Visualization of Hans Kelsen s Pure Theory of Law

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Visualization of Hans Kelsen s Pure Theory of Law"

Transcription

1 Visualization of Hans Kelsen s Pure Theory of Law Vytautas Čyras Vilnius University Vytautas.Cyras@mif.vu.lt Friedrich Lachmayer University of Innsbruck Friedrich.Lachmayer@uibk.ac.at Guido Tsuno Chuo University Guido.Tsuno@mac.com Abstract. Hans Kelsen s Pure Theory of Law is the most prominent and influential legal theory for continental law systems. Kelsen s book contains only text neither logical notation nor pictures. Despite of this, an impression is that Hans Kelsen himself had very clear imagination. In our contribution we make an attempt to start visualizations of his theoretical models. This is important for legal informatics. Explicit visualizations of the structures of law and their theoretical representations are important for the development of legal ontologies. In addition to theoretical importance, visualizations contribute to understanding the law which is expressed in nontextual mode. In particular, legal machines take non-textual effect in legal situations. Kelsen created a paradigm of an up-to-date legal theory so that the visualizations of his ideas bring out an interesting way to understand the pure theory of law. Visualizations proposed in this paper aim at cognition and hence serve as models. Keywords. Legal visualization. Legal informatics. Interpretation of legal terms. Is and ought. Soft visualization. 1. Introduction AI & Law attempts to formalise law, produce logical structures of law and consequently make use of computers. Applying formal notations is a big part of the mainstream. This can be demonstrated by an increased number of JURIX 1 annual conference papers which make use of formal notations. Often formal notations relate to details only. This is because textual systems of law contain details that can be brought out adequately and precisely. On the other hand, on a purely theoretical level the need for contexts can rise, in particular, for the context of legal theory. Here Hans Kelsen s Pure Theory of Law can be considered as a theory on the background. In this respect a connection between the Pure Theory and AI & Law is provided. Hajime Yoshino also concerns Kelsen deliberately. When it comes to visualizations, besides automatic visualizations, see e.g. (Täks et al. 2011), there are inherently intuitive visualizations. Hence, strong visualizations come alongside weak visualizations. Both have their functions. A problem of visualizations is that their syntax is not uniformed. However, this gives the advantage of freedom in shaping. Visualizations can make the context increasingly obvious. This is important to bring AI & Law into action. Visualizations can serve as maps for the orientation in textual landscapes of law. Thus the benefits of AI use are increased. 1 The foundation for legal knowledge based systems; see 1

2 Hans Kelsen is one of the most studied legal philosophers. His texts are of great linguistic and intellectual intensity and combined with a very clear pre-textual imagination. Reading Kelsen is a must during the studies of law. However his imagination is not easy to grasp from the first reading. A layperson may also wish to find a concise conceptual model of law. Legal informatics needs models in a form which is used for knowledge representation in informatics. Visualization is a middle way to graphical models. This paper divided into several parts. Section 2 is devoted to the significance of the Pure Theory of Law in the historical formation, namely, taking over from the natural law. Section 3 distinguishes between the Is (Sein) and Ought (Sollen) realms. Section 4 describes different kinds interpretations of facts, legal texts (content), and legal acts. Section 5 is devoted to construction and Section 6 to purification. 2. Historical position Kelsen wrote two editions of the Pure Theory of Law: the first edition 1934 and the second A key feature of the Pure Theory is a paradigm change of legal theory and proposing a new juridical methodology. Kelsen introduced new concepts and terms, in particular, norm, basic norm, the hierarchy of norms, legal act, etc. Kelsen stopped the scientific discussion and took over from the natural law doctrine: The denial of the duality of Is and Ought implicit in the concepts of entelechy and practical reason is an essential element of the doctrine of Natural Law (Kelsen II; p. 70). Here we recall René Marcic (1971) as one of the last important thinkers of natural law. Legal logic and legal informatics succeeded in the research. A scientific mainstream after Kelsen was the legal logic invented by Georg Henrik von Wright with his article on deontic logic (1951). Other important exponents of this direction are Ilmar Tammelo, Ota Weinberger, Jürgen Rödig and Hajime Yoshino. Since 1970 s, legal informatics exponents are Herbert Fiedler, Leo Reisinger, Alfred Schramm, Erich Schweighofer, Roland Traunmüller, Maria Wimmer, just to mention a few. To characterize Kelsen s position, we invoke Stanley L. Paulson s formulation on resolving the antinony between the reductive thesis and the normativity thesis. In the introduction to 1992 translation of Reine Rechtslehre first edition 1934, Paulson expresses a view of how Kelsen distinguishes his own position from those of the tradition (Kelsen 1992, p. xxviii): (i) Is the normativity thesis derivable from the morality thesis? The tradition: yes. Kelsen: yes. (ii) Turning the question around, is the morality thesis derivable from the normativity thesis? The tradition: yes. Kelsen: no. (iii) Is the separability thesis derivable from the reductive thesis? The tradition: yes. Kelsen: yes. (iv) Turning the question around, is the reductive thesis derivable from the separability thesis? The tradition: yes. Kelsen: no. Paulson finds that Kelsen s answers to questions (ii) and (iv) suggest the hypotheses which he begins the normativity thesis without the morality thesis, and the separability thesis without the reductive thesis. We can symbolize this: NT\MT ST\RT; see Fig. 1. 2

3 Law and fact Law and morality Morality thesis, MT (inseparability of law and morality) Separability thesis, ST (separability of law and morality) no ativity thesis, NT (separability of law and fact) Natural law theory no Kelsen s Pure Theory of Law: NT\MT ST\RT Reductive thesis, RT (inseparability of law and fact) Empirico-positivist theory of law Figure 1. Resolving the antimony. Adapted from Paulson s introduction (Kelsen 1992, p. xxvi, xxviii-xxix). 3. Is and Ought Kelsen uses a categorical distinction between Is and Ought; see (Kelsen 1967, 3ff.): An ought cannot be reduced to an Is, or an Is to an Ought; and so an Is cannot be inferred from an Ought, or an Ought from an Is. (Kelsen I; p. 58) The duality of Is and Ought coincides with that of reality and value/ Thus no value can be derived from reality, and no reality from value. (Kelsen I; p. 61) The Is realm is associated with causality and the Ought with imputation. The irreducible Is-Ought duality corresponds to a very old mythical and religious duality between the Earth and Heaven, in other words, nature and spirit. In Fig. 2 we visualize the Is with a horizontal plane and the Ought with a vertical one. Is/Ought terminology was used already by Pufendorf; see his impositio. Pure Theory of Law as theory aims at cognition and therefore appears on a metalevel (Kelsen 1967, 1). Other elements such as the system of terms form a modal indifferent substratum and appear on the metalevel, too. System of terms: thesaurus, taxonomies, ontologies Metalevel Pure Theory of Law Rules Stage Ought (Sollen) legal meaning (Sinn) E.g. laws, decisions, etc. Is (Sein) E.g. papers, verbal formulations, etc. Content formulations in words, etc. Figure 2. Distinguishing between the Is and Ought worlds. The realm of Is is the primary layer for the actors actions. It can be visualized with the stage metaphor. Not only persons are among the actors but also requisites, for instance, things and, moreover, the actual substrates of speech acts and legal acts such as the paper of statutes and judgments. Verbal formulations are assigned to the Is even in the case the speech content is normative. The verbal formulations of Ought the content are 3

4 distinguished from the legal Ought that has a specific legal meaning (sense, Sinn, Deutung, rechtliche Bedeutung). The next layer, that of rules, is the realm of Ought. It is visualized vertically. According to Kelsen it deals with the legal meaning, namely, a specific legal significance. The Ought comes up to the actual substrate, the Is. Legal acts of the laws, judgments, the private law, e.g. private contracts, etc. constitute the Ought as a regulative background of the Is stage. Material artefacts such as paper documents and verbal formulations appear in the Is world. Their legal meaning appears in Ought. The Is world is factual it comprises facts, for example, the existence of a certain instance of table. The Ought is connected with culture. The notion of table appears in Ought. Pure Theory of Law comes up as next layer and namely as a scientific descriptive metalayer above law, the sense sphere of Ought. The legal science shall be descriptive in principle to remain pure. But the Pure Theory of Law, though admittedly on the top layer, also contains prescriptive elements, namely, the command to legal science to include only descriptive value-free sentences. Kelsen spoke (1991, 16II) about modally indifferent substrate (modal indifferentes Substrat) that constitutes a system of terms built of terms contained in law. Continuing these beginnings, one can arrive to the modern system of terms that comprises thesaurus, taxonomies and ontologies. Science has reached in Kelsen a historical peak, however did not leave standing and in multiple phases distinctively developed further. Ontologies can be viewed as the most modern development of the system of legal terms; see e.g. (Casellas 2008). Causality and imputation. Kelsen devotes separate chapters to explain the distinction; see e.g. (1991, ch. 7). Imputation links a condition and a sanction brought about by a general moral or legal norm. Computer scientists are accustomed to the axiomatic method. Therefore they need special efforts to comprehend when they encounter a principle which is different from the principle of causality expressed in the natural laws formulated by the natural sciences. These are two different, but analogous functional connections: The difference between the two is this: imputation (i.e. the relation between a certain behavior as condition and a sanction as consequence, described by a moral or legal law) is produced by an act of will whose meaning is a norm, while causality (i.e. the relation between cause and effects described by a natural law) is independent of any such intervention. (Kelsen 1991, ch. 7 p. 24) Central and peripheral imputation. Formulating the concept reveals subtleties. Paulson writes about the objectivity motif in Kelsen s Pure Theory of Law and calls Kelsen s thesis the nomological normativity thesis. Kelsen distinguishes between central imputation and peripheral imputation: [Central imputation] is an entirely different operation from the peripheral imputation mentioned earlier, where a material fact is connected to another material fact within the system, that is, where two material facts are linked together in the reconstructed legal norm. (Kelsen 1992, p. 50-1) Paulson proposes the following formulation of peripheral imputation: Formulation II. If an act of a certain type takes place (and if ) then that act is treated as liability ascribing. (Paulson 2011, p. 18) Paulson analyses imputing liability to the act rather to the actor and notes that the character of the liable party actor, surrogate, or collective body is a contingent factor, a question of legal policy, not legal science. 4

5 In any case it is precisely this necessary relation between act and liability that represents the core of what I am calling Kelsen s nomological normativity thesis. The relation is nomological in being necessary or law-like, and it is normative in being non-causal. (Paulson 2011, p. 19) Paulson concludes: Where the antecedent condition obtains, this marks the imputation of liability to the act, a necessary relation. Where the ascription of liability to a person is made, this marks a change in that person s legal position. The change, Kelsen insists, is a normative change, not a causal change. (Paulson 2011, p. 21) No long series of imputation. A difference of causality and imputation is that by the very nature of causality the chain of cause and effect is endless in both directions. Contrary, [t]he imputation series does not have an unlimited number of members as the causal series does: basically it has only two members. (Kelsen 1991, ch. 7 p. 24) Hence a network of causes and effects can be depicted as a graph with two types of edges, denoting causality and imputation (Fig. 2a). Long series of causality may appear, but not those of imputation. Legend: Cause Effect material fact, state of affairs Legal condition Legal consequence, the legal position Figure 2a. A network of causalities (thin edges) and imputations (thick). Different network patterns could be employed to formalise distinguished theories of causality, fault and legal responsibility such as sine qua non and necessary and sufficient condition (Hart & Honoré 1985). 4. Interpretations This section concerns two groups of concepts: (a) facts, norms and texts, and (b) construction and deconstruction. Kelsen describes five (3+2) different interpretations regarding facts, norms and legal texts. We divide these interpretations into two groups (3+1): 1. The interpretation of factual reality (Is, Sein). Facts are the entities of the Is-world and are transformed into the legal meaning (sense, Sinn; Ought, Sollen); 2. The interpretation of legal texts (content). Kelsen describes the interpretation of the content of legal texts and the transformation in a new version of textual understanding. This is associated with the procedure of subsumption; 3. The interpretation of legal acts (Rechtsakte). This is about the interpretation of normative sources (normative texts) and their transformation into valid legal acts (e.g. laws). The basic norm is regarded in this context. In this paper we express the main argument against the Kelsen s basic norm concept: such a (scientific) basic norm delegates a scientific qualification but no legal validity; 4. Construction. 5

6 4.1. The Interpretation of Factual Reality A norm (that is from the Ought world) functions as a scheme of interpretation of a fact (from the Is world): The external fact whose objective meaning is a legal or illegal act is always an event that can be perceived by the senses. However, this event as such, as an element of nature, is not an object of legal cognition. What turns this event into a legal or illegal act is not its physical existence, but the objective meaning resulting from its interpretation. The specifically legal meaning of this act is derived from a norm whose content refers to the act; this norm confers legal meaning to the act. (Kelsen 1967, 4a p. 3) Hence institutional facts are interpreted according to the Ought (Fig. 3). The interpretation is erected on both the Is and Ought. Here Pufendorf s impositio can be recalled. See also (MacCormick & Weinberger 1992, p ) for an institutional theory of facts. Modally indifferent substrate Terms Situation, facts Legal meaning (sense, Sinn ) Interpretation Reaction Interpretation scheme Figure 3. The interpretation of the factual reality. It should be noted that a paper document of a draft law (bill) as such has no meaning. A legal meaning is obtained when it is legitimated, e.g. by a parliamentary procedure. The interpretation above has to be supplemented with the imposition of meaning; see Fig. 4. 6

7 Basic norm Legal norm Objective meaning (Sinn) Not interpreted facts Subjectively interpreted facts Subjective interpretation (Deutung) Subjective meaning (Sinn) Objectively interpreted facts Figure 4. Imposing the meaning to facts. Firstly, facts, i.e. not interpreted facts, appear on the Is-stage. Secondly, subjectively interpreted facts on the Is stage are subject to subjective meaning (Sinn). Subjective interpretation (Deutung) is on the mind layer. Thirdly, objective interpreted facts on the Is-stage have objective legal meaning (Sinn) with respect to a legal norm in the Ought world: is the meaning of an act by which a certain behaviour is commanded, permitted or authorized. (Kelsen 1967, 4b p. 5) The command of a gangster has the same subjective meaning as the command of an income-tax official. But only the command of the official, not of the gangster, has the meaning of a valid norm, binding upon the addressed individual. (Kelsen 1967, 4b p. 8) Kelsen explains the subjective and objective meaning of the act of commanding (we illustrate this in Fig. 4a): If the command is not empowered, then this is merely the subjective meaning of the act of commanding, that is, it is the meaning the act of commanding has from the point of view of the commander and not from the point of view of the addressee or any third party. Only an empowered command also has the objective meaning of Ought, that is, only an empowered command is a norm binding on the addressee, obligating him to act in the prescribed way. (Kelsen 1991, ch. 8.v p. 27) 7

8 Act of commanding No legal meaning, no norm Act of commanding Legal meaning Commander Addressee Commander Addressee Third party (a) (b) Figure 4a. The subjective (a) and objective (b) meaning of the act of commanding. Legal norms conform to the basic norm: Such a presupposition, establishing the objective validity of the norms of a moral or legal order, will here be called a basic norm (Grundnorm) (cf. 34a). Therefore, the objective validity of a norm which is the subjective meaning of an act of will that men ought to behave in a certain way, does not follow from the factual act, that is to say, from an is, but again from a norm authorizing this act, that is to say, from an ought. (Kelsen 1967, 4b p. 8-9) The basic norm concept appears at the metalevel, the Pure Theory of Law. Identity of two modally indifferent substrates. Kelsen (1991) devotes Subsection 16II the idea of behaviour which agrees with a norm. The idea is expressed in the title: Identity of the modally indifferent substrate of the behaviour decreed to be obligatory in the norm with the modally indifferent substrate of the behaviour existing in reality (p. 60). Kelsen illustrates with the fact A pays his gambling debts and the norm A ought to pay his gambling debts. The content of the Is and the content of the Ought is the modally indifferent substrate payinggambling-debts. It is invested both with the mode of Is and the mode of Ought. This explains a formalisation that a behaviour existing in reality, B F, agrees with the behaviour B N in the norm. The answer: the identity relationship between two modally indifferent substrates. We can formally represent this B F = B N ; see Fig. 4b. Ought Behaviour B N Modally indifferent substrate Identity. The relationship being-in-accordance-with-duty Fact Is Behaviour B F Modally indifferent substrate Figure 4b. Behaviour which agrees with a norm is formalised with the identity B F = B N. 8

9 Subsumption procedure. To model the subsumption procedure, we can apply conceptual modelling formalisms which are used in computer science, object-oriented analysis and systems development, namely, the general relationships is-a, instance-of and part-of. Suppose the fact that my-door is open and the norm N The doors ought to be closed. The norm can be formalised with the following modus ponens rule: if x is an instance of Door, then x ought to be closed. Formally, x x Door O closed(x), where O is the deontic operator and closed a predicate. The situation (fact) with the instance my-door is from the Is world. In order to interpret it, the norm (with the door concept Door) from the Ought world has to be chosen. Then my-door is matched with Door, formally match(my-door, Door). This can be simplified and expressed with a truth statement instance-of(mydoor, Door) or my-door Door. This truth statement is from the Is world. A graphical notation is shown in Fig 5. A duty which is conferred on me, to close my-door, is from Ought. In the Is world I can decide to leave my-door open thus violating the norm. Door instance-of my-door Figure 5. Graphical notation of the instance-of relationship, instance-of(my-door, Door) or my-door Door. This visualizes that my-door (from the Is world) is matched with the Door concept within N which is from Ought The Interpretation of Legal Texts The second interpretation is relative to the classical interpretation of the content of legal texts. The subsumption procedure is concerned. The terms which are found in the legal text appear on the metalevel. The terms are modally indifferent substrate (Fig. 6). On the function of application of law, adjudication by a court, see e.g. (Kelsen 1967, 35 g). 9

10 System of terms: thesaurus, taxonomies, ontologies Terms Modally indifferent substrate Legal text Terms Interpretation of the content,,... Situation, facts Meaning (sense, Sinn ) } Subsumption Decision Figure 6. The interpretation of legal texts The Interpretation of Legal Acts (Rechtsakte) Legal acts are interpreted with respect to the basic norm (Fig. 7). A thin arrow represents a transition from a normative text, a substrate that is in the Is world, to its legal meaning, that is in the Ought. Kelsen speaks about different degrees of the relation called correspondence between two norms and the validity of a lower norm which founded on the validity of a higher norm: A positive moral or legal order can never conflict with its Basic. A conflict is always possible between Natural Law and a positive moral or legal order. (Kelsen 1991, ch. 59.ii p. 259). The authors of this paper maintain that Kelsen views the basic norm as a scientific product that has scientific meaning but no normative validity. Thus the main argument against Kelsen s basic norm concept is that such (scientific) basic norms can only delegate a scientific qualification but no legal validity. We think that this is a problem a drawback of the Pure Theory. The scientific significance of the basic norm comes together with normative validity. 10

11 Is Ought Basic norm concept Substrate: normative text Meaning: valid legal act Interpretation scheme Hypothesis Figure 7. The interpretation of legal acts. On the basic norm. Speaking about validity, Kelsen provides the example of the basic norm of Christian morality and holds that only a norm can be the reason for the validity of another norm : It is a basic norm, because nothing further can be asked about the reason for its validity, since it is not a posited norm but a presupposed norm. (Kelsen 1991, ch. 59.i.C p. 255) Kelsen holds that the Basic is not a positive norm, but a merely thought norm (i.e. a fictitious norm), the meaning of a merely fictitious, and not real, act of will : The cognitive goal of the Basic is to ground the validity of the norms forming a positive moral or legal order, that is, to interpret the subjective meaning of the norm-positing acts as their objective meaning (i.e. as valid norms) and to interpret the relevant acts as norm-positing acts. This goal can be attained only by means of a fiction. (Kelsen 1991, ch. 59.i.D p. 256) On validity. Niklas Luhmann devotes a separate chapter to the concept of validity. He notes that validity is not a norm and adds: If one follows Kelsen the question is most often asked the other way around: what is the special status of a basic norm in relation to validity extra-legal, hypothetical, moral? (Luhmann 2004, p. 126) On the basic norm and the transcendental argument see Stanley L. Paulson: The distinction between is and ought implies altogether separate tracks for establishing, respectively, the truth of empirical claims and, inter alia, the validity of legal norms. Tying the distinction between is and ought to the normativity thesis in the manner of methodological dualism is not to deny the familiar distinction between is and ought associated with the separability thesis. Where the distinction is invoked on behalf of the normativity thesis, ought flags legal norms, and is gives expression to facts; where it is invoked on behalf of the separability thesis, ought flags norms of morality, and is gives expression to valid, i.e. existing, legal norms. (Kelsen 1992, p. xxxii) 5. Construction Next is the structural interpretation involving scientific notions where Kelsen was very creative. 11

12 5.1. Double-norm (Doppel-) Kelsen makes a transition from the hypothetical norm concept to categorical norm; see (Kelsen 1967, 25) and Fig. 8. Hypothetical norm Categorical norm Condition Reaction To Do if then if then it is commanded to commanded Figure 8. Hypothetical and categorical norms. The difference is not so easy to grasp and formalise in terms of (i) imputation and (ii) formal logic. Therefore Kelsen devotes chapter 5 to explain this: The difference between categorical and hypothethical norms is the difference between norms which decree that a certain behavior is obligatory unconditionally and those which decree that a certain behavior is obligatory only under certain conditions. (Kelsen 1991, ch. 5 p. 19) Prosecutor A can demand that judge B punish C, who (in A s opinion) committed theft; but the judge, who is willing to punish thieves, can reject the prosecutor s demand because the ought-to-punish-c is valid for the judge only if it his opinion that C has committed theft, and he is of the opinion that he has not. He can decide: C is not to be punished. What is lacking in this case is the condition for the oughtto-punish. (Kelsen 1991, ch. 5 p. 21) Kelsen summarizes: All norms are valid merely conditionally. (1991, p. 21) To explain the difference, Manfred Moritz s words are used: If there is a conditional imperative If it rains, go home!, we can express the parallel judgment for instance in the following way: It is commanded to go home if it rains. It should not be formulated so as to say It it rains, it is commanded to go home. The judgment which is parallel to a conditional imperative does not state under which conditions the action is commanded, but under which conditions the action ought to be performed. (Kelsen 1991, note 24 p. 290) Kelsen adds: The imperative is conditional, not because it is subject to a condition [bedingt], but because it sets a condition [bedingend]. (p. 290) Other norm concepts can also be proposed, see e.g. that of Luhmann (Fig. 9). Condition Reaction Finality Figure 9. Another concept of norm (Luhmann 2004). 12

13 In the chapter devoted to primary and secondary norms, Kelsen views a general legal norm as a combination of them, a double norm: [A] combination of two norms one of which decrees to be obligatory a certain behavior of the legal subject, and the other the performance of a specific coercive act on the part of the legal organ in the event of a violation of the first norm. I have called the latter norm the primary norm, and the former the secondary norm. (Kelsen 1991, ch. 15 p. 56) We show this in Fig. 9a. Double general norm E.g. Secondary norm O A People are to refrain from committing theft; Primary norm if A then O sanction if a court finds that someone has committed theft, this judge is to posit an individual norm which decrees that this person is to be imprisoned Figure 9a. A double norm (Doppel-) is a combination of the secondary and the primary norm Hierarchy of s This section presents a bit more modern version of what Kelsen wrote. Constitution, law, statute and decision form a hierarchy; see (Kelsen 1967, part V, especially 35). This expresses governing by one state; see Fig. 10. Kelsen speaks about a hierarchical structure of norms: whose highest level is the constitution whose validity is founded on the presupposed Basic, and whose lowest level is made of the individual norms decreeing particular concrete behavior to be obligatory. (Kelsen 1991, ch. 59.i.F p. 258) EU primary law and EU secondary law form another hierarchy with the international law being above. Private treaty appears on the bottom. Basic norm is above all and also in the mind. 13

14 Basic norm International law EU primary law Constitution EU secondary law Law Statute Decision Private treaty Figure 10. A hierarchical structure of norms Monism The legal order exclusively consists of norms (Fig. 11). Legal definitions are part of other norms. Definition (a) (b) Figure 11. (a) The legal order consists of norms. (b) Legal definitions are part of norms. Another concept is that there are other legal elements such as indicative legal definitions, legal signs, etc. (Fig. 12). Legal norm Indicative legal sentence Legal sign Figure 12. Another concept of the legal order: apart from norms there are other elements. A formalisation of the legal order with one notion, the norm, makes the model very pure. This is useful to speak on a high philosophical level. However, on lower levels of discourse, more notions would be helpful. For example, legal theory distinguishes between norms to-do, norms to-be (see e.g. Sartor), etc. Other classifications of norms are also possible. In mathematics a formal theory can be formalised with a small number of axioms. Adding an axiom makes the theory more specific and deleting more abstract. 14

15 6. Purification a Deconstruction Kelsen s approach to purification rests on a critical interpretation of other theories. This is a deconstruction of the traditional legal theory. Personality is a traditional key concept. In the Pure Theory of Law a person is only a quantity of rights and duties (Fig. 13). Traditional concepts of personality PTL: person as a quantity of rights and duties Person Person Figure 13. A purification of the personality concept. A traditional concept of institution comprises state, etc. In the Pure Theory of Law, institutions are only sets of norms (Fig. 14). Therefore Kelsen devotes a separate chapter VI to law and state (1967, 36 ff. esp. 41b). Traditional concepts of institutions PTL: institutions as norms Entities like state Figure 14. A purification of the institution concept. An effect of the Pure Theory of Law is also that Kelsen put a new interpretation on traditional terms. State and person are examples where this arises. This is not new in the history of jurisprudence. Both happen: on the one hand adoption and, on the other, re-interpretation of previous terms and creating completely new terms. Guido Tsuno investigates these issues at Chuo University in Tokyo within the project about legal lexicon; see (Tsuno 2011). 7. Apotheosis Kelsen s work entails a paradox. He tried to deconstruct and unmask the former juridical system especially the personification of the state with a paternal face. However, on the other hand he tried to make a personification of his own theory an apotheosis with a female virgin image named Pure Theory of Law (Fig. 15). There are some rhetorical indications in this direction (Lachmayer 1984). 15

16 Pure Theory of Law Personification of jurisprudence Figure 15. A personification of Kelsen s theory an apotheosis with a virgin female image. 8. Conclusions The centerpiece of PTL is concerned in this paper and margins are set aside. Our thesis is that PTL deals with the middle layer. It can also be shown that legal logic is assigned to the higher layer of abstraction, PTL to the middle one, and individual decisions and laws to the lower layer. A relation to legal informatics is also an issue. Ontologies are assigned to the higher layer. Kelsen s works are not written as textbooks for freshmen. To achieve deep understanding, studies of law could help. It is also advised to read other books on legal theory. We hope that the paper can reach beyond legal education. References 1. Casellas N. (2008) Modelling legal knowledge through ontologies. OPJK: the ontology of professional judicial knowledge. PhD thesis, Autonomous University of Barcelona, 2. Čyras V., Lachmayer F., Tsuno G. (2011) Visualization of Hans Kelsen s Pure Theory of Law. Yoshino H., Araszkiewicz M., Walker V.R. (eds.), Proceedings of the Fundamental Concepts and the Systematization of Law, Workshop at JURIX 2011, Vienna, pp Hart H. L. A.; Honoré, Tony (1985) Causation in the law. 2nd ed. Clarendon Press, Oxford. 4. Kelsen H. (2000) Reine Rechtslehre, 2. Auflage. Deuticke, Wien (1960); Verlag Österreich, Wien. 5. Kelsen H. (1967) Pure theory of law. 2 nd ed., Max Knight, trans. University of California Press, Berkeley. 6. Kelsen H. (1992) Introduction to the problems of legal theory. A translation of the First Edition of the Reine Rechtslehre or Pure Theory of Law. Bonnie Litschewski Paulson and Stanley L. Paulson trans. Clarendon Press, Oxford, reprinted Kelsen H. (1991) General Theory of s. Michael Hartney, trans. Clarendon Press, Oxford. 8. Lachmayer F. (1984) No Junsui Hogaku ni okeru Shujiteki Seibun [in Japanese] (Rhetorical Components in the Pure Theory of Hans Kelsen), in: Ho no Riron (Legal Theory), vol. 4, pp , Hiroshi Takahashi trans. 9. Luhmann N. (2004) Law as a social system. Oxford University Press. Klaus A. Ziegert trans. 10. MacCormick N., Weinberger O. (1992) An institutional theory of law: new approaches to legal positivism. D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland. 11. Marcic R. (1971) The right to resist as an attribute of human dignity. University of Sydney, Faculty of Law, Dept. of Jurisprudence and International Law, Institute for Advanced Studies in Jurisprudence, Sydney. 16

17 12. Marcic R., Tammelo I. (1989) Naturrecht und Gerechtigkeit, Eine Einführung in die Grundprobleme [in German] (Natural Law and Justice, An Introduction to Fundamental Problems). Series: Rechts-, Sozial- und Wirtschaftsphilosophie, vol. 9, Peter Lang Publishers, Frankfurt/M. 13. Paulson S. L. (2011) A prelude to Hans Kelsen s concept of law. In: Hajime Yoshino, Michał Araszkiewicz, Vern R. Walker (eds.) Proceedings of the Fundamental Concepts and the Systematization of Law Workshop at JURIX 2011 in Vienna. 14. Täks E., Võhandu L., Lohk A., Liiv I. (2011) An experiment to find deep structure of Estonian legislation, in: Legal Knowledge and Information Systems, JURIX 2011: The Twenty-Fourth Annual Conference, K. M. Atkinson (ed.), IOS Press, pp Tsuno G. (2011) Repertorium Aureum, Rechtslexika im Geltungsbereich des Ius Commune und im 19. Jahrhundert [in German] (Legal Lexicon in the Scope of Ius Commune in the 19th Century). Vico Verlag, Frankfurt/M. 16. von Wright G. H. (1951) Deontic logic. Mind, New Series, vol. 60, no 237 (Jan. 1951) pp Yoshino, H. (2011) The systematization of law in terms of the validity. Proceedings of the Thirteenth International Conference on Artificial Intelligence and Law (ICAIL), AMC, Baltimore, pp

Visualization of Hans Kelsen s Pure Theory of Law

Visualization of Hans Kelsen s Pure Theory of Law Visualization of Hans Kelsen s Pure Theory of Law Vytautas Čyras Vilnius University Vytautas.Cyras@mif.vu.lt http://www.mif.vu.lt/~cyras/ Friedrich Lachmayer University of Innsbruck Friedrich.Lachmayer@uibk.ac.at

More information

Legal positivism represents a view about the nature of law. It states that

Legal positivism represents a view about the nature of law. It states that Legal Positivism A N I NTRODUCTION Polycarp Ikuenobe Legal positivism represents a view about the nature of law. It states that there is no necessary or conceptual connection between law and morality and

More information

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Version 1.1 Richard Baron 2 October 2016 1 Contents 1 Introduction 3 1.1 Availability and licence............ 3 2 Definitions of key terms 4 3

More information

Can Kelsen's Legal Positivism Account for International Regime Change? Christoforos Ioannidis

Can Kelsen's Legal Positivism Account for International Regime Change? Christoforos Ioannidis Can Kelsen's Legal Positivism Account for International Regime Change? by Christoforos Ioannidis A Thesis Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Master of Arts Approved July

More information

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp.

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp. 330 Interpretation and Legal Theory Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp. Reviewed by Lawrence E. Thacker* Interpretation may be defined roughly as the process of determining the meaning

More information

Hans Kelsen. 1. Kelsen s life ( )

Hans Kelsen. 1. Kelsen s life ( ) Hans Kelsen Interview at Kelsen Tours Ltd (The following exchange takes place at the office of a travel agent soon after a democratic government of a holiday island country has been ousted by a military

More information

Does law have to be effective in order for it to be valid?

Does law have to be effective in order for it to be valid? University of Birmingham Birmingham Law School Jurisprudence 2007-08 Assessed Essay (Second Round) Does law have to be effective in order for it to be valid? It is important to consider the terms valid

More information

THE PURE THEORY OF LAW

THE PURE THEORY OF LAW THE PURE THEORY OF LAW Hans Kelsen Introduction, Polycarp Ikuenobe THE GERMAN LEGAL THEORIST AND philosopher Hans Kelsen provides a positivist account of law. He does this by employing the method of what

More information

Contrary to Duty Obligations A Study in Legal Ontology

Contrary to Duty Obligations A Study in Legal Ontology 89 Contrary to Duty Obligations A Study in Legal Ontology Jaap Hage Department of Metajuridica Faculty of Law Universiteit Maastricht The Netherlands jaap.hage@metajur.unimaas.nl Abstract.In this paper

More information

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Chapter 98 Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Lars Leeten Universität Hildesheim Practical thinking is a tricky business. Its aim will never be fulfilled unless influence on practical

More information

Meaning, Logic, and the Systematization of Law: Kelsen, Wittgenstein and Information Architecture

Meaning, Logic, and the Systematization of Law: Kelsen, Wittgenstein and Information Architecture Meaning, Logic, and the Systematization of Law: Kelsen, Wittgenstein and Information Architecture Vern R. Walker Maurice A. Deane School of Law at Hofstra University Vern.R.Walker@Hofstra.edu http://people.hofstra.edu/vern_r_walker/

More information

prohibition, moral commitment and other normative matters. Although often described as a branch

prohibition, moral commitment and other normative matters. Although often described as a branch Logic, deontic. The study of principles of reasoning pertaining to obligation, permission, prohibition, moral commitment and other normative matters. Although often described as a branch of logic, deontic

More information

Meaning and Metameaning as Entities: Content (Is) and Institutional Meaning (Ought)

Meaning and Metameaning as Entities: Content (Is) and Institutional Meaning (Ought) Vytautas Čyras / Friedrich Lachmayer Meaning and Metameaning as Entities: Content (Is) and Institutional Meaning (Ought) Die Autoren befassen sich mit der «Bedeutung der Bedeutung». 1923 wurde dieses Thema

More information

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS SECOND SECTION by Immanuel Kant TRANSITION FROM POPULAR MORAL PHILOSOPHY TO THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS... This principle, that humanity and generally every

More information

***** [KST : Knowledge Sharing Technology]

***** [KST : Knowledge Sharing Technology] Ontology A collation by paulquek Adapted from Barry Smith's draft @ http://ontology.buffalo.edu/smith/articles/ontology_pic.pdf Download PDF file http://ontology.buffalo.edu/smith/articles/ontology_pic.pdf

More information

Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh For Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh I Tim Maudlin s Truth and Paradox offers a theory of truth that arises from

More information

Informalizing Formal Logic

Informalizing Formal Logic Informalizing Formal Logic Antonis Kakas Department of Computer Science, University of Cyprus, Cyprus antonis@ucy.ac.cy Abstract. This paper discusses how the basic notions of formal logic can be expressed

More information

On The Logical Status of Dialectic (*) -Historical Development of the Argument in Japan- Shigeo Nagai Naoki Takato

On The Logical Status of Dialectic (*) -Historical Development of the Argument in Japan- Shigeo Nagai Naoki Takato On The Logical Status of Dialectic (*) -Historical Development of the Argument in Japan- Shigeo Nagai Naoki Takato 1 The term "logic" seems to be used in two different ways. One is in its narrow sense;

More information

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS John Watling Kant was an idealist. His idealism was in some ways, it is true, less extreme than that of Berkeley. He distinguished his own by calling

More information

THE NATURE OF NORMATIVITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC REBECCA V. MILLSOP S

THE NATURE OF NORMATIVITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC REBECCA V. MILLSOP S THE NATURE OF NORMATIVITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC REBECCA V. MILLSOP S I. INTRODUCTION Immanuel Kant claims that logic is constitutive of thought: without [the laws of logic] we would not think at

More information

Is and Ought Distinction in Legal Philosophy

Is and Ought Distinction in Legal Philosophy I Is and Ought Distinction in Legal Philosophy Wojciech Załuski The University of Krakow, Krakow, Poland Introduction The controversy over Is and Ought distinction appears in legal philosophy in two different

More information

Philosophy of Mathematics Nominalism

Philosophy of Mathematics Nominalism Philosophy of Mathematics Nominalism Owen Griffiths oeg21@cam.ac.uk Churchill and Newnham, Cambridge 8/11/18 Last week Ante rem structuralism accepts mathematical structures as Platonic universals. We

More information

ON CAUSAL AND CONSTRUCTIVE MODELLING OF BELIEF CHANGE

ON CAUSAL AND CONSTRUCTIVE MODELLING OF BELIEF CHANGE ON CAUSAL AND CONSTRUCTIVE MODELLING OF BELIEF CHANGE A. V. RAVISHANKAR SARMA Our life in various phases can be construed as involving continuous belief revision activity with a bundle of accepted beliefs,

More information

Kelsen's Pure Theory of Law

Kelsen's Pure Theory of Law The Catholic Lawyer Volume 26 Number 2 Volume 26, Spring 1981, Number 2 Article 4 September 2017 Kelsen's Pure Theory of Law Henry Cohen Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.stjohns.edu/tcl

More information

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem?

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem? 1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem? 1.1 What is conceptual analysis? In this book, I am going to defend the viability of conceptual analysis as a philosophical method. It therefore seems

More information

Chapter 2 Kelsen on Vaihinger

Chapter 2 Kelsen on Vaihinger Chapter 2 Kelsen on Vaihinger Christoph Kletzer Abstract This is a comment by the translator on the translation of Hans Kelsen s On the Theory of Juridic Fictions. With special consideration of Vaihinger

More information

Instrumental reasoning* John Broome

Instrumental reasoning* John Broome Instrumental reasoning* John Broome For: Rationality, Rules and Structure, edited by Julian Nida-Rümelin and Wolfgang Spohn, Kluwer. * This paper was written while I was a visiting fellow at the Swedish

More information

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview 1. Introduction 1.1. Formal deductive logic 1.1.0. Overview In this course we will study reasoning, but we will study only certain aspects of reasoning and study them only from one perspective. The special

More information

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire. KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON The law is reason unaffected by desire. Aristotle, Politics Book III (1287a32) THE BIG IDEAS TO MASTER Kantian formalism Kantian constructivism

More information

Some questions about Adams conditionals

Some questions about Adams conditionals Some questions about Adams conditionals PATRICK SUPPES I have liked, since it was first published, Ernest Adams book on conditionals (Adams, 1975). There is much about his probabilistic approach that is

More information

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable by Manoranjan Mallick and Vikram S. Sirola Abstract The paper attempts to delve into the distinction Wittgenstein makes between factual discourse and moral thoughts.

More information

10. The aim of a theory of law is to reduce chaos and multiplicity to unity. legal theory is science and not volition. It is knowledge of what the

10. The aim of a theory of law is to reduce chaos and multiplicity to unity. legal theory is science and not volition. It is knowledge of what the PURE THEORY OF LAW 1. The Pure theory of Law which is also known as Vienna School of Legal Thought was propounded by Hans Kelson, a professor in Vienna (Austria) University. 2. Though the first exposition

More information

INF5020 Philosophy of Information: Ontology

INF5020 Philosophy of Information: Ontology WEEK 3, LECTURE a INF5020 Philosophy of Information: Ontology M. Naci Akkøk, Fall 2004 Page 1 THIS SESSION The goal History: We first talked about computation, complexity and looked at several definitions

More information

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory Western University Scholarship@Western 2015 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2015 Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory David Hakim Western University, davidhakim266@gmail.com

More information

Legal Positivism: the Separation and Identification theses are true.

Legal Positivism: the Separation and Identification theses are true. PHL271 Handout 3: Hart on Legal Positivism 1 Legal Positivism Revisited HLA Hart was a highly sophisticated philosopher. His defence of legal positivism marked a watershed in 20 th Century philosophy of

More information

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY 1 CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY TORBEN SPAAK We have seen (in Section 3) that Hart objects to Austin s command theory of law, that it cannot account for the normativity of law, and that what is missing

More information

Cover Page. The handle holds various files of this Leiden University dissertation

Cover Page. The handle  holds various files of this Leiden University dissertation Cover Page The handle http://hdl.handle.net/1887/38607 holds various files of this Leiden University dissertation Author: Notermans, Mathijs Title: Recht en vrede bij Hans Kelsen : een herwaardering van

More information

PURE THEORY OF LAW - Legal Validity - Literature: A. Marmor, Philosophy of Law

PURE THEORY OF LAW - Legal Validity - Literature: A. Marmor, Philosophy of Law - Legal Validity - Literature: A. Marmor, Philosophy of Law explanation scientific method by which a phenomenon is interpreted by stating the circumstances, causes and purposes of its emergence why something

More information

Aboutness and Justification

Aboutness and Justification For a symposium on Imogen Dickie s book Fixing Reference to be published in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. Aboutness and Justification Dilip Ninan dilip.ninan@tufts.edu September 2016 Al believes

More information

What Happens When Wittgenstein Asks "What Happens When...?"

What Happens When Wittgenstein Asks What Happens When...? The Philosophical Forum Volume XXVIII. No. 3, Winter-Spring 1997 What Happens When Wittgenstein Asks "What Happens When...?" E.T. Gendlin University of Chicago Wittgenstein insisted that rules cannot govern

More information

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God Father Frederick C. Copleston (Jesuit Catholic priest) versus Bertrand Russell (agnostic philosopher) Copleston:

More information

Précis of Empiricism and Experience. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

Précis of Empiricism and Experience. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh Précis of Empiricism and Experience Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh My principal aim in the book is to understand the logical relationship of experience to knowledge. Say that I look out of my window

More information

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence Filo Sofija Nr 30 (2015/3), s. 239-246 ISSN 1642-3267 Jacek Wojtysiak John Paul II Catholic University of Lublin The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence Introduction The history of science

More information

Correct Beliefs as to What One Believes: A Note

Correct Beliefs as to What One Believes: A Note Correct Beliefs as to What One Believes: A Note Allan Gibbard Department of Philosophy University of Michigan, Ann Arbor A supplementary note to Chapter 4, Correct Belief of my Meaning and Normativity

More information

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice Daniele Porello danieleporello@gmail.com Institute for Logic, Language & Computation (ILLC) University of Amsterdam, Plantage Muidergracht 24

More information

Toward a Jurisprudential Theory of International Law: Directions for Future Thought

Toward a Jurisprudential Theory of International Law: Directions for Future Thought Loyola Marymount University and Loyola Law School Digital Commons at Loyola Marymount University and Loyola Law School Loyola of Los Angeles International and Comparative Law Review Law Reviews 1-1-1979

More information

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics? International Journal of Humanities and Social Science Invention ISSN (Online): 2319 7722, ISSN (Print): 2319 7714 Volume 3 Issue 11 ǁ November. 2014 ǁ PP.38-42 Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

More information

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module - 22 Lecture - 22 Kant The idea of Reason Soul, God

More information

out in his Three Dialogues and Principles of Human Knowledge, gives an argument specifically

out in his Three Dialogues and Principles of Human Knowledge, gives an argument specifically That Thing-I-Know-Not-What by [Perm #7903685] The philosopher George Berkeley, in part of his general thesis against materialism as laid out in his Three Dialogues and Principles of Human Knowledge, gives

More information

A Model of Decidable Introspective Reasoning with Quantifying-In

A Model of Decidable Introspective Reasoning with Quantifying-In A Model of Decidable Introspective Reasoning with Quantifying-In Gerhard Lakemeyer* Institut fur Informatik III Universitat Bonn Romerstr. 164 W-5300 Bonn 1, Germany e-mail: gerhard@uran.informatik.uni-bonn,de

More information

Mohammad Reza Vaez Shahrestani. University of Bonn

Mohammad Reza Vaez Shahrestani. University of Bonn Philosophy Study, November 2017, Vol. 7, No. 11, 595-600 doi: 10.17265/2159-5313/2017.11.002 D DAVID PUBLISHING Defending Davidson s Anti-skepticism Argument: A Reply to Otavio Bueno Mohammad Reza Vaez

More information

1/12. The A Paralogisms

1/12. The A Paralogisms 1/12 The A Paralogisms The character of the Paralogisms is described early in the chapter. Kant describes them as being syllogisms which contain no empirical premises and states that in them we conclude

More information

Copyright 2015 by KAD International All rights reserved. Published in the Ghana

Copyright 2015 by KAD International All rights reserved. Published in the Ghana Copyright 2015 by KAD International All rights reserved. Published in the Ghana http://kadint.net/our-journal.html The Problem of the Truth of the Counterfactual Conditionals in the Context of Modal Realism

More information

Systems in Legal and Moral Theory. Festschrift for Carlos E. Alchourrón and Eugenio Bulygin, Berlin, 1997.

Systems in Legal and Moral Theory. Festschrift for Carlos E. Alchourrón and Eugenio Bulygin, Berlin, 1997. Riccardo Guastini A Sceptical View on Legal Interpretation 1. Scepticism Defined By scepticism in the province of legal interpretation theories I mean the thesis according to which interpretive statements

More information

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER IX CHAPTER IX FORMAL CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER IX CHAPTER IX FORMAL CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE CHAPTER IX CHAPTER IX FORMAL CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE Section 1. A Mediate Inference is a proposition that depends for proof upon two or more other propositions, so connected together by one or

More information

Kant and his Successors

Kant and his Successors Kant and his Successors G. J. Mattey Winter, 2011 / Philosophy 151 The Sorry State of Metaphysics Kant s Critique of Pure Reason (1781) was an attempt to put metaphysics on a scientific basis. Metaphysics

More information

NORMATIVITY WITHOUT NORMATIVISM 1

NORMATIVITY WITHOUT NORMATIVISM 1 FORO DE DEBATE / DEBATE FORUM 195 NORMATIVITY WITHOUT NORMATIVISM 1 Jesús Zamora-Bonilla jpzb@fsof.uned.es UNED, Madrid. Spain. Stephen Turner s book Explaining the Normative (Polity, Oxford, 2010) constitutes

More information

Practical Wisdom and Politics

Practical Wisdom and Politics Practical Wisdom and Politics In discussing Book I in subunit 1.6, you learned that the Ethics specifically addresses the close relationship between ethical inquiry and politics. At the outset, Aristotle

More information

Mika Ojakangas. A Philosophy of Concrete Life. Carl Schmitt and the Political Thought of Late Modernity.

Mika Ojakangas. A Philosophy of Concrete Life. Carl Schmitt and the Political Thought of Late Modernity. Mika Ojakangas. A Philosophy of Concrete Life. Carl Schmitt and the Political Thought of Late Modernity. Stefan Fietz During the last years, the thought of Carl Schmitt has regained wide international

More information

LOGICAL SEMANTICS AND NORMS: A KANTIAN PERSPECTIVE

LOGICAL SEMANTICS AND NORMS: A KANTIAN PERSPECTIVE SÉRGIO MASCARENHAS Instituto Superior de Gestão Bancária CEDIS-FDUNL smascrns@gmail.com LOGICAL SEMANTICS AND NORMS: A KANTIAN PERSPECTIVE abstract It s widely accepted that normativity is not subject

More information

Logic and the Absolute: Platonic and Christian Views

Logic and the Absolute: Platonic and Christian Views Logic and the Absolute: Platonic and Christian Views by Philip Sherrard Studies in Comparative Religion, Vol. 7, No. 2. (Spring 1973) World Wisdom, Inc. www.studiesincomparativereligion.com ONE of the

More information

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström From: Who Owns Our Genes?, Proceedings of an international conference, October 1999, Tallin, Estonia, The Nordic Committee on Bioethics, 2000. THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström I shall be mainly

More information

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals G. J. Mattey Spring, 2017/ Philosophy 1 The Division of Philosophical Labor Kant generally endorses the ancient Greek division of philosophy into

More information

HART ON THE INTERNAL ASPECT OF RULES

HART ON THE INTERNAL ASPECT OF RULES HART ON THE INTERNAL ASPECT OF RULES John D. Hodson Introduction, Polycarp Ikuenobe THE CONTEMPORARY AMERICAN PHILOSOPHER John Hodson, examines what H. L. A. Hart means by the notion of internal aspect

More information

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair FIRST STUDY The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair I 1. In recent decades, our understanding of the philosophy of philosophers such as Kant or Hegel has been

More information

To link to this article:

To link to this article: This article was downloaded by: [University of Chicago Library] On: 24 May 2013, At: 08:10 Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office:

More information

Kelsen s Legal Monism and the Future of the European Constitution

Kelsen s Legal Monism and the Future of the European Constitution Kelsen s Legal Monism and the Future of the European Constitution Draft, August 2011 Lars Vinx Department of Philosophy Bilkent University vinx@bilkent.edu.tr In recent years, much of the debate on the

More information

How Subjective Fact Ties Language to Reality

How Subjective Fact Ties Language to Reality How Subjective Fact Ties Language to Reality Mark F. Sharlow URL: http://www.eskimo.com/~msharlow ABSTRACT In this note, I point out some implications of the experiential principle* for the nature of the

More information

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible ) Philosophical Proof of God: Derived from Principles in Bernard Lonergan s Insight May 2014 Robert J. Spitzer, S.J., Ph.D. Magis Center of Reason and Faith Lonergan s proof may be stated as follows: Introduction

More information

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism At each time t the world is perfectly determinate in all detail. - Let us grant this for the sake of argument. We might want to re-visit this perfectly reasonable assumption

More information

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the THE MEANING OF OUGHT Ralph Wedgwood What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the meaning of a word in English. Such empirical semantic questions should ideally

More information

Argumentation and Positioning: Empirical insights and arguments for argumentation analysis

Argumentation and Positioning: Empirical insights and arguments for argumentation analysis Argumentation and Positioning: Empirical insights and arguments for argumentation analysis Luke Joseph Buhagiar & Gordon Sammut University of Malta luke.buhagiar@um.edu.mt Abstract Argumentation refers

More information

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Kent State University BIBLID [0873-626X (2014) 39; pp. 139-145] Abstract The causal theory of reference (CTR) provides a well-articulated and widely-accepted account

More information

1. Lukasiewicz s Logic

1. Lukasiewicz s Logic Bulletin of the Section of Logic Volume 29/3 (2000), pp. 115 124 Dale Jacquette AN INTERNAL DETERMINACY METATHEOREM FOR LUKASIEWICZ S AUSSAGENKALKÜLS Abstract An internal determinacy metatheorem is proved

More information

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module - 21 Lecture - 21 Kant Forms of sensibility Categories

More information

QUESTIONING GÖDEL S ONTOLOGICAL PROOF: IS TRUTH POSITIVE?

QUESTIONING GÖDEL S ONTOLOGICAL PROOF: IS TRUTH POSITIVE? QUESTIONING GÖDEL S ONTOLOGICAL PROOF: IS TRUTH POSITIVE? GREGOR DAMSCHEN Martin Luther University of Halle-Wittenberg Abstract. In his Ontological proof, Kurt Gödel introduces the notion of a second-order

More information

A Generalization of Hume s Thesis

A Generalization of Hume s Thesis Philosophia Scientiæ Travaux d'histoire et de philosophie des sciences 10-1 2006 Jerzy Kalinowski : logique et normativité A Generalization of Hume s Thesis Jan Woleński Publisher Editions Kimé Electronic

More information

SOME PROBLEMS IN REPRESENTATION OF KNOWLEDGE IN FORMAL LANGUAGES

SOME PROBLEMS IN REPRESENTATION OF KNOWLEDGE IN FORMAL LANGUAGES STUDIES IN LOGIC, GRAMMAR AND RHETORIC 30(43) 2012 University of Bialystok SOME PROBLEMS IN REPRESENTATION OF KNOWLEDGE IN FORMAL LANGUAGES Abstract. In the article we discuss the basic difficulties which

More information

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld PHILOSOPHICAL HOLISM M. Esfeld Department of Philosophy, University of Konstanz, Germany Keywords: atomism, confirmation, holism, inferential role semantics, meaning, monism, ontological dependence, rule-following,

More information

Ethical Consistency and the Logic of Ought

Ethical Consistency and the Logic of Ought Ethical Consistency and the Logic of Ought Mathieu Beirlaen Ghent University In Ethical Consistency, Bernard Williams vindicated the possibility of moral conflicts; he proposed to consistently allow for

More information

Louisiana Law Review. Cheney C. Joseph Jr. Louisiana State University Law Center. Volume 35 Number 5 Special Issue Repository Citation

Louisiana Law Review. Cheney C. Joseph Jr. Louisiana State University Law Center. Volume 35 Number 5 Special Issue Repository Citation Louisiana Law Review Volume 35 Number 5 Special Issue 1975 ON GUILT, RESPONSIBILITY AND PUNISHMENT. By Alf Ross. Translated from Danish by Alastair Hannay and Thomas E. Sheahan. London, Stevens and Sons

More information

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text. Citation: 21 Isr. L. Rev. 113 1986 Content downloaded/printed from HeinOnline (http://heinonline.org) Sun Jan 11 12:34:09 2015 -- Your use of this HeinOnline PDF indicates your acceptance of HeinOnline's

More information

Powerful Arguments: Logical Argument Mapping

Powerful Arguments: Logical Argument Mapping Georgia Institute of Technology From the SelectedWorks of Michael H.G. Hoffmann 2011 Powerful Arguments: Logical Argument Mapping Michael H.G. Hoffmann, Georgia Institute of Technology - Main Campus Available

More information

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism R ealism about properties, standardly, is contrasted with nominalism. According to nominalism, only particulars exist. According to realism, both

More information

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system Floris T. van Vugt University College Utrecht University, The Netherlands October 22, 2003 Abstract The main question

More information

xiv Truth Without Objectivity

xiv Truth Without Objectivity Introduction There is a certain approach to theorizing about language that is called truthconditional semantics. The underlying idea of truth-conditional semantics is often summarized as the idea that

More information

Affirmation-Negation: New Perspective

Affirmation-Negation: New Perspective Journal of Modern Education Review, ISSN 2155-7993, USA November 2014, Volume 4, No. 11, pp. 910 914 Doi: 10.15341/jmer(2155-7993)/11.04.2014/005 Academic Star Publishing Company, 2014 http://www.academicstar.us

More information

PROFESSOR HARTS CONCEPT OF LAW SUBAS H. MAHTO LEGAL THEORY F.Y.LLM

PROFESSOR HARTS CONCEPT OF LAW SUBAS H. MAHTO LEGAL THEORY F.Y.LLM PROFESSOR HARTS CONCEPT OF LAW SUBAS H. MAHTO LEGAL THEORY F.Y.LLM 1 INDEX Page Nos. 1) Chapter 1 Introduction 3 2) Chapter 2 Harts Concept 5 3) Chapter 3 Rule of Recognition 6 4) Chapter 4 Harts View

More information

Legal Doctrine As a Non-Normative Discipline

Legal Doctrine As a Non-Normative Discipline A Refinement of Niiniluoto s and Aarnio s Distinction between Norm-Descriptions, Norm-Contentions and Norm-Recommendations * Anne Ruth Mackor 1 Introduction 1.1 The problem Many legal theorists claim that

More information

MEDITATIONS ON THE FIRST PHILOSOPHY: THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT

MEDITATIONS ON THE FIRST PHILOSOPHY: THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT MEDITATIONS ON THE FIRST PHILOSOPHY: THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT René Descartes Introduction, Donald M. Borchert DESCARTES WAS BORN IN FRANCE in 1596 and died in Sweden in 1650. His formal education from

More information

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Olav Gjelsvik, University of Oslo The thesis. Among people writing about rationality, few people are more rational than Wlodek Rabinowicz. But are there reasons for being

More information

HABERMAS ON COMPATIBILISM AND ONTOLOGICAL MONISM Some problems

HABERMAS ON COMPATIBILISM AND ONTOLOGICAL MONISM Some problems Philosophical Explorations, Vol. 10, No. 1, March 2007 HABERMAS ON COMPATIBILISM AND ONTOLOGICAL MONISM Some problems Michael Quante In a first step, I disentangle the issues of scientism and of compatiblism

More information

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary Moral Objectivism RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary The possibility, let alone the actuality, of an objective morality has intrigued philosophers for well over two millennia. Though much discussed,

More information

AUTONOMY, TAKING ONE S CHOICES TO BE GOOD, AND PRACTICAL LAW: REPLIES TO CRITICS

AUTONOMY, TAKING ONE S CHOICES TO BE GOOD, AND PRACTICAL LAW: REPLIES TO CRITICS Philosophical Books Vol. 49 No. 2 April 2008 pp. 125 137 AUTONOMY, TAKING ONE S CHOICES TO BE GOOD, AND PRACTICAL LAW: REPLIES TO CRITICS andrews reath The University of California, Riverside I Several

More information

CHAPTER THREE Philosophical Argument

CHAPTER THREE Philosophical Argument CHAPTER THREE Philosophical Argument General Overview: As our students often attest, we all live in a complex world filled with demanding issues and bewildering challenges. In order to determine those

More information

THREE LOGICIANS: ARISTOTLE, SACCHERI, FREGE

THREE LOGICIANS: ARISTOTLE, SACCHERI, FREGE 1 THREE LOGICIANS: ARISTOTLE, SACCHERI, FREGE Acta philosophica, (Roma) 7, 1998, 115-120 Ignacio Angelelli Philosophy Department The University of Texas at Austin Austin, TX, 78712 plac565@utxvms.cc.utexas.edu

More information

1/6. The Resolution of the Antinomies

1/6. The Resolution of the Antinomies 1/6 The Resolution of the Antinomies Kant provides us with the resolutions of the antinomies in order, starting with the first and ending with the fourth. The first antinomy, as we recall, concerned the

More information

Revus Journal for Constitutional Theory and Philosophy of Law / Revija za ustavno teorijo in filozofijo prava

Revus Journal for Constitutional Theory and Philosophy of Law / Revija za ustavno teorijo in filozofijo prava Revus Journal for Constitutional Theory and Philosophy of Law / Revija za ustavno teorijo in filozofijo prava 27 2015 Emergence, Coherence, and Interpretation of Law On tû-tû Publisher Klub Revus Electronic

More information

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which 1 Lecture 3 I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which posits a semantic difference between the pairs of names 'Cicero', 'Cicero' and 'Cicero', 'Tully' even

More information