework. Beall s centerpiece is a semantic framework that is paracomplete, but not paraconsistent, and avoids a commitment even to the mere possibility of truth-value gluts. Part IV is an exploration of temporal and epistemic analogs of Fitch s reasoning. The strategy is to translate the modalities in the knowability principle into a favored temporal or epistemic logic, and to draw lessons from there about the plausibility of the knowability principle and the result in which it figures. Johan van Benthem (Chapter 9) does this by placing the result in a dynamic epistemic setting a setting in which the truth values of our epistemic attributions vary over time with the performance of various actions, such as announcements. The essay is a more thorough development of van Benthem (2004). John Burgess (Chapter 10) translates the Fitch modalities into various Priorian temporal modalities. Each of these two approaches offers, not a rejection of Fitch s proof, but an investigation of the problematic nature of the corresponding knowability principle. Bernard Linsky (Chapter 11) proposes that we block Fitch s result by appealing to a theory of types in our account of epistemic and doxastic reasoning. Interestingly, this is one of the proposals that Alonzo Church (in Chapter 1) considers when entertaining objections to the knowability proof. Linsky shows that the theory of types systematically treats a wide variety of contemporary paradoxes of knowledge and belief. Part V is dedicated to Neil Tennant s Cartesian restriction strategy. Tennant s position is that intuitionistic logic alone will not free anti-realism from the grips of Fitch. His well-discussed proposal is to restrict the knowability principle to Cartesian propositions, that is, propositions that it is not provably inconsistent to know. Objections to the proposal include Hand and Kvanvig (1999), Williamson (2000b), and DeVidi and Kenyon (2003). For replies see Tennant (2000a; and 2000b). Further motivation for Tennant s proposal can be found in Jon Cogburn (2004) and Igor Douven (2005). In Chapter 12, Williamson continues the debate, specifically against Tennant (2001a), and renews his pessimism about the prospects for a successful defense of semantic anti-realism (Cf. Williamson 2000b). Debate with Williamson continues in Tennant (forthcoming). Chapter 13 is Kvanvig s renewed discontent with Tennant s (and any other) restriction to the knowability principle. As he sees it, the real paradoxicality is not that Fitch s result threatens anti-realism, but that it threatens to collapse the very distinction between the existence of unknown truth and the existence of unknowable truth. The section is completed

13 Introduction 9 by Chapter 14, which is Tennant s current position a modification of the Cartesian restriction strategy. Part VI is about modal and mathematical fictionalism. We learn in Brogaard (Chapter 15) that modal fictionalism is threatened by Fitch s paradox. Otávio Bueno (Chapter 16) evaluates the relevance of Fitch s paradox in the epistemology of mathematics. He argues that the mathematical fictionalist must contend with the unwelcome consequences of Fitch. Part VII, Knowability Reconsidered, includes papers that reconsider the antirealist thesis about the knowability of truth. There is a history of attempts to either refute or reformulate anti-realism in reaction of Fitch. I mentioned some refuters earlier. The reformulater is one who rejects, or offers an alternative to, the knowability principle as a characterization of anti-realism. They include Edgington (1985), Melia (1991), Wright (2000), Hand (2003), and Jenkins (2005), among many others. Michael Hand (Chapter 17) further develops his 2003 proposal that Dummett s anti-realist is not committed to the knowability principle, owing to the fact that it carelessly blurs semantic conditions about verification procedures with pragmatic conditions about the performance of such procedures. C. S. Jenkins (Chapter 18) agrees that the knowability principle fails as an expression of anti-realism. Her own statement of anti-realism (2005) is echoed here, but her primary concern is to take issue with Kvanvig (2006), in which it is argued that the real paradoxicality of Fitch s proof is the modal collapse that occurs in the reasoning from the knowability principle to the omniscience principle. W. D. Hart (Chapter 19) takes Fitch s proof to be evidence for realism. He argues that the prospects are not good for a solution coming from the theory of types. Christoph Kelp and Duncan Pritchard (Chapter 20) offer some hope for an anti-realism that endorses a justified believability principle in place of the knowability principle. They evaluate the thesis that, for all true propositions, it must be possible to justifiably believe them. An alternative weakening of the knowability principle is proposed by Greg Restall (Chapter 21). His principle states that, for every truth p, there is a collection of truths, such that (i) each of themisknowable and (ii)theirconjunctionis equivalenttop. Restall proves that this formulation evades the paradox, and draws lessons about the operant notion of possibility. I regret that the volume is incomplete. It includes no extensive discussion of Dorothy Edgington s important 1985 proposal, in which the knowability principle is reformatted as a thesis about the knowability of actual truth. Important criticisms are found in Wright (1987a (2nd edn., 1993: )), Williamson (1987a; 1987b; 2000a, ch. 12), and Percival (1991). Developments of Edgington s proposal are found in Rabinowicz and Segerberg (1994), Linström (1997), Rückert (2004), Fara (forthcoming), and Murzi (manuscript). Related proposals, that focus on the modal semantics of Fitch s paradox, include Kvanvig (1995; 2006), Brogaard and Salerno (2006) and Costa-Leite (2006). These latter three approaches diagnose various modal fallacies. Kvanvig appeals to issues about

14 10 Joe Salerno when we are licensed to substitute into modal contexts. Brogaard and Salerno appeal to Stanley and Szabo s (2000) theory of quantifier domain restriction, according to which there is hidden structure in quantified noun phrases. Costa- Leite appeals to the fusion of Kripke frames the insight being that knowability is not to be understood compositionally out of one-dimensional possibility and knowledge operators.

15 1 Referee Reports on Fitch s A Definition of Value Alonzo Church The referee reports transcribed below were handwritten by Alonzo Church to his co-editor, Ernest Nagel, of the Journal of Symbolic Logic. They were issued in 1945 in response to a paper by Frederic Fitch, A Definition of Value, which was not published. They contain the earliest formulations of the modal epistemic result today known as Fitch s knowability paradox. The bracketed numerals, [n.], indicate the original page numbers. Our appendix is a list of the cited principles. They either originate in Lewis and Langford (1932) or are hypothesized by us to be the principles from Fitch s original manuscript, which was not found. The original reports are located in the Ernest Nagel Papers, Box 1, Arranged Correspondence, Church, Alonzo. Rare Book and Manuscript Library, Columbia University. They are printed here in full by their permission and by kind permission of Alonzo Church, Jr. We are grateful to Nick Zavediuk for his assistance in the transcription process. First Referee Report [1.] It seems to me that the role and meaning of Professor Fitch s SC is seriously in need of clarification. It is not sufficient merely to take SC as primitive and undefined. It must be contemplated that ultimately there is either a definition of SC or an elaborate set of empirical postulates about it; otherwise particular empirical necessitations such as brakeless trains are dangerous could not be decided. Perhaps Fitch means to say that there is one absolutely determined set of all the valid laws of empirical sciences, such that the currently accepted laws of the currently known empirical sciences are an approximation to a certain subset of this set, and that SC is something like the conjunction of all the laws of this set. But this belief in an ultimate set of absolutely valid empirical laws is held by hardly any contemporary empirical scientist. And I think that the recent history of the empirical sciences, especially physics, renders such a belief indefensible. The only alternative I see is to take a particular formalized system of empirical science (say a system which unifies the empirical sciences as they are known today),

16 14 Alonzo Church and to take SC to be the conjunction of the primitive propositions of this system. This is acceptable, but it must be realized that it makes empirical necessitation relative to a particular system. Accepting this emendation, I go on to Fitch s Def. 3. [2.] Following the line of Fitch s thought, let me call a proposition empirically impossible if SC strictly implies its negation. (This makes empirical impossibility equivalent to the negation of empirical possibility and is therefore consistent with Fitch s Def. 6.) Then it may plausibly be maintained that if a is not omniscient there is always a true proposition which it is empirically impossible for a to know at time t. Forletk be a true proposition which is unknown to a at time t, and let k be the proposition that k is true but unknown to a at time t. Thenk is true. But it would seem that if a knows k at time t,thena must know k at time t, and must also know that he does not know k at time t. ByDef.2,thisisa contradiction. Now an empirically impossible proposition empirically necessitates every proposition. Therefore, the argument runs, by taking q in Def. 3 to be k,itmay be inferred that everything is of value to a at time t. Thus Def. 3 is reduced to atriviality. In spite of the plausibility of the preceding argument I think Fitch has a good defense (but only one). This defense is that there is no law of psychology according to which one who believes a proposition must believe all its logical consequences; on the contrary, historical counter-examples are well known. To be sure, one who believes a proposition without believing its more obvious consequences is a fool; but it is an empirical fact that there are fools. It is even possible [3.] that there might be so great a fool as to believe the conjunction of two propositions without believing either of the two propositions; at least, an empirical law to the contrary would seem to be open to doubt. On this ground it is empirically possible that a might believe k at time t without believing k at time t (although k is a conjunction one of whose terms is k). Unfortunately this defense compels Fitch to abandon his Ax. 1. And, what is more serious, it lights the way to a second and opposite objection to Def. 3. If there is no empirical law according to which one who believes a proposition must believe its logical consequences, it would seem that by the same token there is no empirical law according to which a person s desires must be in reasonable accord with that person s beliefs. If someone desiring to recover from a certain disease, and knowing the one and only course of action which will lead to recovery, nevertheless does not desire that course of action, we may call that someone a fool; but again the fact is that fools there be. It is a historical fact that there have been persons who desired to avoid smallpox, who knew the medical efficacy of vaccination as a preventive, and who nevertheless violently resisted vaccination (therefore presumably did not desire it). I conclude [4.] that there is no valid law of psychology according to which anything whatsoever about my desires may be inferred from the fact that I know so-and-so. It follows by Def. 3 that nothing

17 Referee Reports on Fitch s A Definition of Value 15 is of value to a at time t, and again Def. 3 is reduced to a triviality. This is my second objection to Def. 3, and the one to which I attach the greater weight. Since Def. 3 is the core of the paper, I hold that the entire paper is therefore untenable. By this it is not to be understood that I disapprove of the idea of applying symbolic logic to value theory. However severe my criticism of Fitch for what I hold to be logical flaws, my criticism is still more severe of those philosophers who offer similar definitions of value in vague verbal form without the attempt at even so much accuracy as may be attained by the use of certain elementary notations of symbolic logic. For these latter escape the kind of criticism I level against Fitch only by making their statement so vague as to render all criticism uncertain. The very fact that an attempt by Fitch to state formally what I take to be a rather ordinary sort of definition of value leads to these logical difficulties is an indication of the need for at least some elementary symbolic logic here. Let me say also that, in order to meet Fitch on his own ground, I have accepted uncritically what seems to be his notion of [5.] proposition, although it is well known that the notion of proposition is uncertain and in need of clarification. I am willing to concede, at least as a possibility, that one way to obtain clarification of the notion is to plunge directly into the use of propositions and to clear up individual difficulties as they arise. Finally, I note that Fitch makes a medical error on page 4 of the manuscript, in implying that quinine is the only cure for malaria. An entirely different drug, atabrine, is as a matter of fact also an effective cure. It seems to me that according to ordinary usage it would be said that quinine is valuable to the malaria sufferer, even if there does exist an alternative method of cure by means of atabrine. This observation may reveal another deficiency in Def. 3. But in view of more serious objections it seems unnecessary to go into this. Second Referee Report 1. It is not clear to me why Fitch thinks that, to quote his letter, In order to show that a s ignorance of k is empirically necessary, he would first have to show that a s ignorance of k is empirically necessary. The fact is that the quoted statement is false. To enforce my point, let me put the matter quite formally: Assume: k. Assume also: (a KNt k). Def.: k = (k & (a KNt k)). By the foregoing Def., and Fitch s Th. 3: (a KNt k )EN(a KNt k). By Fitch s Def. 2, and Lewis-Langford 11.2: (a KNt k )SIk.

18 16 Alonzo Church Hence by the Def. of k, and Lewis-Langford 11.2, 11.6: (a KNt k )SI (a KNt k). Hence by Lewis-Langford 12.42: (a KNt k)si (a KNt k ). Hence by Fitch s Th. 1: (a KNt k)en (a KNt k ). The transitive law for EN follows from Lewis-Langford 15.1, 16.2, Hence from the foregoing step and step 4 above we get: (a KNt k )EN (a KNt k ). Hence by the law of double negation and Fitch s Def. 5: ((a KNt k )EC(a KNt k )). Hence by Fitch s Def. 6: EP(a KNt k ). However, it follows from our assumptions: k. From this now it follows (for the reason explained in my previous report, and as I [2.] understand Fitch to admit) that Fitch s Def. 3 is untenable as it now stands, and must be altered if the paper as a whole is to be maintained. Now let us consider the revised form of Def. 3 which Fitch proposed in his letter of February 26 and afterwards abandoned. As I understand it this is: Def. 3R. (a VLt p) = (Eq) [q &EP(a KNt q)&[(a KNt q)en(a DSt p)]]. I think that a reductio ad absurdum of Def. 3R is possible along the same lines as that I have given for Def. 3. At least, let me attempt it, and leave it to Fitch to say where if anywhere I have assumed something he would not admit. I shall show as a consequence of Def. 3R that instant death is of value to a at time t.inotherwords,ifp is a dies at time t, Ishallshowthata VLt p. Assume that a does not desire instant death at time t (because in the contrary case, if we assume that it is empirically possible for one to know one s own desires, the conclusion a VLt p is obvious). Nevertheless it is empirically possible for a to desire instant death at time t, both (1) because it is empirically possible that a should be insane, and (2) it isempirically possible thata s external circumstances [3.] at time t might have been so dreadful as to compel even a sane man to desire instant death. Assume also that a isnotomniscient, andlet k besomethingwhichis truebut unknown to a at time t. Define k as before. Then as before k is true but a s ignorance of k is empirically necessary. Let q be the disjunction (a DSt p ) k.thenq is true. I suppose Fitch would admit (a KNt p)en(a KNt (p q)). At least this seems to be entirely in the spirit of his Th. 3, and it is hard to see how he could maintain one and deny the other. Also I suppose that logical consequences of the empirically possible are empirically possible, and that it is empirically possible for one to know one s own desires.

19 Referee Reports on Fitch s A Definition of Value 17 Thus because a DSt p is empirically possible, therefore a KNt (a DSt p )is empirically possible, and therefore a KNt q is empirically possible. Because (a DStp )EN(a DStp )andk EN (a DStp ), therefore q EN (a DStp ). Hence because (a KNt q )ENq, it follows that (a KNt q )EN(a DSt p ). Finally, taking, in Def. 3R, p to be p,andq to be q, we get the conclusion that a VLt p. The case of instant death is of course [4.] chosen only for illustration. In general, under Def. 3R, everything is of value to a at time t which it would be empirically possible for a to desire at time t under any empirically possible circumstances (however remote from the actual circumstances). This is little if any less disastrous than the situation under Def. 3, that everything whatever is of value to a at time t. Of course the foregoing refutation of Fitch s definition of value is strongly suggestive of the paradox of the liar and other epistemological paradoxes. It may therefore be that Fitch can meet this particular objection by incorporating into the system of his paper one of the standard devices for avoiding the epistemological paradoxes. If this is possible it will involve a drastic rewriting of the paper, not just a footnote here and there. To my further objection that there is no law of psychology according to which it can be inferred from the fact that a knows something that therefore a desires something Fitch replies by pointing out that a might know that a desires p. If, however, Fitch consents to adopt one of the standard devices for avoiding the epistemological paradoxes, this reply will no longer be open to him. For example, on the basis of Russell s original [5.] theory of types, a desires p is of higher order than p, whereas the two something s in my assertion must of course be understood as of the same order. On the basis of Tarski s resolution of the epistemological paradoxes, the distinction between language and meta-language has roughly the same effect. I insist therefore that there is no known law of psychology according to which a desires p is ever a necessary consequence of a knows q. Moreover, in the light of every-day experience (summed up in the commonly heard conclusion, Some people are utterly unreasonable ), it seems unlikely that there is a valid law of psychology of that sort remaining to be discovered. If some of us think that there is a notion of value in spite of the fact that some people are utterly unreasonable, it is because we think we know how to distinguish between what is reasonable and what is unreasonable. The problem is whether this distinction between reasonable and unreasonable can be defined in non-valuational terms, or whether this or some like value-theoretic concept must be accepted as primitive (undefined). I do not think that Fitch has solved the problem. The assumption that there is an absolute set of valid empirical laws, SC, to which the accepted laws of the empirical sciences are [6.] approximations in some sense, is of course a piece of metaphysics. I have no objection to metaphysics per se.

20 18 Alonzo Church But this particular piece of metaphysics has more opponents than adherents, and it seems that a definition of value which presupposed it would be of interest only to a very restricted circle. I do not understand why Fitch objects to avoiding the metaphysical issue by making his definition of value relative to a particular (comprehensive) system of empirical science. But this is a side-issue, in view of the existence of more serious objections. As to the matter of quinine and atabrine: it seems that, according to Fitch, if a is a malaria sufferer who has equal access to quinine and atabrine, then both quinine is of value to a and atabrine is of value to a are false. Moreover it may be that there is some drug which is a quicker and more certain cure for malaria than either quinine or atabrine, which is easily accessible to a (if he only knew), but whose properties in this respect are still undiscovered. If so, then not even the disjunction, quinine or atabrine, is valuable to a. It seems to me that such a notion of value departs so far from the everyday notion that it is hardly justified to use the same word for it. Finally, Fitch s plan of adding [6.] short postscripts to his paper commenting on particular objections by the referee does not seem to me a good one. So far as the objections either are valid or represent misunderstandings likely to be duplicated by others, they should be met (if that is possible) by alterations in the body of the paper. Appendix Joe Salerno and Julien Murzi Fitch s Operators psiq= p q = p strictly implies q penq= p empirically necessitates q EPp = p is empirically possible pecq= p is empirically consistent with q akntp = a knows at time t that p abtp = a believes at t that p avltp = a values at t that p adstp = a desires at t that p Lewis and Langford (1932) Definition and Theorems (p q) = df (p & q) 11.2 (p & q) p

21 Referee Reports on Fitch s A Definition of Value ((p q) (q r)) (p r) (p q) (q p) 15.1 ((p q) & (q r)) (p r) 16.2 ((p q) & (p r) & T) (p (q & r)): T = ((q & r) (r & q)) Fitch s Definitions¹ Def. 2 Def. 2 is Fitch s definition of knowledge. All we know from Church s use is that it justifies the principle that a s knowing at time t that p strictly implies p: akntp p.² Def. 3 avlt p = df q(q & (akntqenadstp)). Value is what one would desire given sufficient knowledge: it is valuable to a at t that p if and only if there is a true proposition q, such that a s knowing at t that q empirically necessitates a s desiring at t that p.³ Def. 3R avlt p = df q(q & EP(aKNtq) & (akntqenadstp)). Value is what one would desire given sufficient knowledge: it is valuable to a at t that p if and only if there is a truth q that it is empirically possible to know and a s knowing at t that q empirically necessitates a s desiring at t that p.⁴ Def. 5 (p EN p) (p EC p). Necessarily, if p empirically necessitates p, then p is not (empirically) consistent with itself.⁵ Def. 6 (p EC p) = df EPp. p is not (empirically) consistent with itself just in case p is not empirically possible.⁶ ¹ An asterisk,, indicates that the principle does not appear explicitly in the reports, and therefore, that we have hypothesized its content. ² Church s applications appear in Report 1: 2 and Report 2: 1. ³ Our formulation of Def. 3 is based on Church s trivialization argument against it. Compare Report 1: 2 and Report 2: 1 2. ⁴ Report 2: 2. ⁵ Report 2: 1. ⁶ Report 1: 2, and Report 2: 1.

22 20 Alonzo Church Fitch saxiomsandtheorems Ax. 1 (abtp & (p ENq)) abtq Belief is closed under empirically necessary implication: necessarily, if a believes at t that p and p empirically necessitates q, then a believes at t that q.⁷ Th. 1 (p q) (p EN q) Strict implication strictly implies empirical necessitation: necessarily, if p strictly implies q then p empirically necessitates q.⁸ Th. 3 aknt(p & q) (akntp &akntq) Knowing a conjunction strictly implies knowing the conjuncts: necessarily, if a knows at t that both p and q, then a knows at t that p and a knows at t that q.⁹ ⁷ The discussion at Report 1: 2 3 suggests that Ax. 1 is this closure principle for belief. Alternatively, it is an unrestricted closure principle for knowledge (viz., knowledge is closed under necessary empirical implication). ⁸ See for instance, Church s use in Report 2: 1. ⁹ Report 2: 1.

23 2 A Logical Analysis of Some Value Concepts¹ Frederic B. Fitch The purpose of this paper is to provide a partial logical analysis of a few concepts that may be classified as value concepts or as concepts that are closely related to value concepts.among the concepts that will be considered are striving for, doing, believing, knowing, desiring, ability to do, obligation todo,andvalue for.familiarity will be assumed with the concepts of logical necessity, logical possibility, and strict implication as formalized in standard systems of modal logic (such as S4), and with the concepts of obligation and permission as formalized in systems of deontic logic.² It will also be assumed that quantifiers over propositions have been included in extensions of these systems.³ There is no intention to provide exhaustive logical analyses, or to provide logical analyses that reflect in detail the usage of so-called ordinary language. This latter task seems impossible anyhow because of the ambiguities of ordinary language and the obvious inconsistencies and irregularities of usage in ordinary language. Furthermore, the term ordinary language is itself rather vague. Whose ordinary language? Should English be preferred to Chinese? Various arguments that invoke English or Latin grammatical usage are seen to be without foundation from the standpoint of Chinese. Just as the concepts of necessity and possibility used in so-called ordinary language correspond in some degree to the concepts of necessity and possibility Chapter 2 was first published in the Journal of Symbolic Logic 28/2, (1963) and is reproduced by permission of the Association for Symbolic Logic. ¹ An earlier draft of this paper was presented as a retiring presidential address to the Association for Symbolic Logic; read before the Association at Atlantic City, New Jersey, December 27, ² For example see A. R. Anderson, The formal analysis of normative systems, TechnicalReport No. 2, Contract No. SAR/Nonr-609(16), Office of Naval Research, Group Psychology Branch, 1956; also, by the same author, A reduction of deontic logic to alethic modal logic, Mind, n.s.vol.67 (1958), pp ³ Such quantifiers can be introduced by methods analogous to those used in R. C. Barcan (Marcus), A functional calculus of first order based on strict implication, thisjournal,vol. 11 (1946), pp. 1 16; The deduction theorem in a functional calculus of first order based on strict implication,ibid., pp ; and F. B. Fitch, Intuitionistic modal logic with quantifiers, Portugaliae mathematica, vol. 7 (1948), pp See also, R. Carnap, Modalities and quantification,thisjournal,vol.11 (1946), pp

24 22 Frederic B. Fitch used in modal logic, so too it is to be hoped that the ordinary language concepts of striving, doing, believing, desiring and knowing will correspond in some degree to the concepts that we will partially formalize here. Also, just as there are various slightly differing concepts of possibility and necessity corresponding to differing systems of modal logic, so too there are presumably various slightly differing concepts of striving, doing, believing, and knowing, having differing formalizations. We begin by assuming that striving, doing, believing, and knowing all have at least some fairly simple properties which will be described in what follows, and we leave open the question as to what further properties they have. First of all, we assume that striving, doing, believing, and knowing are twotermed relations between an agent and a possible state of affairs. It is convenient to treat these possible states of affairs as propositions, so if I say that a strives for p, wherep is a proposition, I mean that a strives to bring about or realize the (possible) state of affairs expressed by the proposition p. Similarly, if I say that a does p,wherep is a proposition, I mean that a brings about the (possible) state of affairs expressed by the proposition p. We do not even have to restrict ourselves to possible states of affairs, because impossible states of affairs can be expressed by propositions just as well as can possible states of affairs. In the case of believing and knowing, there is surely no serious difficulty in regarding propositions as the things believed and known. So we treat all these concepts as two-termed relations between an agent and a proposition. In a similar way, the concept of proving could also be regarded as a two-termed relation between an agent and a proposition. For purposes of simplification, the element of time will be ignored in dealing with these various concepts. A more detailed treatment would require that time be taken seriously. One method would be to treat these concepts as a three-termed relation between an agent, a proposition, and a time. Another method would be to avoid specifying times explicitly, but rather to use a temporal ordering relation between states of affairs. This latter method might be more in keeping with the theory of relativity, in either its special or general form. As a further step of simplification we will often ignore the agent and thus treat each of the concepts under consideration as a class of propositions rather than as a two-termed relation. For example, by striving we will mean the class of propositions striven for (that is, striven to be realized), and by believing we will mean the class of propositions believed, relativizing the whole treatment to some unspecified agent. But the agent can always be specified if we wish to do so, and we can replace classes by two-termed relations. A class of propositions (in particular such classes of propositions as striving, knowing, etc.) will be said to be closed with respect to conjunction elimination if (necessarily) whenever the conjunction of two propositions is in the class so are the two propositions themselves. For example, the class of true propositions is closed with respect to conjunction elimination because (necessarily) if the

25 A Logical Analysis of Some Value Concepts 23 conjunction of two propositions is true, so are the propositions themselves. If α is a class closed with respect to conjunction elimination, this fact about α can be expressed in logical symbolism by the formula, (p)(q)[(α[p & q]) [(αp) &(αq)]], where stands for strict implication. We assume that the following concepts, viewed as classes of propositions, are closed with respect to conjunction elimination: striving (for), doing, believing, knowing, proving. For example, in the case of believing we assume: (p)(q)[(believes[p & q]) [(believes p) & (believes q)]]. Here are some further concepts which are evidently closed with respect to conjunction elimination: truth, causal necessity (in the sense of Burks),⁴ causal possibility (in the sense of Burks), (logical) necessity, (logical) possibility, obligation (deontic necessity), permission (deontic possibility), desire for. A class of propositions will be said to be closed with respect to conjunction introduction if (necessarily) whenever two propositions are in the class, so is the conjunction of the two propositions. If α is a class closed with respect to conjunctionintroduction, thisfact about α can be expressed in logical symbolism by the formula, (p)(q)[[(αp) &(αq)] (α[p & q])]. Except for causal, logical, and deontic possibility, all the concepts so far regarded as closed with respect to conjunction elimination could perhaps also be regarded as closed with respect to conjunction introduction, or some varieties of them could. For present purposes, however, we do not need to commit ourselves on this matter except to say that truth and causal, logical, and deontic necessity are all indeed closed with respect to conjunction introduction. A class of propositions will be said to be a truth class if (necessarily) every member of it is true. If α is a truth class, this fact about α can be expressed ⁴ A. W. Burks, The logic of causal propositions, Mind, n.s. vol. 60 (1951), pp

Introduction to knowability and beyond

Introduction to knowability and beyond Synthese (2010) 173:1 8 DOI 10.1007/s11229-009-9680-z Introduction to knowability and beyond Joe Salerno Received: 7 April 2008 / Accepted: 25 August 2009 / Published online: 15 October 2009 Springer Science+Business

More information

The Paradox of Knowability and Semantic Anti-Realism

The Paradox of Knowability and Semantic Anti-Realism The Paradox of Knowability and Semantic Anti-Realism Julianne Chung B.A. Honours Thesis Supervisor: Richard Zach Department of Philosophy University of Calgary 2007 UNIVERSITY OF CALGARY This copy is to

More information

BIROn - Birkbeck Institutional Research Online

BIROn - Birkbeck Institutional Research Online BIROn - Birkbeck Institutional Research Online Enabling open access to Birkbeck s published research output The paradox of idealization Journal Article http://eprints.bbk.ac.uk/3179 Version: Post-print

More information

On A New Cosmological Argument

On A New Cosmological Argument On A New Cosmological Argument Richard Gale and Alexander Pruss A New Cosmological Argument, Religious Studies 35, 1999, pp.461 76 present a cosmological argument which they claim is an improvement over

More information

Constructive Logic, Truth and Warranted Assertibility

Constructive Logic, Truth and Warranted Assertibility Constructive Logic, Truth and Warranted Assertibility Greg Restall Department of Philosophy Macquarie University Version of May 20, 2000....................................................................

More information

A Liar Paradox. Richard G. Heck, Jr. Brown University

A Liar Paradox. Richard G. Heck, Jr. Brown University A Liar Paradox Richard G. Heck, Jr. Brown University It is widely supposed nowadays that, whatever the right theory of truth may be, it needs to satisfy a principle sometimes known as transparency : Any

More information

Exercise Sets. KS Philosophical Logic: Modality, Conditionals Vagueness. Dirk Kindermann University of Graz July 2014

Exercise Sets. KS Philosophical Logic: Modality, Conditionals Vagueness. Dirk Kindermann University of Graz July 2014 Exercise Sets KS Philosophical Logic: Modality, Conditionals Vagueness Dirk Kindermann University of Graz July 2014 1 Exercise Set 1 Propositional and Predicate Logic 1. Use Definition 1.1 (Handout I Propositional

More information

Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh For Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh I Tim Maudlin s Truth and Paradox offers a theory of truth that arises from

More information

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002 1 Symposium on Understanding Truth By Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002 2 Precis of Understanding Truth Scott Soames Understanding Truth aims to illuminate

More information

A Note on a Remark of Evans *

A Note on a Remark of Evans * Penultimate draft of a paper published in the Polish Journal of Philosophy 10 (2016), 7-15. DOI: 10.5840/pjphil20161028 A Note on a Remark of Evans * Wolfgang Barz Johann Wolfgang Goethe-Universität Frankfurt

More information

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR CRÍTICA, Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía Vol. XXXI, No. 91 (abril 1999): 91 103 SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR MAX KÖLBEL Doctoral Programme in Cognitive Science Universität Hamburg In his paper

More information

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS [This is the penultimate draft of an article that appeared in Analysis 66.2 (April 2006), 135-41, available here by permission of Analysis, the Analysis Trust, and Blackwell Publishing. The definitive

More information

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts ANAL63-3 4/15/2003 2:40 PM Page 221 Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts Alexander Bird 1. Introduction In his (2002) Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra provides a powerful articulation of the claim that Resemblance

More information

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Ayer and Quine on the a priori Ayer and Quine on the a priori November 23, 2004 1 The problem of a priori knowledge Ayer s book is a defense of a thoroughgoing empiricism, not only about what is required for a belief to be justified

More information

Informalizing Formal Logic

Informalizing Formal Logic Informalizing Formal Logic Antonis Kakas Department of Computer Science, University of Cyprus, Cyprus antonis@ucy.ac.cy Abstract. This paper discusses how the basic notions of formal logic can be expressed

More information

Necessity and Truth Makers

Necessity and Truth Makers JAN WOLEŃSKI Instytut Filozofii Uniwersytetu Jagiellońskiego ul. Gołębia 24 31-007 Kraków Poland Email: jan.wolenski@uj.edu.pl Web: http://www.filozofia.uj.edu.pl/jan-wolenski Keywords: Barry Smith, logic,

More information

Williams on Supervaluationism and Logical Revisionism

Williams on Supervaluationism and Logical Revisionism Williams on Supervaluationism and Logical Revisionism Nicholas K. Jones Non-citable draft: 26 02 2010. Final version appeared in: The Journal of Philosophy (2011) 108: 11: 633-641 Central to discussion

More information

Truth and Molinism * Trenton Merricks. Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, 2011.

Truth and Molinism * Trenton Merricks. Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, 2011. Truth and Molinism * Trenton Merricks Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, 2011. According to Luis de Molina, God knows what each and every possible human would

More information

How Gödelian Ontological Arguments Fail

How Gödelian Ontological Arguments Fail How Gödelian Ontological Arguments Fail Matthew W. Parker Abstract. Ontological arguments like those of Gödel (1995) and Pruss (2009; 2012) rely on premises that initially seem plausible, but on closer

More information

Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments

Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments Jeff Speaks January 25, 2011 1 Warfield s argument for compatibilism................................ 1 2 Why the argument fails to show that free will and

More information

Modal Realism, Counterpart Theory, and Unactualized Possibilities

Modal Realism, Counterpart Theory, and Unactualized Possibilities This is the author version of the following article: Baltimore, Joseph A. (2014). Modal Realism, Counterpart Theory, and Unactualized Possibilities. Metaphysica, 15 (1), 209 217. The final publication

More information

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the THE MEANING OF OUGHT Ralph Wedgwood What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the meaning of a word in English. Such empirical semantic questions should ideally

More information

Can Gödel s Incompleteness Theorem be a Ground for Dialetheism? *

Can Gödel s Incompleteness Theorem be a Ground for Dialetheism? * 논리연구 20-2(2017) pp. 241-271 Can Gödel s Incompleteness Theorem be a Ground for Dialetheism? * 1) Seungrak Choi Abstract Dialetheism is the view that there exists a true contradiction. This paper ventures

More information

LOGICAL PLURALISM IS COMPATIBLE WITH MONISM ABOUT METAPHYSICAL MODALITY

LOGICAL PLURALISM IS COMPATIBLE WITH MONISM ABOUT METAPHYSICAL MODALITY LOGICAL PLURALISM IS COMPATIBLE WITH MONISM ABOUT METAPHYSICAL MODALITY Nicola Ciprotti and Luca Moretti Beall and Restall [2000], [2001] and [2006] advocate a comprehensive pluralist approach to logic,

More information

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence Prequel for Section 4.2 of Defending the Correspondence Theory Published by PJP VII, 1 From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence Abstract I introduce new details in an argument for necessarily existing

More information

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Fall 2010 Hamilton College Russell Marcus Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism I. The Continuum Hypothesis and Its Independence The continuum problem

More information

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods delineating the scope of deductive reason Roger Bishop Jones Abstract. The scope of deductive reason is considered. First a connection is discussed between the

More information

A Puzzle about Knowing Conditionals i. (final draft) Daniel Rothschild University College London. and. Levi Spectre The Open University of Israel

A Puzzle about Knowing Conditionals i. (final draft) Daniel Rothschild University College London. and. Levi Spectre The Open University of Israel A Puzzle about Knowing Conditionals i (final draft) Daniel Rothschild University College London and Levi Spectre The Open University of Israel Abstract: We present a puzzle about knowledge, probability

More information

1. Lukasiewicz s Logic

1. Lukasiewicz s Logic Bulletin of the Section of Logic Volume 29/3 (2000), pp. 115 124 Dale Jacquette AN INTERNAL DETERMINACY METATHEOREM FOR LUKASIEWICZ S AUSSAGENKALKÜLS Abstract An internal determinacy metatheorem is proved

More information

In this paper I will critically discuss a theory known as conventionalism

In this paper I will critically discuss a theory known as conventionalism Aporia vol. 22 no. 2 2012 Combating Metric Conventionalism Matthew Macdonald In this paper I will critically discuss a theory known as conventionalism about the metric of time. Simply put, conventionalists

More information

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice Daniele Porello danieleporello@gmail.com Institute for Logic, Language & Computation (ILLC) University of Amsterdam, Plantage Muidergracht 24

More information

G. H. von Wright Deontic Logic

G. H. von Wright Deontic Logic G. H. von Wright Deontic Logic Kian Mintz-Woo University of Amsterdam January 9, 2009 January 9, 2009 Logic of Norms 2010 1/17 INTRODUCTION In von Wright s 1951 formulation, deontic logic is intended to

More information

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW DISCUSSION NOTE BY CAMPBELL BROWN JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE MAY 2015 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT CAMPBELL BROWN 2015 Two Versions of Hume s Law MORAL CONCLUSIONS CANNOT VALIDLY

More information

McDowell and the New Evil Genius

McDowell and the New Evil Genius 1 McDowell and the New Evil Genius Ram Neta and Duncan Pritchard 0. Many epistemologists both internalists and externalists regard the New Evil Genius Problem (Lehrer & Cohen 1983) as constituting an important

More information

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become Aporia vol. 24 no. 1 2014 Incoherence in Epistemic Relativism I. Introduction In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become increasingly popular across various academic disciplines.

More information

5 A Modal Version of the

5 A Modal Version of the 5 A Modal Version of the Ontological Argument E. J. L O W E Moreland, J. P.; Sweis, Khaldoun A.; Meister, Chad V., Jul 01, 2013, Debating Christian Theism The original version of the ontological argument

More information

Aquinas' Third Way Modalized

Aquinas' Third Way Modalized Philosophy of Religion Aquinas' Third Way Modalized Robert E. Maydole Davidson College bomaydole@davidson.edu ABSTRACT: The Third Way is the most interesting and insightful of Aquinas' five arguments for

More information

1/12. The A Paralogisms

1/12. The A Paralogisms 1/12 The A Paralogisms The character of the Paralogisms is described early in the chapter. Kant describes them as being syllogisms which contain no empirical premises and states that in them we conclude

More information

REASONS AND ENTAILMENT

REASONS AND ENTAILMENT REASONS AND ENTAILMENT Bart Streumer b.streumer@rug.nl Erkenntnis 66 (2007): 353-374 Published version available here: http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s10670-007-9041-6 Abstract: What is the relation between

More information

CONCEPT FORMATION IN ETHICAL THEORIES: DEALING WITH POLAR PREDICATES

CONCEPT FORMATION IN ETHICAL THEORIES: DEALING WITH POLAR PREDICATES DISCUSSION NOTE CONCEPT FORMATION IN ETHICAL THEORIES: DEALING WITH POLAR PREDICATES BY SEBASTIAN LUTZ JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE AUGUST 2010 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT SEBASTIAN

More information

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction? Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction? We argue that, if deduction is taken to at least include classical logic (CL, henceforth), justifying CL - and thus deduction

More information

Skepticism and Internalism

Skepticism and Internalism Skepticism and Internalism John Greco Abstract: This paper explores a familiar skeptical problematic and considers some strategies for responding to it. Section 1 reconstructs and disambiguates the skeptical

More information

UC Berkeley, Philosophy 142, Spring 2016

UC Berkeley, Philosophy 142, Spring 2016 Logical Consequence UC Berkeley, Philosophy 142, Spring 2016 John MacFarlane 1 Intuitive characterizations of consequence Modal: It is necessary (or apriori) that, if the premises are true, the conclusion

More information

On possibly nonexistent propositions

On possibly nonexistent propositions On possibly nonexistent propositions Jeff Speaks January 25, 2011 abstract. Alvin Plantinga gave a reductio of the conjunction of the following three theses: Existentialism (the view that, e.g., the proposition

More information

What God Could Have Made

What God Could Have Made 1 What God Could Have Made By Heimir Geirsson and Michael Losonsky I. Introduction Atheists have argued that if there is a God who is omnipotent, omniscient and omnibenevolent, then God would have made

More information

Molnar on Truthmakers for Negative Truths

Molnar on Truthmakers for Negative Truths Molnar on Truthmakers for Negative Truths Nils Kürbis Dept of Philosophy, King s College London Penultimate draft, forthcoming in Metaphysica. The final publication is available at www.reference-global.com

More information

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Kent State University BIBLID [0873-626X (2014) 39; pp. 139-145] Abstract The causal theory of reference (CTR) provides a well-articulated and widely-accepted account

More information

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions Truth At a World for Modal Propositions 1 Introduction Existentialism is a thesis that concerns the ontological status of individual essences and singular propositions. Let us define an individual essence

More information

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible ) Philosophical Proof of God: Derived from Principles in Bernard Lonergan s Insight May 2014 Robert J. Spitzer, S.J., Ph.D. Magis Center of Reason and Faith Lonergan s proof may be stated as follows: Introduction

More information

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic 1 Introduction Zahra Ahmadianhosseini In order to tackle the problem of handling empty names in logic, Andrew Bacon (2013) takes on an approach based on positive

More information

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006 In Defense of Radical Empiricism Joseph Benjamin Riegel A thesis submitted to the faculty of the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of

More information

Conventionalism and the linguistic doctrine of logical truth

Conventionalism and the linguistic doctrine of logical truth 1 Conventionalism and the linguistic doctrine of logical truth 1.1 Introduction Quine s work on analyticity, translation, and reference has sweeping philosophical implications. In his first important philosophical

More information

Scott Soames: Understanding Truth

Scott Soames: Understanding Truth Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXV, No. 2, September 2002 Scott Soames: Understanding Truth MAlTHEW MCGRATH Texas A & M University Scott Soames has written a valuable book. It is unmatched

More information

Semantic Entailment and Natural Deduction

Semantic Entailment and Natural Deduction Semantic Entailment and Natural Deduction Alice Gao Lecture 6, September 26, 2017 Entailment 1/55 Learning goals Semantic entailment Define semantic entailment. Explain subtleties of semantic entailment.

More information

Paradox of Deniability

Paradox of Deniability 1 Paradox of Deniability Massimiliano Carrara FISPPA Department, University of Padua, Italy Peking University, Beijing - 6 November 2018 Introduction. The starting elements Suppose two speakers disagree

More information

Varieties of Apriority

Varieties of Apriority S E V E N T H E X C U R S U S Varieties of Apriority T he notions of a priori knowledge and justification play a central role in this work. There are many ways in which one can understand the a priori,

More information

THE POSSIBILITY OF AN ALL-KNOWING GOD

THE POSSIBILITY OF AN ALL-KNOWING GOD THE POSSIBILITY OF AN ALL-KNOWING GOD The Possibility of an All-Knowing God Jonathan L. Kvanvig Assistant Professor of Philosophy Texas A & M University Palgrave Macmillan Jonathan L. Kvanvig, 1986 Softcover

More information

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE Diametros nr 29 (wrzesień 2011): 80-92 THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE Karol Polcyn 1. PRELIMINARIES Chalmers articulates his argument in terms of two-dimensional

More information

Automated Reasoning Project. Research School of Information Sciences and Engineering. and Centre for Information Science Research

Automated Reasoning Project. Research School of Information Sciences and Engineering. and Centre for Information Science Research Technical Report TR-ARP-14-95 Automated Reasoning Project Research School of Information Sciences and Engineering and Centre for Information Science Research Australian National University August 10, 1995

More information

Qualitative and quantitative inference to the best theory. reply to iikka Niiniluoto Kuipers, Theodorus

Qualitative and quantitative inference to the best theory. reply to iikka Niiniluoto Kuipers, Theodorus University of Groningen Qualitative and quantitative inference to the best theory. reply to iikka Niiniluoto Kuipers, Theodorus Published in: EPRINTS-BOOK-TITLE IMPORTANT NOTE: You are advised to consult

More information

Realism and the success of science argument. Leplin:

Realism and the success of science argument. Leplin: Realism and the success of science argument Leplin: 1) Realism is the default position. 2) The arguments for anti-realism are indecisive. In particular, antirealism offers no serious rival to realism in

More information

GROUNDING AND LOGICAL BASING PERMISSIONS

GROUNDING AND LOGICAL BASING PERMISSIONS Diametros 50 (2016): 81 96 doi: 10.13153/diam.50.2016.979 GROUNDING AND LOGICAL BASING PERMISSIONS Diego Tajer Abstract. The relation between logic and rationality has recently re-emerged as an important

More information

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece Outline of this Talk 1. What is the nature of logic? Some history

More information

Evidential arguments from evil

Evidential arguments from evil International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 48: 1 10, 2000. 2000 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands. 1 Evidential arguments from evil RICHARD OTTE University of California at Santa

More information

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE AND META-ETHICS

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE AND META-ETHICS The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 54, No. 217 October 2004 ISSN 0031 8094 PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE AND META-ETHICS BY IRA M. SCHNALL Meta-ethical discussions commonly distinguish subjectivism from emotivism,

More information

Intersubstitutivity Principles and the Generalization Function of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh. Shawn Standefer University of Melbourne

Intersubstitutivity Principles and the Generalization Function of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh. Shawn Standefer University of Melbourne Intersubstitutivity Principles and the Generalization Function of Truth Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh Shawn Standefer University of Melbourne Abstract We offer a defense of one aspect of Paul Horwich

More information

This is a longer version of the review that appeared in Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 47 (1997)

This is a longer version of the review that appeared in Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 47 (1997) This is a longer version of the review that appeared in Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 47 (1997) Frege by Anthony Kenny (Penguin, 1995. Pp. xi + 223) Frege s Theory of Sense and Reference by Wolfgang Carl

More information

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE By RICHARD FELDMAN Closure principles for epistemic justification hold that one is justified in believing the logical consequences, perhaps of a specified sort,

More information

THIRD NEW C OLLEGE LO GIC MEETING

THIRD NEW C OLLEGE LO GIC MEETING THIRD NEW C OLLEGE LO GIC MEETING 22, 23 and 25 April 2012 Noel Salter Room New College final version The conference is supported by the uk-latin America and the Caribbean Link Programme of the British

More information

Philosophy 240: Symbolic Logic

Philosophy 240: Symbolic Logic Philosophy 240: Symbolic Logic Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2011 Class 27: October 28 Truth and Liars Marcus, Symbolic Logic, Fall 2011 Slide 1 Philosophers and Truth P Sex! P Lots of technical

More information

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg 1 In Search of the Ontological Argument Richard Oxenberg Abstract We can attend to the logic of Anselm's ontological argument, and amuse ourselves for a few hours unraveling its convoluted word-play, or

More information

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999):

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999): Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999): 47 54. Abstract: John Etchemendy (1990) has argued that Tarski's definition of logical

More information

HOW TO SOLVE THE KNOWABILITY PARADOX WITH TRANSCENDENTAL EPISTEMOLOGY

HOW TO SOLVE THE KNOWABILITY PARADOX WITH TRANSCENDENTAL EPISTEMOLOGY HOW TO SOLVE THE KNOWABILITY PARADOX WITH TRANSCENDENTAL EPISTEMOLOGY Andrew Stephenson University of Southampton Abstract A novel solution to the knowability paradox is proposed based on Kant s transcendental

More information

Negative Introspection Is Mysterious

Negative Introspection Is Mysterious Negative Introspection Is Mysterious Abstract. The paper provides a short argument that negative introspection cannot be algorithmic. This result with respect to a principle of belief fits to what we know

More information

Luminosity, Reliability, and the Sorites

Luminosity, Reliability, and the Sorites Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXXXI No. 3, November 2010 2010 Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LLC Luminosity, Reliability, and the Sorites STEWART COHEN University of Arizona

More information

Constructing the World

Constructing the World Constructing the World Lecture 1: A Scrutable World David Chalmers Plan *1. Laplace s demon 2. Primitive concepts and the Aufbau 3. Problems for the Aufbau 4. The scrutability base 5. Applications Laplace

More information

Can Negation be Defined in Terms of Incompatibility?

Can Negation be Defined in Terms of Incompatibility? Can Negation be Defined in Terms of Incompatibility? Nils Kurbis 1 Abstract Every theory needs primitives. A primitive is a term that is not defined any further, but is used to define others. Thus primitives

More information

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill Forthcoming in Thought please cite published version In

More information

On Some Alleged Consequences Of The Hartle-Hawking Cosmology. In [3], Quentin Smith claims that the Hartle-Hawking cosmology is inconsistent with

On Some Alleged Consequences Of The Hartle-Hawking Cosmology. In [3], Quentin Smith claims that the Hartle-Hawking cosmology is inconsistent with On Some Alleged Consequences Of The Hartle-Hawking Cosmology In [3], Quentin Smith claims that the Hartle-Hawking cosmology is inconsistent with classical theism in a way which redounds to the discredit

More information

SMITH ON TRUTHMAKERS 1. Dominic Gregory. I. Introduction

SMITH ON TRUTHMAKERS 1. Dominic Gregory. I. Introduction Australasian Journal of Philosophy Vol. 79, No. 3, pp. 422 427; September 2001 SMITH ON TRUTHMAKERS 1 Dominic Gregory I. Introduction In [2], Smith seeks to show that some of the problems faced by existing

More information

Truth and Realism. EDITED BY PATRICK GREENOUGH AND MICHAEL P. LYNCH. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. ix Price h/b, p/b.

Truth and Realism. EDITED BY PATRICK GREENOUGH AND MICHAEL P. LYNCH. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. ix Price h/b, p/b. Truth and Realism. EDITED BY PATRICK GREENOUGH AND MICHAEL P. LYNCH. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2006. Pp. ix + 253. Price 45.00 h/b, 18.99 p/b.) This book collects papers presented at a conference of the

More information

Generic truth and mixed conjunctions: some alternatives

Generic truth and mixed conjunctions: some alternatives Analysis Advance Access published June 15, 2009 Generic truth and mixed conjunctions: some alternatives AARON J. COTNOIR Christine Tappolet (2000) posed a problem for alethic pluralism: either deny the

More information

Figure 1 Figure 2 U S S. non-p P P

Figure 1 Figure 2 U S S. non-p P P 1 Depicting negation in diagrammatic logic: legacy and prospects Fabien Schang, Amirouche Moktefi schang.fabien@voila.fr amirouche.moktefi@gersulp.u-strasbg.fr Abstract Here are considered the conditions

More information

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea. Book reviews World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Naturalism, by Michael C. Rea. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2004, viii + 245 pp., $24.95. This is a splendid book. Its ideas are bold and

More information

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM SKÉPSIS, ISSN 1981-4194, ANO VII, Nº 14, 2016, p. 33-39. THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM ALEXANDRE N. MACHADO Universidade Federal do Paraná (UFPR) Email:

More information

Entailment, with nods to Lewy and Smiley

Entailment, with nods to Lewy and Smiley Entailment, with nods to Lewy and Smiley Peter Smith November 20, 2009 Last week, we talked a bit about the Anderson-Belnap logic of entailment, as discussed in Priest s Introduction to Non-Classical Logic.

More information

Mohammad Reza Vaez Shahrestani. University of Bonn

Mohammad Reza Vaez Shahrestani. University of Bonn Philosophy Study, November 2017, Vol. 7, No. 11, 595-600 doi: 10.17265/2159-5313/2017.11.002 D DAVID PUBLISHING Defending Davidson s Anti-skepticism Argument: A Reply to Otavio Bueno Mohammad Reza Vaez

More information

BENEDIKT PAUL GÖCKE. Ruhr-Universität Bochum

BENEDIKT PAUL GÖCKE. Ruhr-Universität Bochum 264 BOOK REVIEWS AND NOTICES BENEDIKT PAUL GÖCKE Ruhr-Universität Bochum István Aranyosi. God, Mind, and Logical Space: A Revisionary Approach to Divinity. Palgrave Frontiers in Philosophy of Religion.

More information

Experience and Foundationalism in Audi s The Architecture of Reason

Experience and Foundationalism in Audi s The Architecture of Reason Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXVII, No. 1, July 2003 Experience and Foundationalism in Audi s The Architecture of Reason WALTER SINNOTT-ARMSTRONG Dartmouth College Robert Audi s The Architecture

More information

AN EPISTEMIC PARADOX. Byron KALDIS

AN EPISTEMIC PARADOX. Byron KALDIS AN EPISTEMIC PARADOX Byron KALDIS Consider the following statement made by R. Aron: "It can no doubt be maintained, in the spirit of philosophical exactness, that every historical fact is a construct,

More information

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory Western University Scholarship@Western 2015 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2015 Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory David Hakim Western University, davidhakim266@gmail.com

More information

Review of "The Tarskian Turn: Deflationism and Axiomatic Truth"

Review of The Tarskian Turn: Deflationism and Axiomatic Truth Essays in Philosophy Volume 13 Issue 2 Aesthetics and the Senses Article 19 August 2012 Review of "The Tarskian Turn: Deflationism and Axiomatic Truth" Matthew McKeon Michigan State University Follow this

More information

BOOK REVIEWS. Duke University. The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVII, No. 1 (January 1988)

BOOK REVIEWS. Duke University. The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVII, No. 1 (January 1988) manner that provokes the student into careful and critical thought on these issues, then this book certainly gets that job done. On the other hand, one likes to think (imagine or hope) that the very best

More information

Philosophy of Mathematics Nominalism

Philosophy of Mathematics Nominalism Philosophy of Mathematics Nominalism Owen Griffiths oeg21@cam.ac.uk Churchill and Newnham, Cambridge 8/11/18 Last week Ante rem structuralism accepts mathematical structures as Platonic universals. We

More information

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27)

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27) How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol 3 1986, 19-27) John Collier Department of Philosophy Rice University November 21, 1986 Putnam's writings on realism(1) have

More information

TRUTH IN MATHEMATICS. H.G. Dales and G. Oliveri (eds.) (Clarendon: Oxford. 1998, pp. xv, 376, ISBN X) Reviewed by Mark Colyvan

TRUTH IN MATHEMATICS. H.G. Dales and G. Oliveri (eds.) (Clarendon: Oxford. 1998, pp. xv, 376, ISBN X) Reviewed by Mark Colyvan TRUTH IN MATHEMATICS H.G. Dales and G. Oliveri (eds.) (Clarendon: Oxford. 1998, pp. xv, 376, ISBN 0-19-851476-X) Reviewed by Mark Colyvan The question of truth in mathematics has puzzled mathematicians

More information

prohibition, moral commitment and other normative matters. Although often described as a branch

prohibition, moral commitment and other normative matters. Although often described as a branch Logic, deontic. The study of principles of reasoning pertaining to obligation, permission, prohibition, moral commitment and other normative matters. Although often described as a branch of logic, deontic

More information

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI? Diametros nr 28 (czerwiec 2011): 1-7 WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI? Pierre Baumann In Naming and Necessity (1980), Kripke stressed the importance of distinguishing three different pairs of notions:

More information

On Possibly Nonexistent Propositions

On Possibly Nonexistent Propositions Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXXXV No. 3, November 2012 Ó 2012 Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LLC On Possibly Nonexistent Propositions

More information

Philosophy 125 Day 21: Overview

Philosophy 125 Day 21: Overview Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 1 Philosophy 125 Day 21: Overview 1st Papers/SQ s to be returned this week (stay tuned... ) Vanessa s handout on Realism about propositions to be posted Second papers/s.q.

More information