The Weight of Dogmatism: Investigating Learning in Dewey s Pragmatism and Wittgenstein s Ordinary Language Philosophy

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "The Weight of Dogmatism: Investigating Learning in Dewey s Pragmatism and Wittgenstein s Ordinary Language Philosophy"

Transcription

1 Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain Annual Conference New College, Oxford 1-3 April 2016 The Weight of Dogmatism: Investigating Learning in Dewey s Pragmatism and Wittgenstein s Ordinary Language Philosophy Dr Viktor Johansson Örebro University & Dalarna Uiniversity viktor.johansson@oru.se

2 Investigating Learning in Dewey s Pragmatism and Wittgenstein s Ordinary Language Philosophy 1. Attach a Weight to Your Foot What is it to learn something? Some would say that this question cannot be solved by philosophy, but by empirical investigations. Philosophers of education want to ask what it is we are empirically investigating. What kind of phenomenon is this? Someone may suggest that we simply define what we mean by learning and then investigate what falls under such a definition. Someone else may suggest that we specify what we mean by learning something particular, such as reading, fencing, walking, calculating, or the Aristotelean concept of virtue. Wouldn t that make the question researchable? For others what learning is may not be a concern. They may want to define it to set up criteria for assessing educational practices or students achievements in schools and preschools. We want to be able to tell when a student is learning to read. This want to tell what learning is can blind us. We may fall for the temptation to set ontological and epistemological requirements for how we use a word like learning and seek justifications for such requirements: A dogmatism we so easily fall into when doing philosophy, as Wittgenstein put it (1953, 131). He describes his aim in philosophy as trying to overcome difficulties having to do with the will, rather than the intellect (Wittgenstein, 1980, p. 17). However, since we are limited by preconceived ideas about learning, which obscures our acknowledgement of the variations in how the concept of learning functions in our lives, such philosophising is tough. In this essay I will sketch out Dewey s pragmatic view of learning as a response to our need to lay down metaphysical requirements for learning. In order to uphold a Deweyan view of learning without reverting to dogmatic metaphysics, we need a philosophical method that destabilises philosophical accomplishments. This essay places Dewey in conversation with Wittgenstein (read through Cavell) in order to dissolve our wish to say something philosophically constructive about learning. Following Wittgenstein s turn to our use words in ordinary language can be seen as a practice that is meant to maintain a vision uncontaminated by metaphysical assumptions. Surely Dewey s philosophy is arguably also anti-metaphysical and anti-foundational (Rorty, 1979, pp. 5-7, , ). But even an anti-metaphysical and non-foundational philosophy can lay down requirements for learning. Wittgenstein s aim in philosophy goes deeper than replacing dogmatic metaphysics with anti-foundationalism. Consider this remark from 1937: I am not thinking of these dogmas as determining men s opinions but rather as completely controlling the expression of all opinions. Wittgenstein not only attacks dogmatic opinions, but also dogmatic pre-conceptions of what can be expressed. He is not attacking one dogmatic view, say of learning as a reconstruction of a mental map or even learning as doing, but even dogmatisms in anti-foundationalist visions of learning. He continues: 1

3 People will live under an absolute, palpable tyranny, though without being able to say they are not free. For dogma is expressed in the form of an assertion, and is unshakeable, but at the same time any practical opinion can be said to harmonize with it; admittedly more easily in some cases than others. It is not a wall setting limits to what can be believed, it is rather like a brake which, however, practically serves the same purpose; it s almost as though someone were to attach a weight to your foot to restrict your freedom of movement. This is how dogma becomes irrefutable and beyond the reach of attack (Wittgenstein, 1980, p. 28). When we think of dogmatism in our want for requirements of learning, it is not enough to struggle against the wall of metaphysical preconceptions in search of anti-foundational alternatives. We must struggle against our very need, or want, for such requirements and pre-conceptions. Although Dewey is helpful in tearing down walls that limit our views of learning, such tearing down may blind us to the heavy metaphysics that is attached to our foot. We may still want to assert something about learning. Hence, we need to focus our attention to our feet. In Wittgenstein s later philosophy, looking at our feet means looking at our ordinary language. To get a clear view of the role learning has in our lives, we investigate our ordinary use of words like learning. In this essay I practice Dewey s pragmatism and Wittgenstein s ordinary language philosophy together (cf. Hutchinson & Read, 2013, p. 170). 2. Philosophy and Metaphysical Pictures Wittgenstein admits that his philosophy may appear destructive: Where does our investigation get its importance from, given that it seems only to destroy everything interesting: that is, all that is great and important? His response: what we are destroying are only houses of cards and we are clearing up the ground of language upon which they stood (1953, 118). What is Wittgenstein destroying? Consider, for example, how Deleuze and Guattari describe philosophy as art or an activity, however imprecise or historicised, of forming, inventing and fabricating concepts (1994, p. 2). The history of philosophy can be read in this way. In philosophy, concepts are created as a function of problems which are thought to be badly understood or badly posed (pedagogy of the concept) (Ibid. p. 16). No wonder Deleuze called Wittgenstein a philosophical catastrophe and Wittgenstein s followers assassins of philosophy (Deleuze, 2011). Without delving more into Deleuze and Guattari s view of philosophy, one may say that the Wittgensteinian position I am proposing here, despite some other affinities with them, goes in the opposite direction. For Wittgenstein, what leads philosophers to nonsense is this drive to respond to problems by creating new concepts or transforming old ones. The problems we are dealing with, philosophical problems, arise not because we do not have the rights words, but because the words we are using when forming the problem arise when language is, as it were, idling, not when it is doing work (Wittgenstein, 1953, 132). The problem with the concept-creation view of philosophy is that 2

4 it assumes that by creating concepts we can lay down in advance what it is we are thinking about that philosophical concepts have a particular status in that they can solve certain types of problems, as if the problems will disappear as long as we can conceptualise them in satisfying ways, like the turns of thought in solving a riddle. If there is something to Wittgenstein s story, what can philosophy do? It can liberate us from metaphysical weights attached to our feet, from the laying down of requirements and the philosophical creation of concepts. The dogmatic bonds that we are destroying are the preconceptions of a phenomenon that make us think the phenomenon needs a philosophical explanation or that it involves a problem to be solved by philosophy (Diamond, 1991, pp , 33). Destroying those pictures allows us to leave things as they are and instead give an honest account of our lives, our uses of words, our practices. This method of ordinary language philosophy is in this sense autobiographical: it tells stories of our lives and lets those stories dissolve our philosophical problems by making visible the idleness, emptiness, and nonsensicality of our metaphysical requirements. Taking a Wittgensteinian stance on learning means to liberate the word learning from philosophy and metaphysics. But, Wittgenstein needs conversational partners. Although learning is a subject that is present throughout Wittgenstein s later work, the stories that he tells are in the service of liberating us from other kinds of requirements by reminding us of the everyday struggle to learn words and concepts. He is not primarily investigating the use of learn or learning or trying to dissolve metaphysical pictures of learning. Therefore, let us put Wittgenstein in conversation with Dewey. 3. Dewey s Learning Without Fixed Ends Dewey often uses words such as growth, change, experience, adaption, inquiry, and, of course, education. These notions go in different directions and explicate various aspects of what Biesta and Burbules call Dewey s experimental theory of learning. The theory is based on the idea that the human animal, like any living being, has an experimental way of establishing coordinated transactions in its environment (Biesta & Burbules 2003, p. 37). Learning is a form of establishing new habits and a reconstruction of old habits. It is learning in the sense of acquisition of a complex set of predispositions to act (Ibid.). This links Dewey s ideas of knowledge as action, transactional experience, and educational practice in understanding acquisition of knowledge as inquiry a sequential process rooted in life itself. If human beings, like all other animals, transact in their environment and continually transform the established ways of such transactions, then learning and education become non-teleological. There cannot be a final end to such transformation since the growth it involves is in response to new happenings in the environment and as such changes the environment, which means that all habits and established practices will be disrupted. Therefore, Dewey can say: Since in reality there is nothing to which growth is relative save more growth, there is nothing to which education is subordinate save more education (1916, p. 58). 3

5 Dewey s emphasis on intellectual and scientific inquiry as an openness to explore the unknown redirects our attention to which abilities are conditional to a capacity to grow. Immaturity is understood as a capacity to grow and a capacity to sustain life which is why Dewey can say such things as for certain moral and intellectual purposes adults must become as little children and [w]ith respect to sympathetic curiosity, unbiased responsiveness and openness of mind, we may say that the adult should be growing in childlikeness (Dewey, 1916, p. 55). The aim of learning is not maturity or adulthood or a final state of mastery of a technique or a practice. When we abandon the attempt to define immaturity by means of fixed comparison with adult accomplishments, we are compelled to give up thinking of it as denoting lack of desired traits (1916, p. 56). There is no metaphysical requirement determining the goal of growth. To be learning something is to be set on a path of growth (1916, p. 58). In his effort to overcome the dualism between the individual and the social, Dewey argues that full education comes only when there is a responsible share on the part of each person, in proportion to capacity, in shaping the aims and policies of the social groups to which he belongs (Dewey, 1920, p. 199). For Dewey it is impossible to talk about an individual as growing outside an environment consisting of both the social and the physical (Dewey, 1920, p. 193 cf. Read 2007 pp. 5-22). The idea is that growing in an environment not only puts into question the individual-social dualism; like Wittgenstein s notions of natural history and form of life, it also dissolves the culture-nature divide. The growth of an organism, a plant, a human, or other animal is a result of responding and reacting to an environment, consisting as much of stones, rocks, trees, bodies, and brains as social pressures, norms, and value systems. The environment of a human organism is cultural-natural and as such not a synonym for mere nature. Not only do we have a dualism of natural or socio-cultural phenomena that affect the organism, but we also have a plurality of different environments with immense variation (Read, 2007, p. 14). Thinking of environments as a way of avoiding metaphysical assumptions about the individual-social and nature-culture divides also dissolves the idea of an individual learner or inquirer separate from his or her environment. As part of the environment, every inquiry involves a growth or transformation of the whole environment, however small. Determining ends for growth will be incomprehensible since the conditions for growth would always change due to the growing and evolving environment. Dewey maintains that education should involve children in the process of inquiry and in this way children can take charge of themselves and not only adapt themselves to the changes which are going on, but have power to shape and direct those changes (1897, p. 60). Dissolving the assumptions of clear distinctions between particular learners and their environment implies a distinctive view of growth that is salient when we consider Dewey s pragmatic understating of action and the world of things. The individual and reality is a result of a transactional whole where the mind and world as separate entities are not the presumed points of departure for a philosophical 4

6 exploration of the nature of reality and knowledge (1925, p. 28). The transactional whole out of which both the individual and her environment emerges establishes what Dewey calls experience. Yet, this take on Dewey is so far too epistemological. Jim Garrison reminds us that experience is first and foremost a practical matter: Experience is what happens to a sentient creature in its reciprocally trans-forming trans-actions with its natural environment, including the human created world of language and institutions we call culture (2013, p. 7). Experience is a form of practice a deed where we put art and creation first, preceding the intellectual or epistemological: It would then be seen that science is an art, that art is practice, and that the only distinction worth drawing is not between practice and theory, but between those modes of practice that are not intelligent, not inherently and immediately enjoyable, and those which are full of enjoyed meanings (Dewey, 1925, p ). Intellectual work or scientific inquiry becomes an embodied art for Dewey. Conceptual learning becomes a practical matter. For him learning is an open-ended art. Learning becomes a continual process of inquiry in everyday habits, a result of the immaturity of the organism and its environment. 4. A Wittgensteinian Twist on Pragmatic Metaphors Dewey s avoidance of the metaphysics of learning is interweaved with his view of an intellectual fallacy in western philosophy. By intellectualism as an indictment is meant the theory that all experiencing is a mode of knowing, and that all subject-matter, all nature, is, in principle, to be reduced and transformed till it is defined in terms identical with the characteristics presented by refined objects of science as such. The assumption of intellectualism goes contrary to the facts of what is primarily experienced (Dewey, 1925, p. 28). To Dewey, intellectualism, not to be confused with Dewey s use of intelligent, leads to superficial simplifications in philosophy. In thinking about learning it presumes a foundation and a telos for learning based on a priori assumptions. Such tendencies, particularly in modern times, have become chains that are, like Wittgenstein s weights, so natural that they are not even felt (Dewey, 2012, p. 257). This means that in certain forms of philosophising we are tempted to forget that [t]he philosopher is first and last a human being with his own intellectual and emotional habits who is involved in a concrete scene having its own color of tradition; its own occupations and dominant desires; its own overhanging problems and preferred ways of meeting them (Ibid. p. 33). 5

7 Wittgenstein shares this view of philosophy s tendency for intellectualism. To Wittgenstein, however, the tendency to forget that the philosopher is a human being, a growing organism, is not only a problem with professional philosophy, but is a result of our lives with languages. A picture held us captive. And we could not get outside it, for it lay in our language, and language seemed only to repeat it to us inexorably (1953, 115). Therefore, the source of philosophy s bounds, metaphysical pictures, and requirements, is not only philosophy s tendency to forget the human animal in its cultural contexts, but the way we are speaking and living seems to inescapably disconnect us with that same life. Although we may resolve philosophical pictures and destroy the metaphysical buildings we build, they will reoccur in new forms. The emphatic variance between Dewey s and Wittgenstein s view of what we can do about the philosophical tendency towards intellectualism reveals a radical difference in temperament of their thinking. In Dewey there is still hope for philosophy to do something constructive. In Dewey we find an attempt to form a philosophy that is free from metaphysical requirements. In Wittgenstein s later work there is no such hope for philosophy. There the task of philosophy is not to found a philosophy free from metaphysical requirements, but to treat our very need for such requirements by freeing us from philosophy to remove the weight from our feet. Nevertheless, even this task is hopeless since the very means we have to do so is the same language that inexorably repeats the pictures to us. We cannot finally escape the captivations and temptations of our own thought and language. Rather, in philosophizing you have to descend into primeval chaos and feel at home there (Wittgenstein 1980, p. 65). In philosophy of education, this means that Dewey can write a new creed, a pedagogical credo, something constructive a novel vision of what education can be about. In Wittgensteinian philosophy of education, there can be no such creeds, only confession, an honest account, of all our faults, temptations, hopes, and desires, and the metaphysical presuppositions in which we are entangled. Does Dewey s new creed, his creative and constructive philosophy, disguise other metaphysical requirements and pictures? The focus on future behaviours, say applications of concepts in further context, may seem an innocent step, a step pragmatists share with Wittgensteinians that is, basically the pragmatic metaphor of concepts as tools that we use for particular purposes, for doing things, which of course is an idea that we find in ordinary language philosophy in both its Austinian and Wittgensteinian forms. Nonetheless, the different temperaments and styles brought into their writing bring the tool/use-metaphor into play in quite different ways. Consider how Dewey uses the metaphor in Democracy and Education: In short, the sound h-a-t gains meaning in the same way that the thing hat gains it, by being used in a given way. And they acquire the same meaning with the child which they have with the adult because they are used in a common experience by both (Dewey, 1916, p. 19, emphasis added). He continues: The guarantee for the same manner of use is found in the fact that the thing and the sound are first employed in a joint activity, as a means of setting up an active connection 6

8 between the child and the grown-up (Ibid.). For Dewey the meaning of an utterance emerges out of what we do with it, in our trans-actions with it. Speaking is one of the many ways in which some organisms live in their environments. He is aware of the risk of meaning scepticism if I use a word to do something, I cannot know whether others understand what I am doing or whether they use the word that same way thus Dewey thinks that a word is meaningful because it is common experience. The use of a word, its value as a tool, emerges out of a practice that involves a community of speakers with shared experiences. Similarly Wittgenstein writes: For a large class of cases of the employment of the word meaning though not for all this word can be explained in this way: the meaning of a word is its use in the language (1953, 43 emphasis added). Notice Wittgenstein s twist on the tool metaphor. Wittgenstein investigates meaning not by telling us what makes something meaningful, or even for a basis of meaning in use or common action. Rather, Wittgenstein starts with how we employ or use the word meaning before drawing any other conclusions. He starts investigating before he can even speak of how to investigate. His investigation investigates how to investigate. Later he writes: One cannot guess how a word functions. Not even the word meaning. One has to look at its use and learn from that. But the difficulty is to remove the prejudice which stands in the way of doing this. It is not a stupid prejudice (1953, 340). Wittgenstein is not trying to explain that what makes words meaningful is their use. He investigates different uses of words, not only in actual practices but also in what happens when we take them outside of practices, whether they can have a point for us, for me, in different contexts, to see what we may learn from that. Such investigations are, of course, a challenging task. It is difficult to be honest about how we use words, how we think, and what we do. Still, this is all we need to do. We do not need to explain anything. In Stephen Mulhall s words, This suggests that Wittgenstein is not proposing that we picture meaning as use, but rather that, if we answer the question of how a word is used, then we will have no inclination to inquire about, or to attempt to picture, its meaning (Mulhall, 2001, p. 42). Wittgenstein, unlike Dewey, does not say that the meaning of the word is its use. There are no metaphysical requirements for meaning, no claim about meaning, but rather referring to use is a methodological claim about how to do philosophy, a method that he actually tests in his investigations of uses of words. As in Dewey, Wittgenstein s child is sometimes described as learning to master a technique, but Wittgenstein s child is also involved in philosophy s methodological struggle about meaning. Learning words is not a matter of learning how to use words, but is more a matter of learning methods for investigating uses of words, what words may do. Learning words is like learning a philosophical method. Therefore, Dewey s starting point is turned around; we do not start to think about what learning and meaning can be, the philosophical intellectualism both Wittgenstein and Dewey detest. We start by looking at how we use the words meaning and learning, where such words have a point in our actual lives. This philosophical method involves a form of dramatic struggle between 7

9 looking at a linguistic community s conventional practices and uses, and looking at my own idiosyncratic employment of words, a struggle that, if we acknowledge the autobiographical dimension of such philosophical methods, spills over into my view of myself as learner. Or to put in more Deweyan lingo, if we start with the methods of philosophical inquiry as a matter of investigating our use of words, we start with not only a realisation that we are describing human organisms transacting in environments, but also a realisation that my present philosophical inquiry is an inquiry into an environment. Philosophy (of learning) becomes personal, about my life. Reading Wittgenstein, and reading Dewey through Wittgenstein, is not only about reading to understand theories and his reasons for rejecting theories, but is also about reading a drama a drama of multiple voices trying to get a grip on human nature and practices, constantly losing that grip and returning to the activities themselves, feeling content in these ordinary practices, feeling discontent and moving on. By using the protagonist s self-imaginations, Wittgenstein moves at a level that is deeper than that of arguing about theses, as the basis of the possibility of holding any view about anything at all is continually queried and required (Eldridge, 1997:15). 5. Towards a Grammar of Learning If we look at how we use words such as learn and teach, a radical vision of learning and teaching may emerge. Investigating use involves presenting objects of comparison that shed light on distinctions which our ordinary forms of language easily makes us overlook, making plain our preconceived ideas and the dogmatism into which we fall so easily in doing philosophy (Wittgenstein 1953, ). Accordingly, we cannot presume there to be any other criteria for when learning occurs other than what we find in our own application of the concept learn. Here is where the problem with Dewey s view lies. If the growth and processes of trans-active inquiry are taken as metaphysical criteria for learning, just as meaning as use can for meaning, then it can become a preconceived idea that can miss other complexities in how we live with the concept of learning. Any theory of mind, language, or learning would, in a sense, become regulatory, dogmatic (Eldridge 1997, p. 2). A philosophical theory of learning, in this sense, could not recognise the struggle of testing our claims involved in using a term like learn, since a theory would offer directions and definitions for what it means to learn something. Having said this, we should be aware of our need for such theories, which is the incitement for our theorising. Dewey stresses the significance of both the limitations of the inheritance of the practices of adulthood and the playfulness of childhood: Thus the artistic capacities of the adult exhibit what certain tendencies of the child are capable of; if we did not have the adult achievements we should be without assurance as to the significance of the drawing, reproducing, modelling, coloring activities of childhood. So if it were not for adult language, we should not be able to see the import 8

10 of the babbling impulses of infancy. But it is one thing to use adult accomplishments as a context in which to place and survey the doings of childhood and youth; it is quite another to set them up as a fixed aim without regard to the concrete activities of those educated (Dewey, 1916, p. 115). Although some of Dewey s insight here seems to be correct education is concerned both with inheritance and with newness there is something important that is missing in Dewey s account. That is the voice of the child (Cavell, 2003, p. 218). Although, Dewey scrupulously investigates different ideas about education and learning, he is not equally attentive to his style in expressing them. Although he submits to a use of theory of meaning, he does not always first turn to ordinary uses of words as a method for philosophical inquiry. In Cavell s words: It might be worth pointing out that these teachings [the impossibility of a private language and the emphasis on functions and contexts of language] are fundamental to American pragmatism; but then we must keep in mind how different these arguments sound, and admit that in philosophy it is the sound which makes the difference (Cavell 2002, p. 35). Wittgenstein, on the other hand, though not directly engaged in educational issues, lends his philosophy to give voice to the struggles of childhood. The sound of childhood is crucial to both the style and the content of his later philosophy. For him, looking at children s struggles in finding their way into adult communities is a way to investigate what we mean by words in the context of their use. He reminds us of children s responses to instruction and the fragility of the attunement between the child, the teacher, and the community. In Philosophical Investigations (1953), Wittgenstein explores different variants of what it can mean to following an instruction to continue to write down series of numbers. The child can refuse to go on the way its teacher expects her to. She does not have to conform to our established use of words and numbers ( 185). In those refusals, or misunderstandings, Wittgenstein is careful to give voice to the pupil s attempts, even describing them as a systematic mistake, or a variant ( 143). These scenes are often taken as examples of rule-following, but what Wittgenstein says he is exploring is the grammar of know and its relatives. A methodological remark in the midst of the discussion of these scenes clarifies the emphatic difference between Wittgenstein and Dewey further: The grammar of the word know is evidently closely related to the grammar of the words can, is able to. But also closely related to that of the word understand. (To have mastered a technique.) (1953, 150) The scenes of instruction and the children s voices in them in the Investigations connects the grammar knowing with doing or being able to do something. For Dewey this connection is important. Knowing is acting. In Wittgenstein these are not theoretical remarks for an alternative to traditional epistemology, but reminders of how we use words. In giving voice to the pupil s attempts 9

11 to go on with the teacher, Wittgenstein also appropriates questions about the use of learn ; for instance, when asking: What do I mean when I say the pupil s ability to learn may come to an end here? ( 144). The voice of the child becomes a reminder for the philosopher of the importance of looking at our use of words. Attending to the voice of the child changes our way of looking at things ( 144). The child speaks back to philosophy and makes us aware of the fact that our use of know, learn, and is able is what is at stake, not metaphysical or epistemological conditions. We see grammatical rather than theoretical connections though an awareness of how the child is constrained when trying to make herself intelligible to us as much as we are to him/her. In a way, as Cavell emphasises, Wittgenstein s attention to grammar acknowledges the child s struggle for his or her elders acknowledgement of the child s voice (Cavell, 1996, p. 288). Wittgenstein ordinary language philosophy will not solve any pedagogical problems. He describes our various uses of learning, what we mean by the word, and our applications of the concept. What we need in a philosophy of learning is not a doctrine, but acknowledgement of our dual need to lead our words back from their metaphysical to their everyday use (Wittgenstein, 1953, 116) and to move beyond the present state of culture towards future cultures and project our words into new contexts (Cavell, 2002, p. 52). As a consequence of the Wittgensteinian vision, we can never know beforehand what it would mean to learn or to have learnt something. Learning is not only used as a word for conforming to a fixed pattern of societal norms, and nor is it limited to being used for merely dealing with problems in our transactions. The criteria for how we use learn may be expressed analogously to what Wittgenstein seems to have meant when he talked about his vision of certainty and corrections of our opinions: Here once more there is needed a step like the one taken in relativity theory (1974, 305). 1 In Philosophical Investigations, Wittgenstein famously claims that humans agree, or attune (to be more true to the German übereinstimung ), in language, in forms of life, in judgments, but not in opinions (1953, 241-2). 2 Even so, to Wittgenstein the fragility in the possibility of disagreement seems equally important. 3 Dissonant moments or the threat of dissonance may tempt us to invoke metaphysical requirements, justifications, and explanations (Cavell, 1979:31-3). In an educational context we might be tempted to say that the result of a process of learning is attunement in practice. In fact, sometimes Wittgenstein seems to say something like this. Instruction in acting according to the rule can be described without employing and so on. 1 For a complementary discussion of the educational aspects of this passage, see Stickney There has been some discussion regarding how to translate Wittgenstein s übereinstimmung. Agreement is common, but I follow Cavell s suggestion in my use of attunement. See Cavell 1979, p See , 185 and the discussion of rule-following and private language remarks in Johansson 2013, pp

12 What can be described in this description is a gesture, a tone of voice, a sign which the teacher uses in a particular way in giving instruction, and which the pupils imitate. The effect of these expressions can also be described, again without calling and so on to our aid, i.e. finitely. The effect of and so on will be to produce agreement going beyond what is done in the lessons, with the result that we all or nearly all count the same and calculate the same. It would be possible, though, to imagine the very instruction without any and so on in it. But on leaving school the people would still all calculate the same beyond the examples in the instruction they had (Wittgenstein, 1978, VI 45). In most instruction of, for example, mathematical rules, an and so on seems to be implied. We say something to the effect of This is how you apply the rule here and here and so on. What is implied is that there are inestimable ways in which we may apply a rule and an infinite number of contexts in which we can use a word. Wittgenstein shows that agreement beyond the examples is the goal of these instructions that are contained in the actual teaching activity. This is the step like the one in relativity theory. The aim of an instruction in mathematics could not be that the pupil arrives at a certain mental state or is successful in doing something determinate, but simply an attunement in practice. We can say that someone has learnt something that he can read when we are attuned and expect to continue to be attuned with that pupil in how we use letters, construct meanings, and so on in further contexts. There are no criteria beyond our attunement in use, and in practice, that we can come to agree on. Because when we determine the movements of two bodies in relation to each other in the theory of relativity (odd as it may sound), this means that we cannot, without taking the perspective of one or the other, determine who is changing: the student s or the teacher s, the community s or the individual s. The transformation taking place in learning processes is determined by whose use we are taking as a point of reference mine or my student s. Does this mean that we end in learning skepticism that we cannot know where to place learning? Or does the focus of common agreement put too much pressure on the individual to conform to the community, which makes learning a socialisation into heteronomous agreement? Not if we let go of the idea of agreement having a role in theory that justifies a certain view on learning. Remember the question Wittgenstein: Suppose one day instruction no longer produced agreement? (1978, VI 45) Of course that day is already here and has always been here. Teachers are very much aware of the fact that their instructions quite often do not lead the teacher and the pupil to go on together. In science, in art and in politics and in all aspects of human life, we fall in and out of tune. This, one may say, is the human drama expressed in Wittgenstein s ordinary language philosophy. When our use of the word learn is the subject of our philosophical investigations, we cannot even determine what extent we use learn to refer to a change in the child, the adult, or the community. We are either attuned or 11

13 we are not. Stating that the child has learnt to read can mean that we can go together with texts, words, and letters. But what does it really mean if this is a claim about how we use the term learn? First we test our use of the word learn and related terms. The ordinary language philosopher tests whether his or her uses corresponds with those of others. That is what Wittgenstein does in his later writings. Second, we test whether our uses of learn are representative for how others use it. In short we test who the we are when we claim that we say so and so (cf. Johansson, 2015). Third, and this is quite distinct for how we use learn and its cousins and how such uses seem to be a step like that in relativity theory, it seems that in many cases when we employ words and concepts like learn, we also make claims for a future attunement with those who we claim are learning. We make claims for a future we. An investigation of the use of learn lifts the weight of dogmatism from our feet. Rather than looking for requirements for determining when learning has taken place or for what learning is, we explore how and when we use the term in attunement or dissonance. In so doing, we can see that words like learn are used as claims about present and future attunement that rather than individual or communal or environmental change. This transforms Dewey s pragmatism and gives children a voice in the process of their learning. If we carefully investigate the use of learn, Dewey s idea of habit reconstruction and interaction in various environments, the dissolution of the distinction between the organism and the environment, between the individual and the society, becomes even more radical. Looking at the use of learn becomes a method of releasing us from the dogmatic requirements determining what learning is. Even Dewey s terminology comes to consist of examples of possible uses rather than theoretical remarks on learning words (excluding references). References Biesta, G. & Burbules, N. (2003) Pragmatism and Educational Research (Oxford, Roman and Littlefield Publishers). Cavell, S. (1979) The Claim of Reason (Oxford University Press, Oxford). Cavell, S. (1996) Notes and afterthoughts on the opening of Wittgenstein s Investigations, in H. Sluga & D Stern (eds.) The Cambridge Companion to Wittgenstein (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Cavell, S. (2002) Must We Mean What We Say? (2 nd updated ed.) (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Cavell, S. (2003) Emerson s Transcendental Etudes (Stanford, Stanford University Press). Deleuze, G. (2011) Gilles Deleuze from A to Z DVD, (Cambridge, MA, MIT. Press). Deleuze, G. & Guattari, F. (1994) What is Philosophy? (New York, Columbia University Press). Dewey, J. (1897) Ethical Principles Underlying Education, in: J.A. Boydston (ed.) The Early Works of John Dewey, vol 5. (Carbondale, Southern Illinois University Press). Dewey, J. (1916) Democracy and Education, in J.A. Boydston (ed.) The Middle Works of John Dewey, vol. 9. (Carbondale, Southern Illinois University Press). 12

14 Dewey, J. (1920) Reconstruction in Philosophy, in J.A. Boydston (ed.) The Middle Works of John Dewey, vol. 12. (Carbondale, Southern Illinois University Press). Dewey, J. (1925) Experience and Nature, in Boydston, J.A. (ed.) The Later Works of John Dewey, Vol. 5. (Carbondale, Southern Illinois University Press). Dewey, J. (2012) Unmodern Philosophy and Modern Philosophy. (Carbondale and Edwardsville, Southern Illinois University Press). Diamond, C. (1991) The Realistic Spirit: Wittgenstein, Philosophy and the Mind. (Cambridge, MIT Press. Eldridge, R. (1997) Leading a Human Life: Wittgenstein, Intentionality and Romanticism (Chicago, University of Chicago Press). Garrison, J. (2013) 2012 Dewey Lecture: Making Meaning Together Beyond Theory and Practice, Education and Culture 29:2, pp Hutchinson, P. & Read R. (2013) Practising pragmatist-wittgensteinianism, in A. Malachowski ed. The Cambridge Companion to Pragmatism (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press), pp Johansson, V. (2013) Dissonant Voices: Philosophy, Children s Literature, and Perfectionist Education (Stockholm, Stockholm University, Department of Education). Dissertation. Johansson, V. (2015) Questions from the Rough Ground: Teaching, Autobiography and the Cosmopolitan I, in Studies in Philosophy and Education, 34:5, pp Mulhall, S. (2001) Inheritance and Originality: Wittgenstein, Heidegger, Kierkegaard (Oxford, Oxford University Press). Read, R. (2007) Philosophy for Life: Applying Philosophy in Politics and Culture (London, Continuum). Rorty, R. (1979) Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton, Princeton University Press). Stickney, J. (2008) Wittgenstein s Relativity : Training in language-games and agreement in Forms of Life, Educational Philosophy and Theory, 40:5, pp Wittgenstein, L. (1953) Philosophical Investigations (4 th Revised Ed.) (Oxford, Blackwell Publishing). Wittgenstein, L. (1974) On Certainty (Oxford, Blackwell Publishing). Wittgenstein, L. (1978) Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics (3 rd Revised Ed.) (Oxford, Basil Blackwell Publishing). Wittgenstein, L. (1980) Culture and Value (Oxford, Basil Blackwell Publishing). 13

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings 2017 Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society An Alternative Approach to Mathematical Ontology Amber Donovan (Durham University) Introduction

More information

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Michael Esfeld (published in Uwe Meixner and Peter Simons (eds.): Metaphysics in the Post-Metaphysical Age. Papers of the 22nd International Wittgenstein Symposium.

More information

Different kinds of naturalistic explanations of linguistic behaviour

Different kinds of naturalistic explanations of linguistic behaviour Different kinds of naturalistic explanations of linguistic behaviour Manuel Bremer Abstract. Naturalistic explanations (of linguistic behaviour) have to answer two questions: What is meant by giving a

More information

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable by Manoranjan Mallick and Vikram S. Sirola Abstract The paper attempts to delve into the distinction Wittgenstein makes between factual discourse and moral thoughts.

More information

Towards Richard Rorty s Critique on Transcendental Grounding of Human Rights by Dr. P.S. Sreevidya

Towards Richard Rorty s Critique on Transcendental Grounding of Human Rights by Dr. P.S. Sreevidya Towards Richard Rorty s Critique on Transcendental Grounding of Human Rights by Dr. P.S. Sreevidya Abstract This article considers how the human rights theory established by US pragmatist Richard Rorty,

More information

COPYRIGHT 2009ASSOCIAZIONE PRAGMA

COPYRIGHT 2009ASSOCIAZIONE PRAGMA EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PRAGMATISM AND AMERICAN PHILOSOPHY COPYRIGHT 2009ASSOCIAZIONE PRAGMA Maria Luisi* Pragmatism, Ethics and Democracy. YEP SEMINAR, May 4 th 2011, Rome Abstract. The first international

More information

This is the published version of a paper published in The Journal of Aesthetic Education.

This is the published version of a paper published in The Journal of Aesthetic Education. http://www.diva-portal.org This is the published version of a paper published in The Journal of Aesthetic Education. Citation for the original published paper (version of record): Viktor, J. (2014) Perfectionist

More information

Wittgenstein on forms of life: a short introduction

Wittgenstein on forms of life: a short introduction E-LOGOS Electronic Journal for Philosophy 2017, Vol. 24(1) 13 18 ISSN 1211-0442 (DOI 10.18267/j.e-logos.440),Peer-reviewed article Journal homepage: e-logos.vse.cz Wittgenstein on forms of life: a short

More information

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary Critical Realism & Philosophy Webinar Ruth Groff August 5, 2015 Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary You don t have to become a philosopher, but just as philosophers should know their way around

More information

To the first questions the answers may be obtained by employing the process of going and seeing, and catching and counting, respectively.

To the first questions the answers may be obtained by employing the process of going and seeing, and catching and counting, respectively. To the first questions the answers may be obtained by employing the process of going and seeing, and catching and counting, respectively. The answers to the next questions will not be so easily found,

More information

The Philosophy of Physics. Physics versus Metaphysics

The Philosophy of Physics. Physics versus Metaphysics The Philosophy of Physics Lecture One Physics versus Metaphysics Rob Trueman rob.trueman@york.ac.uk University of York Preliminaries Physics versus Metaphysics Preliminaries What is Meta -physics? Metaphysics

More information

Gestures in the Making

Gestures in the Making European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy VIII-1 2016 Dewey s Democracy and Education as a Source of and a Resource for European Educational Theory and Practice Gestures in the Making Mathias

More information

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1 By Tom Cumming Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics represents Martin Heidegger's first attempt at an interpretation of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason (1781). This

More information

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Chapter 98 Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Lars Leeten Universität Hildesheim Practical thinking is a tricky business. Its aim will never be fulfilled unless influence on practical

More information

Pragmatism s Alternative to Foundationalism and Relativism. Introduction

Pragmatism s Alternative to Foundationalism and Relativism. Introduction Pragmatism s Alternative to Foundationalism and Relativism Introduction Pragmatists discuss a variety of philosophical topics including truth, reality, belief, inquiry, meaning, the good, justification,

More information

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld PHILOSOPHICAL HOLISM M. Esfeld Department of Philosophy, University of Konstanz, Germany Keywords: atomism, confirmation, holism, inferential role semantics, meaning, monism, ontological dependence, rule-following,

More information

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. The Physical World Author(s): Barry Stroud Source: Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, Vol. 87 (1986-1987), pp. 263-277 Published by: Blackwell Publishing on behalf of The Aristotelian

More information

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion) Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion) Arguably, the main task of philosophy is to seek the truth. We seek genuine knowledge. This is why epistemology

More information

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology Philosophy of Science Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology Philosophical Theology 1 (TH5) Aug. 15 Intro to Philosophical Theology; Logic Aug. 22 Truth & Epistemology Aug. 29 Metaphysics

More information

Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the. Gettier Problem

Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the. Gettier Problem Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the Gettier Problem Dr. Qilin Li (liqilin@gmail.com; liqilin@pku.edu.cn) The Department of Philosophy, Peking University Beiijing, P. R. China

More information

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational Joshua Schechter Brown University I Introduction What is the epistemic significance of discovering that one of your beliefs depends

More information

Title: Wittgenstein on forms of life: a short introduction.

Title: Wittgenstein on forms of life: a short introduction. Tonner, Philip (2017) Wittgenstein on forms of life : a short introduction. E-Logos Electronic Journal for Philosophy. ISSN 1211-0442, 10.18267/j.e-logos.440 This version is available at https://strathprints.strath.ac.uk/62192/

More information

Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University,

Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University, The Negative Role of Empirical Stimulus in Theory Change: W. V. Quine and P. Feyerabend Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University, 1 To all Participants

More information

Spinoza, the No Shared Attribute thesis, and the

Spinoza, the No Shared Attribute thesis, and the Spinoza, the No Shared Attribute thesis, and the Principle of Sufficient Reason * Daniel Whiting This is a pre-print of an article whose final and definitive form is due to be published in the British

More information

This is the published version of a paper published in Journal of Philosophy of Education.

This is the published version of a paper published in Journal of Philosophy of Education. http://www.diva-portal.org This is the published version of a paper published in Journal of Philosophy of Education. Citation for the original published paper (version of record): Johansson, V. (2011)

More information

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary Moral Objectivism RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary The possibility, let alone the actuality, of an objective morality has intrigued philosophers for well over two millennia. Though much discussed,

More information

Book Review. The Cambridge Companion to Dewey. Justin Bell

Book Review. The Cambridge Companion to Dewey. Justin Bell Book Review The Cambridge Companion to Dewey Justin Bell Molly Cochran (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Dewey. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010. 356 +xvii pages. ISBN 978-0-521-69746-0. $25.00

More information

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture Intentionality It is not unusual to begin a discussion of Kant with a brief review of some history of philosophy. What is perhaps less usual is to start with a review

More information

Christian Lotz, Commentary, SPEP 2009 Formal Indication and the Problem of Radical Philosophy in Heidegger

Christian Lotz, Commentary, SPEP 2009 Formal Indication and the Problem of Radical Philosophy in Heidegger Christian Lotz, Commentary, SPEP 2009 Formal Indication and the Problem of Radical Philosophy in Heidegger Introduction I would like to begin by thanking Leslie MacAvoy for her attempt to revitalize the

More information

Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence. Abstract

Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence. Abstract Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence Edoardo Zamuner Abstract This paper is concerned with the answer Wittgenstein gives to a specific version of the sceptical problem of other minds.

More information

Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox

Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox Marie McGinn, Norwich Introduction In Part II, Section x, of the Philosophical Investigations (PI ), Wittgenstein discusses what is known as Moore s Paradox. Wittgenstein

More information

This handout follows the handout on The nature of the sceptic s challenge. You should read that handout first.

This handout follows the handout on The nature of the sceptic s challenge. You should read that handout first. Michael Lacewing Three responses to scepticism This handout follows the handout on The nature of the sceptic s challenge. You should read that handout first. MITIGATED SCEPTICISM The term mitigated scepticism

More information

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp.

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp. 330 Interpretation and Legal Theory Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp. Reviewed by Lawrence E. Thacker* Interpretation may be defined roughly as the process of determining the meaning

More information

Naturalism Without Reductionism. A Pragmatist Account of Religion. Dr. des. Ana Honnacker, Goethe University Frankfurt a. M.

Naturalism Without Reductionism. A Pragmatist Account of Religion. Dr. des. Ana Honnacker, Goethe University Frankfurt a. M. Naturalism Without Reductionism. A Pragmatist Account of Religion Dr. des. Ana Honnacker, Goethe University Frankfurt a. M. [Draft version, not for citation] Introduction The talk of naturalizing religion

More information

Tuukka Kaidesoja Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

Tuukka Kaidesoja Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology Journal of Social Ontology 2015; 1(2): 321 326 Book Symposium Open Access Tuukka Kaidesoja Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology DOI 10.1515/jso-2015-0016 Abstract: This paper introduces

More information

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Author: Terence Rajivan Edward, University of Manchester. Abstract. In the sixth chapter of The View from Nowhere, Thomas Nagel attempts to identify a form of idealism.

More information

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY Subhankari Pati Research Scholar Pondicherry University, Pondicherry The present aim of this paper is to highlights the shortcomings in Kant

More information

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair FIRST STUDY The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair I 1. In recent decades, our understanding of the philosophy of philosophers such as Kant or Hegel has been

More information

Aboutness and Justification

Aboutness and Justification For a symposium on Imogen Dickie s book Fixing Reference to be published in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. Aboutness and Justification Dilip Ninan dilip.ninan@tufts.edu September 2016 Al believes

More information

Wittgenstein and the Skeptical Paradoxes

Wittgenstein and the Skeptical Paradoxes 9 Wittgenstein and the Skeptical Paradoxes Saul Kripke (1982) reads out of Wittgenstein s later writings two skeptical paradoxes and a skeptical solution of each of them. A skeptical solution consists

More information

Descartes and Schopenhauer on Voluntary Movement:

Descartes and Schopenhauer on Voluntary Movement: Descartes and Schopenhauer on Voluntary Movement: Why My Arm Is Lifted When I Will Lift It? Katsunori MATSUDA (Received on October 2, 2014) The purpose of this paper In the ordinary literature on modern

More information

BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity: Thomas Reid s Theory of Action

BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity: Thomas Reid s Theory of Action University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Faculty Publications - Department of Philosophy Philosophy, Department of 2005 BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity:

More information

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works Title Disaggregating Structures as an Agenda for Critical Realism: A Reply to McAnulla Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/4k27s891 Journal British

More information

The Need for Metanormativity: A Response to Christmas

The Need for Metanormativity: A Response to Christmas The Need for Metanormativity: A Response to Christmas Douglas J. Den Uyl Liberty Fund, Inc. Douglas B. Rasmussen St. John s University We would like to begin by thanking Billy Christmas for his excellent

More information

Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle

Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle 1 Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle I have argued in a number of writings 1 that the philosophical part (though not the neurobiological part) of the traditional mind-body problem has a

More information

The Kripkenstein Paradox and the Private World. In his paper, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Languages, Kripke expands upon a conclusion

The Kripkenstein Paradox and the Private World. In his paper, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Languages, Kripke expands upon a conclusion 24.251: Philosophy of Language Paper 2: S.A. Kripke, On Rules and Private Language 21 December 2011 The Kripkenstein Paradox and the Private World In his paper, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Languages,

More information

Is the Skeptical Attitude the Attitude of a Skeptic?

Is the Skeptical Attitude the Attitude of a Skeptic? Is the Skeptical Attitude the Attitude of a Skeptic? KATARZYNA PAPRZYCKA University of Pittsburgh There is something disturbing in the skeptic's claim that we do not know anything. It appears inconsistent

More information

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Ayer and Quine on the a priori Ayer and Quine on the a priori November 23, 2004 1 The problem of a priori knowledge Ayer s book is a defense of a thoroughgoing empiricism, not only about what is required for a belief to be justified

More information

The Philosophy of Education. An Introduction By: VV.AA., Richard BALEY (Ed.) London: Continuum

The Philosophy of Education. An Introduction By: VV.AA., Richard BALEY (Ed.) London: Continuum John TILLSON The Philosophy of Education. An Introduction By: VV.AA., Richard BALEY (Ed.) London: Continuum John TILLSON II Época, Nº 6 (2011):185-190 185 The Philosophy of Education. An Introduction 1.

More information

Assertion and Inference

Assertion and Inference Assertion and Inference Carlo Penco 1 1 Università degli studi di Genova via Balbi 4 16126 Genova (Italy) www.dif.unige.it/epi/hp/penco penco@unige.it Abstract. In this introduction to the tutorials I

More information

Roman Madzia. Education and Culture 30 (2) (2014):

Roman Madzia. Education and Culture 30 (2) (2014): Book Review The Things in Heaven and Earth Roman Madzia John Ryder, The Things in Heaven and Earth: An Essay in Pragmatic Naturalism. New York: Fordham University Press, 2013. 327 + xiv pp. ISBN 978-0-8232-4469-0.

More information

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10. Introduction This book seeks to provide a metaethical analysis of the responsibility ethics of two of its prominent defenders: H. Richard Niebuhr and Emmanuel Levinas. In any ethical writings, some use

More information

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory Western University Scholarship@Western 2015 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2015 Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory David Hakim Western University, davidhakim266@gmail.com

More information

SYSTEMATIC RESEARCH IN PHILOSOPHY. Contents

SYSTEMATIC RESEARCH IN PHILOSOPHY. Contents UNIT 1 SYSTEMATIC RESEARCH IN PHILOSOPHY Contents 1.1 Introduction 1.2 Research in Philosophy 1.3 Philosophical Method 1.4 Tools of Research 1.5 Choosing a Topic 1.1 INTRODUCTION Everyone who seeks knowledge

More information

Chapter Summaries: Introduction to Christian Philosophy by Clark, Chapter 1

Chapter Summaries: Introduction to Christian Philosophy by Clark, Chapter 1 Chapter Summaries: Introduction to Christian Philosophy by Clark, Chapter 1 In chapter 1, Clark reviews the purpose of Christian apologetics, and then proceeds to briefly review the failures of secular

More information

RECENT WORK THE MINIMAL DEFINITION AND METHODOLOGY OF COMPARATIVE PHILOSOPHY: A REPORT FROM A CONFERENCE STEPHEN C. ANGLE

RECENT WORK THE MINIMAL DEFINITION AND METHODOLOGY OF COMPARATIVE PHILOSOPHY: A REPORT FROM A CONFERENCE STEPHEN C. ANGLE Comparative Philosophy Volume 1, No. 1 (2010): 106-110 Open Access / ISSN 2151-6014 www.comparativephilosophy.org RECENT WORK THE MINIMAL DEFINITION AND METHODOLOGY OF COMPARATIVE PHILOSOPHY: A REPORT

More information

The title of this collection of essays is a question that I expect many professional philosophers have

The title of this collection of essays is a question that I expect many professional philosophers have What is Philosophy? C.P. Ragland and Sarah Heidt, eds. New Haven and London: Yale University Press, 2001, vii + 196pp., $38.00 h.c. 0-300-08755-1, $18.00 pbk. 0-300-08794-2 CHRISTINA HENDRICKS The title

More information

Søren Kierkegaard Philosophical Fragments, Concluding Scientific Postscript excerpts 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 10/10/13 12:03 PM

Søren Kierkegaard Philosophical Fragments, Concluding Scientific Postscript excerpts 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 10/10/13 12:03 PM Søren Kierkegaard Philosophical Fragments, Concluding Scientific Postscript excerpts 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 10/10/13 12:03 PM Section III: How do I know? Reading III.5 Søren Kierkegaard (1813-1855)

More information

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Book Reviews 1 In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998. Pp. xiv + 232. H/b 37.50, $54.95, P/b 13.95,

More information

The Sea-Fight Tomorrow by Aristotle

The Sea-Fight Tomorrow by Aristotle The Sea-Fight Tomorrow by Aristotle Aristotle, Antiquities Project About the author.... Aristotle (384-322) studied for twenty years at Plato s Academy in Athens. Following Plato s death, Aristotle left

More information

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to Haruyama 1 Justin Haruyama Bryan Smith HON 213 17 April 2008 Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to geometry has been

More information

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE NATURALISM a philosophical view according to which philosophy is not a distinct mode of inquiry with its own problems and its own special body of (possible) knowledge philosophy

More information

Wittgenstein and Heidegger: on Use

Wittgenstein and Heidegger: on Use Wittgenstein and Heidegger: on Use It is well-known that since the end of the 1970 s, a prolific tradition of comparison has undertaken to highlight the similitudes between the work of those two major

More information

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Kent State University BIBLID [0873-626X (2014) 39; pp. 139-145] Abstract The causal theory of reference (CTR) provides a well-articulated and widely-accepted account

More information

Unit 3: Philosophy as Theoretical Rationality

Unit 3: Philosophy as Theoretical Rationality Unit 3: Philosophy as Theoretical Rationality INTRODUCTORY TEXT. Perhaps the most unsettling thought many of us have, often quite early on in childhood, is that the whole world might be a dream; that the

More information

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea. Book reviews World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Naturalism, by Michael C. Rea. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2004, viii + 245 pp., $24.95. This is a splendid book. Its ideas are bold and

More information

Selections of the Nicomachean Ethics for GGL Unit: Learning to Live Well Taken from classic.mit.edu archive. Translated by W.D. Ross I.

Selections of the Nicomachean Ethics for GGL Unit: Learning to Live Well Taken from classic.mit.edu archive. Translated by W.D. Ross I. Selections of the Nicomachean Ethics for GGL Unit: Learning to Live Well Taken from classic.mit.edu archive. Translated by W.D. Ross I.7 Let us again return to the good we are seeking, and ask what it

More information

"Can We Have a Word in Private?": Wittgenstein on the Impossibility of Private Languages

Can We Have a Word in Private?: Wittgenstein on the Impossibility of Private Languages Macalester Journal of Philosophy Volume 14 Issue 1 Spring 2005 Article 11 5-1-2005 "Can We Have a Word in Private?": Wittgenstein on the Impossibility of Private Languages Dan Walz-Chojnacki Follow this

More information

Rezensionen / Book reviews

Rezensionen / Book reviews Research on Steiner Education Volume 4 Number 2 pp. 146-150 December 2013 Hosted at www.rosejourn.com Rezensionen / Book reviews Bo Dahlin Thomas Nagel (2012). Mind and cosmos. Why the materialist Neo-Darwinian

More information

Wittgenstein: Meaning and Representation

Wittgenstein: Meaning and Representation Wittgenstein: Meaning and Representation What does he mean? By BRENT SILBY Department Of Philosophy University of Canterbury Copyright (c) Brent Silby 1998 www.def-logic.com/articles There is a common

More information

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Ralph Wedgwood 1 Two views of practical reason Suppose that you are faced with several different options (that is, several ways in which you might act in a

More information

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006 In Defense of Radical Empiricism Joseph Benjamin Riegel A thesis submitted to the faculty of the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of

More information

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central TWO PROBLEMS WITH SPINOZA S ARGUMENT FOR SUBSTANCE MONISM LAURA ANGELINA DELGADO * In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central metaphysical thesis that there is only one substance in the universe.

More information

PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT FALL SEMESTER 2009 COURSE OFFERINGS

PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT FALL SEMESTER 2009 COURSE OFFERINGS PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT FALL SEMESTER 2009 COURSE OFFERINGS INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY (PHIL 100W) MIND BODY PROBLEM (PHIL 101) LOGIC AND CRITICAL THINKING (PHIL 110) INTRODUCTION TO ETHICS (PHIL 120) CULTURE

More information

There is no need to explain who Hilary Putnam is in light of the sheer number of books and articles on his work that have appeared over the past

There is no need to explain who Hilary Putnam is in light of the sheer number of books and articles on his work that have appeared over the past There is no need to explain who Hilary Putnam is in light of the sheer number of books and articles on his work that have appeared over the past several decades. For the sake of the youngest readers, it

More information

Moore s paradoxes, Evans s principle and self-knowledge

Moore s paradoxes, Evans s principle and self-knowledge 348 john n. williams References Alston, W. 1986. Epistemic circularity. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 47: 1 30. Beebee, H. 2001. Transfer of warrant, begging the question and semantic externalism.

More information

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1 Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1 Analysis 46 Philosophical grammar can shed light on philosophical questions. Grammatical differences can be used as a source of discovery and a guide

More information

Psychology and Psychurgy III. PSYCHOLOGY AND PSYCHURGY: The Nature and Use of The Mind. by Elmer Gates

Psychology and Psychurgy III. PSYCHOLOGY AND PSYCHURGY: The Nature and Use of The Mind. by Elmer Gates [p. 38] blank [p. 39] Psychology and Psychurgy [p. 40] blank [p. 41] III PSYCHOLOGY AND PSYCHURGY: The Nature and Use of The Mind. by Elmer Gates In this paper I have thought it well to call attention

More information

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY 1 CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY TORBEN SPAAK We have seen (in Section 3) that Hart objects to Austin s command theory of law, that it cannot account for the normativity of law, and that what is missing

More information

THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781)

THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781) THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781) From: A447/B475 A451/B479 Freedom independence of the laws of nature is certainly a deliverance from restraint, but it is also

More information

Process Thought and Bridge Building: A Response to Stephen K. White. Kevin Schilbrack

Process Thought and Bridge Building: A Response to Stephen K. White. Kevin Schilbrack Archived version from NCDOCKS Institutional Repository http://libres.uncg.edu/ir/asu/ Schilbrack, Kevin.2011 Process Thought and Bridge-Building: A Response to Stephen K. White, Process Studies 40:2 (Fall-Winter

More information

Introduction. 1 Bertrand Russell, The Problems of Philosophy (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, n.d.), 7.

Introduction. 1 Bertrand Russell, The Problems of Philosophy (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, n.d.), 7. Those who have consciously passed through the field of philosophy would readily remember the popular saying to beginners in this discipline: philosophy begins with the act of wondering. To wonder is, first

More information

37. The Analytic/Synthetic Distinction

37. The Analytic/Synthetic Distinction 37. The Analytic/Synthetic Distinction There s a danger in not saying anything conclusive about these matters. Your hero, despite all his talk about having the courage to question presuppositions, doesn

More information

Précis of Democracy and Moral Conflict

Précis of Democracy and Moral Conflict Symposium: Robert B. Talisse s Democracy and Moral Conflict Précis of Democracy and Moral Conflict Robert B. Talisse Vanderbilt University Democracy and Moral Conflict is an attempt finally to get right

More information

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text. Citation: 21 Isr. L. Rev. 113 1986 Content downloaded/printed from HeinOnline (http://heinonline.org) Sun Jan 11 12:34:09 2015 -- Your use of this HeinOnline PDF indicates your acceptance of HeinOnline's

More information

Anaximander. Book Review. Umberto Maionchi Carlo Rovelli Forthcoming, Dunod

Anaximander. Book Review. Umberto Maionchi Carlo Rovelli Forthcoming, Dunod Book Review Anaximander Carlo Rovelli Forthcoming, Dunod Umberto Maionchi umberto.maionchi@humana-mente.it The interest of Carlo Rovelli, a brilliant contemporary physicist known for his fundamental contributions

More information

Chapter Six. Aristotle s Theory of Causation and the Ideas of Potentiality and Actuality

Chapter Six. Aristotle s Theory of Causation and the Ideas of Potentiality and Actuality Chapter Six Aristotle s Theory of Causation and the Ideas of Potentiality and Actuality Key Words: Form and matter, potentiality and actuality, teleological, change, evolution. Formal cause, material cause,

More information

My self-as-philosopher and my self-as-scientist meet to do research in the classroom: Some Davidsonian notes on the philosophy of educational research

My self-as-philosopher and my self-as-scientist meet to do research in the classroom: Some Davidsonian notes on the philosophy of educational research My self-as-philosopher and my self-as-scientist meet to do research in the classroom: Some Davidsonian notes on the philosophy of educational research Andrés Mejía D., Universidad de Los Andes, Bogotá,

More information

Epistemology for Naturalists and Non-Naturalists: What s the Difference?

Epistemology for Naturalists and Non-Naturalists: What s the Difference? Res Cogitans Volume 3 Issue 1 Article 3 6-7-2012 Epistemology for Naturalists and Non-Naturalists: What s the Difference? Jason Poettcker University of Victoria Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans

More information

Foundationalism Vs. Skepticism: The Greater Philosophical Ideology

Foundationalism Vs. Skepticism: The Greater Philosophical Ideology 1. Introduction Ryan C. Smith Philosophy 125W- Final Paper April 24, 2010 Foundationalism Vs. Skepticism: The Greater Philosophical Ideology Throughout this paper, the goal will be to accomplish three

More information

ABSTRACT of the Habilitation Thesis

ABSTRACT of the Habilitation Thesis ABSTRACT of the Habilitation Thesis The focus on the problem of knowledge was in the very core of my researches even before my Ph.D thesis, therefore the investigation of Kant s philosophy in the process

More information

Metaphysical Pluralism: James and the Neo-Pragmatists

Metaphysical Pluralism: James and the Neo-Pragmatists Metaphysical Pluralism: James and the Neo-Pragmatists Sarah Wellan University of Potsdam Pragmatism has often been characterized as a non-metaphysical or even anti-metaphysical philosophical movement.

More information

Understanding and its Relation to Knowledge Christoph Baumberger, ETH Zurich & University of Zurich

Understanding and its Relation to Knowledge Christoph Baumberger, ETH Zurich & University of Zurich Understanding and its Relation to Knowledge Christoph Baumberger, ETH Zurich & University of Zurich christoph.baumberger@env.ethz.ch Abstract: Is understanding the same as or at least a species of knowledge?

More information

SAMPLE. Religious Language, Reference, and Autonomy

SAMPLE. Religious Language, Reference, and Autonomy 1 Religious Language, Reference, and Autonomy Logical positivism emerged in the early 1920s when Moritz Schlick, around whom it centered, became professor of philosophy at the University of Vienna. The

More information

이찬희.

이찬희. 서평 http://dx.doi.org/10.15750/chss.59.201602.012 The Undiscovered Dewey: Religion, Morality, and the Ethos of Democracy, by Melvin L. Rogers. New York: Columbia University Press, 2009. xxi+328pp., Index

More information

The Representation of Logical Form: A Dilemma

The Representation of Logical Form: A Dilemma The Representation of Logical Form: A Dilemma Benjamin Ferguson 1 Introduction Throughout the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus and especially in the 2.17 s and 4.1 s Wittgenstein asserts that propositions

More information

Ludwig Wittgenstein: Philosophical Investigations

Ludwig Wittgenstein: Philosophical Investigations Ludwig Wittgenstein: Philosophical Investigations Published posthumously in 1953 Style and method Style o A collection of 693 numbered remarks (from one sentence up to one page, usually one paragraph long).

More information

Man and the Presence of Evil in Christian and Platonic Doctrine by Philip Sherrard

Man and the Presence of Evil in Christian and Platonic Doctrine by Philip Sherrard Man and the Presence of Evil in Christian and Platonic Doctrine by Philip Sherrard Source: Studies in Comparative Religion, Vol. 2, No.1. World Wisdom, Inc. www.studiesincomparativereligion.com OF the

More information

Tm: education of man is his journey through life on earth. The

Tm: education of man is his journey through life on earth. The THE AIMS OF EDUCATION by J. CHR. COETZEE DR. COETZEE is Principal and Vice"Chancellor of Potchefstroom University for Christian Higher Education. where he occupies the Chair of Education. and his occasional

More information

Virtue Ethics without Character Traits

Virtue Ethics without Character Traits Virtue Ethics without Character Traits Gilbert Harman Princeton University August 18, 1999 Presumed parts of normative moral philosophy Normative moral philosophy is often thought to be concerned with

More information