Political Legitimacy and Luck

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Political Legitimacy and Luck"

Transcription

1 Tamsin Shaw Princeton University Draft: please do not cite Political Legitimacy and Luck Introduction Since political institutions have coercive powers, moral evaluation of them must begin with the question: under what conditions are they justified in coercing us? States and governments that meet such conditions can be said to be legitimate. The task of normative political theory may be seen as that of telling us what the conditions are which must be met. In this paper I shall examine one (at least prima facie) plausible and widely accepted condition of state legitimacy and will claim that it cannot be met through any intentional human effort. It requires reliance on luck. I shall also claim that acknowledgement of this reliance may impair our ability to sustain legitimacy, judged by this criterion, where it exists. Many people have found plausible the idea that the state only has a moral entitlement to exercise coercive power if its subjects accept that it has such an entitlement. I will refer to this as the popular acceptance condition. A state is legitimate, on this view, only if it is morally accepted by those coerced by it. This condition will need to be consistent with the realistic assumption that some people will not have thought about state legitimacy, but we can specify that it is hypothetical just in the sense that if they were to reflect on it, keeping their moral views fixed, they would accept the state as legitimate. This may be contrasted with the idea that legitimacy requires only moral acceptability in the sense of hypothetical acceptance of the state by idealized subjects. It might look as though popular acceptance is not just a discrete moral condition, but a necessary precondition of any form of legitimate rule, since acceptance of some sort is a necessary functional requirement of states. Complex modern states cannot rule by force alone. They require the cooperation of their subjects. But this functional requirement only demands as much popular acceptance as is necessary for stability. It is compatible with the coercive 1

2 suppression of minority dissenters. And it demands only compliance, rather than acceptance on normative grounds, so it may be secured through fear or through ideological manipulation. The popular acceptance condition, on the other hand, is a moral requirement. It derives from the view that anyone who is subject to the coercive power of the state is owed some justification that they can accept for that coercion. It requires that the state be acceptable to everyone. And as a moral requirement, it can be seen to incorporate two assumptions. It will not do for people s acceptance to be based on merely prudential considerations, such as the calculation that they will be better off if they obey rather than disobey the state to which they happen to be subject. The state must be acceptable to them on the basis of their moral beliefs. And it will not do for these moral beliefs to have been manufactured by the very power that they purport to legitimate. Acceptance must be uncoerced. 1 As we shall see, popular acceptance need not be taken to be a necessary and sufficient condition for legitimacy. It is compatible with a wide range of further conditions that can be independently specified. An objectivist about values might hold that acceptance is only valid if it involves reference to objectively correct standards for legitimacy. The motivation for endorsing the popular acceptance condition, in such a case, would be the intuition that although legitimacy requires conformity to objectively correct standards, the state of affairs prescribed by these standards cannot be coercively imposed on a population. It must be willingly accepted by them. Something like this intuition has of course for a long time found expression in the social contract tradition of political thought. Social contract theorists have attempted to discover an actual or potential basis of agreement that might sustain shared forms of political authority. Hobbes claimed to have identified a source of actual agreement in the universal desire for selfpreservation and hence our common desire for social peace. 2 However, this Hobbesean minimal agreement is sufficient only to justify the state per se and does not constrain the form that state power should take or specify its limits in relation to its subjects. Locke, on the other hand, thought that we could justify the coercive powers of particular states: they are legitimate just so long as the powers in question have been conferred by the actual consent of those subject to 1 Bernard Williams formulates this condition as the critical theory principle, which states that the acceptance of a justification does not count if the acceptance itself is produced by the coercive power which is supposedly being justified. Cf. Williams, Realism and Moralism in Political Theory, in In the Beginning was the Deed: Realism and Moralism in Political Argument (Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press, 2005), 1-18, at 6 2 Cf. Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, ed. Richard Tuck (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996) 2

3 them. 3 This foundational liberal theory of political legitimacy is strongly voluntaristic. So much so that it is generally considered unfeasible today. Most political thinkers now accept that full voluntariness is impossible. The modern state is in important respects simply a non-voluntary form of organization. The enormously complex and extensive nexus of power that states now comprise is unavoidable for any individuals born in the modern world. And it is not clear that it could be intentionally eliminated from our collective lives by any conceivable human efforts. Not only is statehood per se unavoidable, but for many of us subjection to the very state that we are born into will be unavoidable, since leaving it will be unfeasible. It would be implausible to attribute even tacit consent to people on the basis of their behavior in such constrained political circumstances. 4 Citizens of actual societies cannot be said to have freely consented to conferring on states the powers that those states have acquired over them. Some modern heirs of the social contract tradition regret this fact and draw the implication that political legitimacy is impossible in the modern world. 5 Other thinkers claim that we can make do with something less than full voluntariness or consent, something more like popular acceptance, which plays the same legitimizing role without making unrealistic demands. Even if political life cannot take the form of an entirely voluntary scheme of cooperation, it is still intuitively plausible, as Bernard Williams points out, to draw a distinction between a society that is an example of the human capacity for intelligible order and one that exemplifies the human tendency to unmediated coercion. 6 An intelligible order of authority, for Williams, is one that makes sense to all the participants in it. There is a legitimation offered which goes beyond the assertion of power and this legitimation will make sense to everyone on the basis of their own normative convictions, assuming that those convictions are themselves uncoerced. 7 We 3 Cf. John Locke, Second Treatise, Two Treatises of Government, ed. Peter Laslett (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1960). 4 Cf. Simmons, Moral Principles and Political Obligations, Cf. e.g. A. John Simmons, Justification and Legitimacy, Ethics, vol.109, no.4 (Jul., 1999), Cf. Williams, Realism and Moralism, Ibid., 11 3

4 can make do, in other words, with a less extravagant ideal to define the morally relevant contrast with mere coercion. We will call this ideal the ideal of an internally intelligible order. 8 This ideal expresses a traditionally liberal value, that of the priority of liberty over (forced) happiness. 9 Such an order may be contrasted with what we will call a coercively just regime, that is, one which either uses or is prepared to use force to make its subjects conform to norms which they do not themselves necessarily endorse. The realization of the ideal of an internally intelligible order must involve popular acceptance. The ideal seems to me to be implicit in much contemporary liberal theory. Thomas Nagel sets out what he calls an ideal of quasi-voluntariness according to which a political system s coercive power is legitimate so long as there are independent reasons for everyone to cooperate voluntarily in the maintenance of such a system and respect its results. 10 Nagel s insistence on everyone s having independent reasons to cooperate is ambiguous. It is consistent with holding that merely hypothetical consent is a sufficient condition for legitimacy. This would be a nonvoluntaristic view, one that is compatible with a coercively just regime. But his stress on voluntariness is disambiguating. Nagel makes clear that the search for legitimacy is, for him, an attempt to realize some of the values of voluntary participation. 11 His aim is to try to show people living under non-voluntary political arrangements that it would be unreasonable of them to reject the option of living under such a system. 12 A political theory that has this aim has a persuasive, as well as an ideal function. 13 It therefore tries to be sensitive to the perspectives of the individuals whom the arguments are meant to persuade. 14 This project of persuasion clearly indicates an aspiration to generate a political order that is internally intelligible to its participants. 8 Jeremy Waldron identifies the central ideal of the liberal tradition as that of a social order that can be justified to the people who have to live under it. He sees this as being related to the Enlightenment impulse that is based on the demand of the individual mind for the intelligibility of the social world. REF 9 Simmons, Moral Principles and Political Obligations, Nagel, Equality and Partiality, ibid., 36. For Nagel, the problem of legitimacy is inseparable from the demand for voluntarism of some for, for the problem of legitimacy arises not simply because the state has the capacity to coerce us, but because political society requires a special involvement of agency or the will. Although membership may not be optional, the engagement of the will that is essential to life inside a society still generates a special presumption against [ ][arbitrary distinctions in the way that it engages us. He writes: One might even say that we are all participants in the general will. Cf. Nagel, The Problem of Global Justice, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 33, no.2, , at Equality and Partiality.,36 13 ibid., ibid., 23 4

5 John Rawls, in his later work, seeks in a similar way to be sensitive to the perspectives of those whom his theory is meant to persuade. He outlines a form of political liberalism which adopts, he tells us, the liberal ideal of political legitimacy, namely, that social cooperation, at least as it concerns the constitutional essentials, is to be conducted so far as possible on terms both intelligible and acceptable to all citizens as reasonable and rational. 15 Justice as fairness, he tells us, must generate support by addressing each citizen s reason: Only in this manner is justice as fairness an account of political legitimacy. Only so does it escape being a mere account of how those who hold political power can satisfy themselves, in the light of their own convictions, whether political or fully comprehensive, that they are acting properly satisfy themselves, that is, and not citizens generally. 16 The contrast between an internally intelligible order and a coercively just regime is clearly playing a justificatory role here. As Brain Barry points out, in The Theory of Justice, Rawls holds that those who hold conceptions of the good that are incompatible with justice can be legitimately coerced. But in Political Liberalism, uncoerced consensus on the foundational principles of the regime is required. Dissenters would undermine the legitimacy of Rawlsian institutions. 17 In other words, Rawls mature position is shaped by his adoption of the popular acceptance condition. It has nevertheless been argued that the apparent concern with voluntarism in both Nagel and Rawls is insincere, that their constraint that acceptance be reasonable more closely resembles hypothetical consent than a demand for actual consent. It would not then involve a real commitment to actual acceptance as a moral requirement. 18 However, it is possible to make sense of both their commitment to normative standards for acceptability and their ideal of actual acceptance. We might see their aspiration to set out standards for acceptability as being motivated 15 John Rawls, The Domain of the Political and Overlapping Consensus, in Collected Papers, ed. Samuel Freeman (Cambridge, Mass., and London, England: Harvard University Press, 2001), ibid., cf. Brian Barry, Review: John Rawls and the Search for Stability, Ethics, vol.105, no.4 (Jul., 1995), Cf. Simmons, Justification and Legitimacy, 761: contemporary Kantian and hypothetical contractarian political philosophies have illicitly appropriated the justificatory force of voluntarism while being (like Kant) in no real way motivated by it. Kantians think of institutional evaluation in terms of what ought to be chosen by the people that is, in terms of the moral quality of institutions, what makes those institutions good (virtuous, just, etc.) not in terms of people s actual choices. Cf. also Cynthia A. Stark, Hypothetical Consent and Justification, The Journal of Philosophy, vol.97, no.6 (Jun., 2000), , at 334: the fact that the source of the authority of political principles is, in hypothetical-consent theory, located in citizens rational willing does not make citizens compliance to those principles voluntary, if those citizens are not in fact willing to obey and are moreover, forced to obey by an external authority. So it is somewhat misleading for Nagel and Rawls to claim that hypothetical-consent theories reflect, to some extent, the voluntarist ideal. 5

6 by the aim of facilitating actual acceptance. 19 They can be seen as being guided, at least implicitly, by the ideal of an internally intelligible order. Popular acceptance, in other words, may be seen to play the role of a necessary but not sufficient condition in their theories of legitimacy. Contemporary liberal theory, then, seems to be animated by the ideal of realizing an intelligible order in Williams sense. The aim of producing such an order generates a distinctive burden. Since it demands that a regime be acceptable to everyone, it requires basic normative agreement. It is this need for agreement, I shall argue, that generates our reliance on luck. And I shall claim that this reliance will be inevitable whether or not moral realism is true, that is, whether or not rational convergence on normative truths is in principle possible. If this is so, we need to ask whether it should be disturbing to us. Normative political theory has often been seen to have a practical task, answering for us the question of how we should best organize our societies. If the best social and political order turns out to depend on luck, we will have to revise our ordinary sense of what this reflective enterprise can hope to accomplish. In particular, we will have to admit that it has nothing to say to the unlucky, that is, to those who currently live under illegitimate political arrangements. But I shall also argue that even those who are lucky might find this view disturbing; for what is implied is that we may be deluded in imagining that transparency and intelligibility can give us greater rational control of our social world. If in fact we are dependent on luck for basic agreement, there is no way in which we can intentionally order our evaluative priorities around the end of attaining political legitimacy, since no collective rational effort is likely to guarantee that outcome. For individuals living in societies where there is already basic agreement, the acknowledgement that the order of priorities they have adopted still leaves them at the mercy of luck and arbitrariness as far as legitimacy is concerned might be a disincentive to sustaining the compromises on which the current agreement is inevitably built. Theoretical reflection, in this case, would be corrosive to the very end endorsed by the theory. 19 Jeremy Waldron points out that hypothetical consent can potentially play an important role in the establishment of actual consent: If the lack of actual consent is to be remedied, the first step must be reform of the society so that consent becomes an imaginable option. Hypothetical contractarianism provides the basis for that step to be taken. Cf. Theoretical Foundations, 51 6

7 I. The nature of the required agreement What kind of agreement is minimally required by the popular acceptance condition? It need not be very deep. The condition does not demand, for example, that everyone subject to a state s authority share the same set of moral values, nor even that they hold in common a set of normative beliefs about political legitimacy. It requires only that everyone, in the light of whatever moral convictions they do hold, finds a particular set of political arrangements acceptable. It does not require that people endorse the popular acceptance condition itself. Ordinarily, we will evaluate political institutions with reference to a wide range of moral values, but still not all of our values will always be politically relevant. The category of politically relevant values may be fluid. Although some moral values will be stable members of this subset, others might have political relevance only where they happen to become implicated in situations in which the state must act, or when they are introduced into public debate as justifications for some state action. Moral values governing sexual relations, for example, might be fluid members of the relevant subset. Some politically relevant values hold greater weight for people than others. Some are moral deal-breakers. If the state does not conform to them it will be held to be illegitimate (examples of such moral deal-breakers might include the commitment to basic human rights, or to the upholding of sharia law). These deal-breakers might or might not be part of consciously formulated theories of legitimacy. And they might or might not be related in a systematic way to our other values. Where conflict amongst moral deal-breakers exists, there will be people who feel themselves subject to unacceptable forms of coercive power. So what the popular acceptance condition requires as the minimum necessary form of agreement is simply an absence of conflicting moral deal-breakers. There can be no merely procedural solution to the problem of eliminating conflict amongst deal-breakers. The employment of any procedure for resolving disagreement would already have to already presuppose the relevant kind of moral agreement. Majoritarianism, for example, would already have to presuppose agreement that the supreme principle of legitimacy is deferral to the majority and this principle must trump, for everyone, all other potential moral dealbreakers. This would be a peculiar moral position for anyone to take, inasmuch as it would involve regarding all of our substantive moral commitments, except for the bare majoritarian one, as defeasible by mere unpopularity. 7

8 The view that more substantive basic agreement is necessary is still compatible with support for democratic institutions. But the latter can only be legitimacy-preserving if we presuppose prior fulfillment of the popular acceptance condition. Democracy may be held to be a necessary condition for governmental legitimacy, or in other words, a means of selecting officeholders in a legitimate state. There may be broad scope for policy differences amongst these office-holders. But there must nevertheless be prior acceptance by all parties that the kinds of disagreements they represent are of a sort that can be resolved procedurally, by deferring to the will of the majority. Such acceptance will only make sense in cases where no moral deal-breakers are violated in deferring. If certain rights and freedoms, for example, are considered dealbreakers, those elements of the polity will have to be immune to electoral outcomes. The popular acceptance condition seems to require more than majority agreement in establishing the basic foundation for rule. The idea is that no one should be subject to a form of rule that they could not accept on the basis of their avowed moral beliefs. But this condition, like its forbears in the consent tradition, raises the problem of unanimity. If no exceptions are permissible, then it might seem that one anarchist could delegitimate a state. 20 No state is then ever likely to be legitimate. One solution is to regard this as a threshold problem and to accept that the threshold is vague. States will be just as legitimate as they are popularly accepted. Beyond a certain threshold they can be held to be by and large legitimate. Below that threshold they will be by and large illegitimate. The extent to which a state forms an internally intelligible order will be a question of degree. It might be thought that an alternative way of solving the unanimity problem is boundarysetting. Some normative constraints might be applied to the set of people who must agree, for example, through the specification that they should all be reasonable. The definition of reasonable will then restrict the kinds of values on which agreement has to be reached, keeping out potential deal-breakers and thereby increasing the likelihood of unanimity. And it will also serve to define a restricted political community to whom the popular acceptance condition applies, one that is not coextensive with all members of any actual community. 21 However, if such a method were to exclude, in a real case, most members, or even just a significant minority, of a given population, it would constitute an abandonment of the liberal ideal of quasi-voluntariness as opposed to a coercively just regime. If that contrast is serving any, 20 Cf. Simmons, Moral Principles and Political Obligations, This constructivist strategy will be discussed in section IV. 8

9 even implicit, justifying role in the argument of a given theorist, it looks as though it will still be necessary to demand majority agreement in just the same way that the bare popular acceptance condition does. 22 The boundary-setting strategy just shifts the popular acceptance condition into the background, but as an implicit condition it raises the same threshold problem. The question, then, must be how agreement of the sort required by the popular acceptance condition can be achieved. And we must bear in mind that it cannot be achieved coercively, that is through ideological manipulation by the state that it is supposed to legitimate. What will be required in some independent mechanism for generating consensus. There is widespread disagreement about whether reason can itself generate consensus on moral issues. One s answer to this question will depend on one s meta-ethical position. But I will claim below that no matter what meta-ethical position we adopt, it seems unrealistic to suppose that any rational effort will yield the required form of agreement. The historical process might sometimes generate such agreement by accident, but it is hard to see how it could, without coercion, be intentionally achieved. II. Internal Intelligibility and Internalism about Reasons Williams s ideal of legitimacy does not look, prima facie, like a challenge to the practical ambitions of political theory. In fact, it looks as though it is precisely motivated by feasibility. The ideal of an internally intelligible order is invoked in order to restrain the ambitions, displayed by moralistic political theorists, to advance justifications for political power that people actually subject to that power could not in fact be expected to accept. 23 The version of the ideal that Williams offers is intended to be minimally morally exacting. It requires that states offer to each one of their subjects a justifying explanation for their 22 Any ideal of a just social system must presuppose that its realization requires conformity by an entire social order, and not simply some segment of a larger, unjust social order. Cf. e.g. John Rawls, who stresses that majority support is essential to the feasibility of a democratic society: an enduring and secure democratic regime, one not divided into contending doctrinal confessions and hostile social classes, must be willingly and freely supported by at least a substantial majority of its politically active citizens. His background assumption, then, must be that of widespread basic agreement. Ibid., 475. Cf. also The Idea of Public Reason Revisited, in John Rawls, The Law of Peoples (Cambridge Mass., & London, England: Harvard University Press, 1999), 139, where Rawls tells us that deliberative democracy requires the knowledge and desire on the part of citizens generally to follow public reason and realize its ideal in their political conduct. 23 Cf. Realism and Moralism,

10 power that is acceptable to them. In other words, the state must conform to local norms, or what makes sense to people in a particular cultural context. 24 Legitimacy can be intentionally achieved, then, by making political institutions conform to the state of affairs prescribed by these local norms. Because popular acceptance is here playing the role of a necessary and sufficient condition, the attainment of legitimacy looks as though it is simply a matter of political engineering. This is not to imply that it will always be simple to achieve what popular acceptance requires, but any attempt can be intentionally directed through instrumental reasoning towards the specified ends. Since Williams makes mere acceptance, rather than acceptance on the basis of recognition of the correct norms, a sufficient condition for legitimacy, his ideal looks particularly inclusive. It rules in states (theocracies, for example) that many liberal theories would rule out. 25 Many different kinds of regimes could meet his criterion. And this adds to the impression that it maximizes feasibility. What makes moralistic liberal theories look particularly unfeasible to Williams is their lack of any sound account of how convergence on liberal values is possible. He tells us that political moralism has no answer in its own terms to the question of why what it takes to be the true moral solution to the questions of politics, liberalism, should for the first time (roughly) become evident in European culture from the late seventeenth century onward, and why these truths have been concealed from other people. Moralistic liberalism cannot plausibly explain, adequately to its moral pretensions, why, when, and by whom it has been accepted and rejected. 26 His implication is that the best explanatory account of how liberal values have come to be accepted does not involve rational convergence on the truth. But absent the constraints of moralistic liberalism, he implies, no such account of convergence is required. We need only be concerned with the standards that make sense to the people in their particular historical and cultural context. Their regime has to be internally intelligible to them, in the light of their own normative beliefs. We do not have to insist that everyone, everywhere, should have converged on the very standards that we have converged on. 24 ibid., Cf. Williams, Human Rights and Relativism, In the Beginning was the Deed, Williams, Realism and Moralism, 9 10

11 This anti-universalism points to an important motivation for Williams view. His internalist account of practical reasons is driving this critique of political moralism. On this view, there are no universally binding moral reasons. An agent can have a real reason to act only if there exists a sound deliberative route between that reason and the contents of the agents existing subjective motivational set. 27 The motivational elements that comprise this include desires, along with dispositions of evaluation, patterns of emotional reaction, personal loyalties, and various projects, as they may be abstractly called, embodying commitments of the agent. 28 But on Williams view, as Christine Korsgaard points out, there are no universal, or rationally necessary motivations, such as pure practical reasons, that would apply to any rational being. 29 The view therefore implies that moral reasoning must take people as they contingently are, constructing a sound deliberative route from their particular, contingent motivational set. No moral or political theory can hope to persuade everybody, everywhere. Political theories, Williams claims, should not aim to persuade any possible rational being, but rather engage a particular ethical constituency. 30 This view is presented as being less demanding, in terms of the required convergence, than that of the political moralist. For where we disagree, he insists, we do not need the idea of an ultimately objective answer the answer, for instance, that would imply, if it were expanded enough, an account in terms of a universal moral psychology of where exactly at least one of the disputants had been in error. We need only something more restricted, the idea of the acceptable answer to this disagreement, an answer that might be reached in actual historical circumstances. 31 However, it is precisely the problem of disagreement that makes the ideal of internal intelligibility seem, on this view, unachievable by any intentionally directed process. 27 Williams, Internal and External Reasons, Moral Luck (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), ibid., p cf. Christine M. Korsgaard, Skepticism about Practical Reason, The Journal of Philosophy, vol.83, no.1 (Jan., 1986), On the view that internalism does not defeat universalism, cf. also Thomas Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, Mass., and London, England: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2000), appendix, Williams, In the Beginning Was the Deed, 149. Cf. also In the Beginning Was the Deed, 25: Foundationalism can never achieve what it wants. Any such theory will seem to make sense, and will to some degree reorganize political thought and action, only by virtue of the historical situation in which it is presented, and its relation to that historical situation cannot be fully theorized or captured in reflection. Those theories and reflections will themselves always be subject to the condition that, to someone who is intelligently and informedly in that situation (and those are not empty conditions), it does or does not seem a sensible way to go on. Also, 28: no political theory, liberal or other, can determine by itself its own application. The conditions in which the theory or any given interpretation of it makes sense to intelligent people are determined by an opaque aggregation of many actions and forces. 31 Williams, Saint Just s Illusion, Philosophy as a Humanistic Discipline (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995),

12 On the internalist account, if I want to persuade others I must find a sound deliberative route from their subjective motivational set to my own claims about what ought to be done. If a constitutional monarch is a deal-breaker for people in my political community, but a socialist republic is a deal-breaker for me, I will have to hope that there is a sound route from their underlying desires, beliefs, and projects to my desired form of political constitution. And it will have to be a route that they all, or at least most of them, can comprehend, if sufficient convergence is to be achieved to generate an internally intelligible order. But since there are no rationally necessary motivations, there is no guarantee that such a route can be found. It will be a matter of luck. 32 It might be objected that if reason-giving fails, there are other non-rational forms of persuasion at our disposal. For the rationalist these methods will count as coercive. Those who value rational autonomy will object on moral grounds. But the coercion prohibition that Williams proposes as a necessary condition of legitimacy does not rule them out on these grounds. It stipulates only that the state should not itself have manufactured the normative beliefs on the basis of which it is being evaluated by its subjects. 33 There is no further stipulation about how basic consensus amongst its subjects must have been reached. Williams cannot, given his antiobjectivist internalism, demand rational convergence. And his acceptance of theocracies as potentially legitimate also implies that non-rational methods can be sanctioned. Religious institutions have powerful means of non-rational persuasion at their disposal, backed up by hundreds of years worth of accumulated experience in the psychological art of compelling agreement. Secularists have fewer resources at their disposal, but some might hope that they have sufficient rhetorical powers to compete for converts to their political values. Are there not, then, consensus-generating mechanisms that do not rely on either reason or state 32 John Dunn points out that the political implications of this view for those who do not have a lucky consensus, are bleak: [ ] if Nature cannot today be reasonably supposed to have a Law to govern it, the justification of human actions in conditions of intense conflict (as in other conditions) cannot rest ultimately upon interpretations of the requirements of authority. What else might it rest upon instead? One answer a highly skeptical one [ ] would be that it must rest upon brute culture or psychological fact: on what just happens to appear justified to the members of a particular group or to singular individuals (on what Williams calls their subjective motivational set ). I doubt if we can in any sense know this answer to be wrong. But it is worth pointing out that accepting it involves construing all human conflict simply and without residue as a collision of power, and categories of justification as mere plastic components within this field of power, without inherent power of their own modifying its grim contours. Cf. Dunn, The History of Political Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), Realism and Moralism, 10 12

13 coercion? If so, could they not be intentionally employed to produce convergence around our values? The first thing to note is that religions which have generated sufficient consensus to support a structure of political authority have not done so without the aid of the states that they purport to legitimate. And on the basis of historical experience it seems reasonable to conclude that a great deal of coercion is required to inhibit the emergence of dissenting sects. It seems equally unpromising, then, for secularists to pin their hopes on non-rational, or merely rhetorical, methods for generating convergence around a stable set of political values. This is an empirical claim, so of course it might turn out in the long run to be refuted by the facts. But we have some reason to expect consensus generated by non-rational means to be unstable. Non-rational forms of persuasion must appeal to the contingent dispositions of those being persuaded. And dispositions, unlike reasons, are mutable. As Rousseau saw particularly clearly, human imagination is limitless and all of our non-rational dispositions, our emotions, desires, loyalties, and hopes, are subject to its constant reinvention. 34 So agreement generated in this way will only be as stable as the dispositional basis to which the methods of persuasion appeal. It will be subject over time to rationally arbitrary fluctuations. It will be peculiarly dependent, in other words, on luck. When Williams refers to the ethical constituencies to which justifications for political power must be made, he must be presupposing a lucky, stable consensus. But there is nothing in his account of our subjective motivational sets to encourage the hope that we will be continually lucky. Neither can he offer us any means of mitigating our reliance on luck in promoting the kind of minimal political consensus that legitimacy requires. So Williams insistence that political theory should appeal to particular ethical constituencies presupposes rather than offers a solution to what is, on his account, the fundamental problem of legitimacy. What is required is that the popular acceptance condition be met. But the kind of agreement required by this condition may or may not, for the anti-objectivist, be attainable in any given time and place. We can hope that historical communities will generate coherent and stable sets of local norms. We can hope that other people in our own communities 34 supply ref. 13

14 will come to agree that our norms are the most acceptable. But we cannot, on this view, devise a means of realizing this hope through any intentional effort. III. Objectivism and Rational Convergence We might expect the objectivist, however, to have a route out of this problem. If there are in fact universally binding moral norms, then the combined rational efforts of human beings should lead to convergence. Unlike the kind of convergence that is achieved through non-rational means, it should be stable and predictable. The strongest regulative ideal, what we will call the Enlightenment ideal, would be that of an order that is fully internally intelligible, fully just, and free from any arbitrary exercise of power. It would involve governance by rational norms and not the arbitrary will of human beings. Probably no one has ever imagined that such a political order is fully realizable by fallible human beings. But the demand can be weakened in various ways that might make it more plausible. The moral objectivist might hold both that the state should conform to the correct norms and that it should be popularly accepted without demanding that popular acceptance involve recognition of the correct norms. The objectivist might be satisfied if political institutions and actions were to conform to the correct norms, in the absence of popular convergence on those norms, so long as this state of affairs were acceptable to people on the basis of their own normative beliefs. The problem with such a compromise is that it still leaves us hostages to fortune, insofar as it relies on rationally arbitrary convictions lining up in the appropriate way with what is objectively correct. Where this situation does obtain, we might or might not have a stable compromise. Where it does not obtain, we have no means of bringing it about. Actual recognition of the correct norms, on the other hand, would create transparency, intelligibility and stability. But this stronger, recognition model seems to be very demanding. However, we need not assume that it requires of us complete realization of the Enlightenment ideal. If what we want is both conformity to the correct norms and popular acceptance, we might achieve this whilst accepting that we will fall short of that ideal. We do not have to demand absolute removal of arbitrariness just so long as states do not violate norms that are deal-breakers for legitimacy. And we do not even have to demand explicit recognition of the correct norms, and of the state s conformity to them. We might make do with implicit acceptance, that is, the 14

15 absence of explicit adherence to moral deal-breakers that would conflict with them. 35 This more realistic model might plausibly be held to be sufficient for an internally intelligible order. However, even this less exacting model requires basic normative agreement to be established and maintained over time. One advantage of objectivism, we might imagine, is that it can explain how such stable agreement might be possible. Since on this view it is in principle possible as reasoned agreement, reliance on human contingency will be mitigated by reasoning. It can never be entirely eliminated, since human opinions, like our dispositions, are variable, but it may be diminished by whatever degree of rationality can be attained. Were it to be possible, convergence on the truth would, unlike non-rational convergence, lessen our reliance on luck. However, the objectivist does not necessarily have reason to be optimistic about the possibility of convergence. One basis for pessimism would be moral pluralism. On this view, expounded in its most influential form by Isaiah Berlin, there may be ineliminable conflicts between our values. 36 The demands of liberty and those of equality, to use his most famous example, may not coincide. This sounds like an anti-objectivist view, since it follows that there are moral questions to which no objectively correct answer can be given. Berlin himself insisted that he was not an anti-objectivist: pluralism is not relativism - the multiple values are objective, part of the essence of humanity rather than arbitrary creations of men's subjective fancies. But it does nevertheless open up a great deal of scope for rational arbitrariness in any moral system. So it may the case, if moral pluralism is true, that even ideal reasoners could not necessarily eliminate all conflicting moral deal-breakers. An internally intelligible order would still require lucky consensus. Unsurprisingly, some objectivists are reluctant to accept that moral pluralism is true. Ronald Dworkin points out just how difficult it is to defend it, asking: When are we entitled, not simply to the negative idea that we do not know what it is right for us to do, but to the positive claim that we know that nothing we do is right because, whatever we do, we do something wrong? The latter is an extremely ambitious claim: it purports to see the bottom of a dilemma 35 Both Ronald Dworkin and John Rawls take as a starting point for their political theories norms which, they claim, are implicit in the political culture of liberal democracies. Part of the task of political philosophy, on this view, is to set out explicitly our implicit commitments. Cf. Dworkin, Is Democracy Possible Here?: Principles for a New Political Debate (Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press, 2006); and John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993). 36 Isaiah Berlin, Two Concepts of Liberty, Liberty, ed. Henry Hardy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1969,

16 and see that there is no escape. 37 It may be the case that where we perceive apparently intractable conflict what is required is further rational reflection, further refinement of our understanding of the needs and values that appear to conflict. 38 Dilemmas that seem inescapable may turn out to be resolvable in non-obvious ways. This exhortation to further reflection, however, itself raises a problem for those who endorse the popular acceptance condition. For it indicates that moral reasoning is a complex affair. Even if we believe that there always are objectively correct answers, it is going to be very hard for us to get at them. Actual convergence, it seems, is still unlikely to come about as the product of spontaneous reasoning on the part of beings with widely disparate rational capacities, whose reflective capabilities will be constrained in different ways by their circumstances. Liberal theorists have, in the past, relied on religious arguments to justify optimism about popular rational convergence; it is not clear that any non-religious alternative is available. Various religious views purport to explain how everyone can arrive at normative knowledge by their own lights. They do not need very sophisticated intellectual capacities in order to know how they ought to act, since they will be moved to do what is right by some inner revelation, or they will be endowed with reason sufficient to comprehend God s purposes. The idea that we have basic intellectual equality of this sort has, as John Dunn has pointed out, been central to the liberal tradition since Locke. 39 But it is not clear that secularists have any grounds for such faith in the popular capacity to acquire moral knowledge. As Jeremy Waldron points out, Locke himself saw a tension between the cultivation of normative expertise that was central to his own philosophical project, and the basic faith, essential to his political vision, in the adequacy of ordinary human powers to discern normative truth. But in the end, his faith in the reliability of the ordinary human intelligence won out. 40 Locke relies on a religious argument to defend this claim, insisting that there is a threshold above which intellectual differences become irrelevant, and that threshold is determined by the capacity 37 Ronald Dworkin, Moral Pluralism, Justice in Robes (Cambridge, Mass. and London England: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2006), 110. Cf. also Thomas Nagel, The Fragmentation of Value, Mortal Questions. 38 Dworkin, Moral Pluralism, cf. John Dunn, Western Political Theory in the Face of the Future, p.41, on Locke s view: Christian revelation and the god-given capacity for rational understanding gave all men who bothered to make the effort a clear grasp of how they should live their lives. 40 Jeremy Waldron, God, Locke, and Equality: Christian Foundations in Locke s Political Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002), p.85 16

17 for abstraction and hence for reasoning to the existence of God. This capacity is sufficient for people to understand that they must follow God s commandments, given by faith and revelation. 41 But the atheist, for whom no such threshold exists, Waldron tells us, will be at a loss to explain why we should ignore the evident differences in people s rationality. 42 Waldron is concerned about the illiberal implications that seem to follow if there can be no secular justification for basic equality. But we might equally take this problem as a basis for concern about access to normative knowledge and hence the impossibility of uncoerced convergence. If people do not have equal access to normative truth, it is hard to see how an internally intelligible order could be constructed around the correct norms. The more complex the normative claims of political theorists are, the more unlikely it seems that all people could engage in such sophisticated forms of justification themselves. However, if those theorists claim to have normative expertise, can they not identify the correct norms for us? 43 Can they not then use rational persuasion to educate others, that is, to demonstrate that these norms are justifiable? The problem is that there are no recognized normative experts for secularists. For the religious, a priesthood has recognized authority in normative matters. But there is no secular equivalent to this institution. In the case of scientific knowledge, we can identify experts because there is a high degree of convergence and because we can identify specific forms of relevant expertise and specialized knowledge. We know that a powerful microscope will assist in the acquisition of knowledge about microbiology. But there is no normative equivalent of a microscope. And there is much less convergence amongst those who would claim expertise in this area of human knowledge ibid., pp ibid., p.81. I have argued elsewhere that this consequence of secularism was of great concern to Nietzsche. Cf. Tamsin Shaw, Nietzsche s Political Skepticism (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2007). 43 Berlin sees a reliance on experts as essential to the rationalist position. He tells us that Comte put bluntly what had been implicit in the rationalist theory of politics from its ancient Greek beginnings. There can, in principle, be only one correct way of life; the wise lead it spontaneously, that is why they are called wise. The unwise must be dragged towards it by all the social means in the power of the wise; for why should demonstrable error be suffered to survive and breed? cf. Two Concepts of Liberty, Cf. Jeremy Waldron, The Irrelevance of Moral Objectivity, Law and Disagreement (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999),

18 Bernard Williams pours scorn on the idea of such expertise. It is invoked with increasing frequency in questions of medical ethics. Williams tells us that consulting such supposed experts performs a number of functions: it enables ethical considerations to be presented in an institutionally recognizable form, parallel to a consultant s expertise, and as a secular alternative, or addition, to religious opinions. But he finds absurd the idea that we should place any confidence in such judgements: You need to accept some pretty startlingly strong presuppositions if you are to believe in these practices on their own terms. The supposed experts receive their qualifications by taking certain courses in philosophy, in particular in ethical theory and associated devices of casuistry. It is obvious that someone may acquire an excellent PhD in such topics and yet be someone whose judgement you would not trust on anything. 45 And one does not have to be a moral anti-objectivist to share this skepticism. Even if there were indeed people (such as philosophers) who had the relevant intellectual capabilities and were able to ascertain normative truth, most people would still be incapable of recognizing their authority. They would have no reason to defer to any particular individual who claims expertise in this area, for they would not be equipped to assess whose view really should be rationally binding for them. 46 If people are ill-equipped to arrive at normative knowledge by their own lights, they will also be ill-equipped to consider to whom it is rational for them to defer on normative issues. This does not mean that objectivists have to assume that convergence on the correct norms is impossible. There are objectivists who think that the very principles which philosophers find should govern our political lives have in fact been generally accepted, albeit only implicitly, in our political community. This is the view defended by Ronald Dworkin in Is Democracy Possible Here? He holds that two objectively correct, basic political principles, sufficient to ground a legitimate form of politics, are implicit in the normative commitments of most Americans, even though the concrete implications of these principles are disputed Williams, In the Beginning Was the Deed, Cf. Alexander Nehamas, The Art of Living: Socratic Reflections from Plato to Foucault (Berkeley, Los Angeles, London: University of California Press, 1998), Dworkin s view is that although not every American would immediately accept these two principles, still enough Americans on both sides of the supposedly unbridgeable divide would accept them if they took sufficient care to understand them. Cf. Is Democracy Possible Here?, p.7. I take this to mean not that sufficient reflection would require people to alter their fundamental normative commitments, but that the current normative commitments that most people hold would support these principles. 18

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström From: Who Owns Our Genes?, Proceedings of an international conference, October 1999, Tallin, Estonia, The Nordic Committee on Bioethics, 2000. THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström I shall be mainly

More information

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981). Draft of 3-21- 13 PHIL 202: Core Ethics; Winter 2013 Core Sequence in the History of Ethics, 2011-2013 IV: 19 th and 20 th Century Moral Philosophy David O. Brink Handout #14: Williams, Internalism, and

More information

Comment on Martha Nussbaum s Purified Patriotism

Comment on Martha Nussbaum s Purified Patriotism Comment on Martha Nussbaum s Purified Patriotism Patriotism is generally thought to require a special attachment to the particular: to one s own country and to one s fellow citizens. It is therefore thought

More information

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism Mathais Sarrazin J.L. Mackie s Error Theory postulates that all normative claims are false. It does this based upon his denial of moral

More information

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS By MARANATHA JOY HAYES A THESIS PRESENTED TO THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF THE UNIVERSITY OF FLORIDA IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS

More information

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text. Citation: 21 Isr. L. Rev. 113 1986 Content downloaded/printed from HeinOnline (http://heinonline.org) Sun Jan 11 12:34:09 2015 -- Your use of this HeinOnline PDF indicates your acceptance of HeinOnline's

More information

PROVOCATION EVERYONE IS A PHILOSOPHER! T.M. Scanlon

PROVOCATION EVERYONE IS A PHILOSOPHER! T.M. Scanlon PROVOCATION EVERYONE IS A PHILOSOPHER! T.M. Scanlon In the first chapter of his book, Reading Obama, 1 Professor James Kloppenberg offers an account of the intellectual climate at Harvard Law School during

More information

SANDEL ON RELIGION IN THE PUBLIC SQUARE

SANDEL ON RELIGION IN THE PUBLIC SQUARE SANDEL ON RELIGION IN THE PUBLIC SQUARE Hugh Baxter For Boston University School of Law s Conference on Michael Sandel s Justice October 14, 2010 In the final chapter of Justice, Sandel calls for a new

More information

REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET. Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary

REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET. Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary 1 REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary Abstract: Christine Korsgaard argues that a practical reason (that is, a reason that counts in favor of an action) must motivate

More information

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Chapter 98 Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Lars Leeten Universität Hildesheim Practical thinking is a tricky business. Its aim will never be fulfilled unless influence on practical

More information

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY 1 CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY TORBEN SPAAK We have seen (in Section 3) that Hart objects to Austin s command theory of law, that it cannot account for the normativity of law, and that what is missing

More information

Practical Rationality and Ethics. Basic Terms and Positions

Practical Rationality and Ethics. Basic Terms and Positions Practical Rationality and Ethics Basic Terms and Positions Practical reasons and moral ought Reasons are given in answer to the sorts of questions ethics seeks to answer: What should I do? How should I

More information

Well-Being, Time, and Dementia. Jennifer Hawkins. University of Toronto

Well-Being, Time, and Dementia. Jennifer Hawkins. University of Toronto Well-Being, Time, and Dementia Jennifer Hawkins University of Toronto Philosophers often discuss what makes a life as a whole good. More significantly, it is sometimes assumed that beneficence, which is

More information

The Conflict Between Authority and Autonomy from Robert Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (1970)

The Conflict Between Authority and Autonomy from Robert Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (1970) The Conflict Between Authority and Autonomy from Robert Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (1970) 1. The Concept of Authority Politics is the exercise of the power of the state, or the attempt to influence

More information

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have served as the point of departure for much of the most interesting work that

More information

Seth Mayer. Comments on Christopher McCammon s Is Liberal Legitimacy Utopian?

Seth Mayer. Comments on Christopher McCammon s Is Liberal Legitimacy Utopian? Seth Mayer Comments on Christopher McCammon s Is Liberal Legitimacy Utopian? Christopher McCammon s defense of Liberal Legitimacy hopes to give a negative answer to the question posed by the title of his

More information

Introduction: the original position and The Original Position an overview

Introduction: the original position and The Original Position an overview Introduction: the original position and The Original Position an overview Timothy Hinton John Rawls s idea of the original position arguably the centerpiece of his theory of justice has proved to have

More information

Philosophy in Review XXXIII (2013), no. 5

Philosophy in Review XXXIII (2013), no. 5 Robert Stern Understanding Moral Obligation. Kant, Hegel, Kierkegaard. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 2012. 277 pages $90.00 (cloth ISBN 978 1 107 01207 3) In his thoroughly researched and tightly

More information

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Ralph Wedgwood 1 Two views of practical reason Suppose that you are faced with several different options (that is, several ways in which you might act in a

More information

Disagreement and the Duties of Citizenship. Japa Pallikkathayil

Disagreement and the Duties of Citizenship. Japa Pallikkathayil Disagreement and the Duties of Citizenship Japa Pallikkathayil Political liberalism holds that some kinds of disagreement give rise to a duty of restraint. On this view, citizens ought to limit the considerations

More information

Compromise and Toleration: Some Reflections I. Introduction

Compromise and Toleration: Some Reflections  I. Introduction Compromise and Toleration: Some Reflections Christian F. Rostbøll Paper for Årsmøde i Dansk Selskab for Statskundskab, 29-30 Oct. 2015. Kolding. (The following is not a finished paper but some preliminary

More information

DEMOCRACY, DELIBERATION, AND RATIONALITY Guido Pincione & Fernando R. Tesón

DEMOCRACY, DELIBERATION, AND RATIONALITY Guido Pincione & Fernando R. Tesón 1 Copyright 2005 Guido Pincione and Fernando R. Tesón DEMOCRACY, DELIBERATION, AND RATIONALITY Guido Pincione & Fernando R. Tesón Cambridge University Press, forthcoming CHAPTER 1. INTRODUCTION CONTENTS

More information

4 Liberty, Rationality, and Agency in Hobbes s Leviathan

4 Liberty, Rationality, and Agency in Hobbes s Leviathan 1 Introduction Thomas Hobbes, at first glance, provides a coherent and easily identifiable concept of liberty. He seems to argue that agents are free to the extent that they are unimpeded in their actions

More information

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z.   Notes ETHICS - A - Z Absolutism Act-utilitarianism Agent-centred consideration Agent-neutral considerations : This is the view, with regard to a moral principle or claim, that it holds everywhere and is never

More information

Take Home Exam #2. PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert

Take Home Exam #2. PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert Name: Date: Take Home Exam #2 Instructions (Read Before Proceeding!) Material for this exam is from class sessions 8-15. Matching and fill-in-the-blank questions

More information

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Version 1.1 Richard Baron 2 October 2016 1 Contents 1 Introduction 3 1.1 Availability and licence............ 3 2 Definitions of key terms 4 3

More information

No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships

No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships In his book Practical Ethics, Peter Singer advocates preference utilitarianism, which holds that the right

More information

Oxford Scholarship Online

Oxford Scholarship Online University Press Scholarship Online Oxford Scholarship Online The Quality of Life Martha Nussbaum and Amartya Sen Print publication date: 1993 Print ISBN-13: 9780198287971 Published to Oxford Scholarship

More information

Comment on Robert Audi, Democratic Authority and the Separation of Church and State

Comment on Robert Audi, Democratic Authority and the Separation of Church and State Weithman 1. Comment on Robert Audi, Democratic Authority and the Separation of Church and State Among the tasks of liberal democratic theory are the identification and defense of political principles that

More information

Skepticism and Internalism

Skepticism and Internalism Skepticism and Internalism John Greco Abstract: This paper explores a familiar skeptical problematic and considers some strategies for responding to it. Section 1 reconstructs and disambiguates the skeptical

More information

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to: Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS MGT604 CHAPTER OBJECTIVES After exploring this chapter, you will be able to: 1. Explain the ethical framework of utilitarianism. 2. Describe how utilitarian

More information

Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social

Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social position one ends up occupying, while John Harsanyi s version of the veil tells contractors that they are equally likely

More information

Legal Positivism: the Separation and Identification theses are true.

Legal Positivism: the Separation and Identification theses are true. PHL271 Handout 3: Hart on Legal Positivism 1 Legal Positivism Revisited HLA Hart was a highly sophisticated philosopher. His defence of legal positivism marked a watershed in 20 th Century philosophy of

More information

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction 24 Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Abstract: In this paper, I address Linda Zagzebski s analysis of the relation between moral testimony and understanding arguing that Aquinas

More information

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6 SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6 Textbook: Louis P. Pojman, Editor. Philosophy: The quest for truth. New York: Oxford University Press, 2006. ISBN-10: 0199697310; ISBN-13: 9780199697311 (6th Edition)

More information

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS SECOND SECTION by Immanuel Kant TRANSITION FROM POPULAR MORAL PHILOSOPHY TO THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS... This principle, that humanity and generally every

More information

On the Relevance of Ignorance to the Demands of Morality 1

On the Relevance of Ignorance to the Demands of Morality 1 3 On the Relevance of Ignorance to the Demands of Morality 1 Geoffrey Sayre-McCord It is impossible to overestimate the amount of stupidity in the world. Bernard Gert 2 Introduction In Morality, Bernard

More information

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006 In Defense of Radical Empiricism Joseph Benjamin Riegel A thesis submitted to the faculty of the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of

More information

The Need for Metanormativity: A Response to Christmas

The Need for Metanormativity: A Response to Christmas The Need for Metanormativity: A Response to Christmas Douglas J. Den Uyl Liberty Fund, Inc. Douglas B. Rasmussen St. John s University We would like to begin by thanking Billy Christmas for his excellent

More information

Kantian Constructivism, Baseball and Christian Ethics. part of it, about physics, about morality or some of its parts, about reasons or normativity.

Kantian Constructivism, Baseball and Christian Ethics. part of it, about physics, about morality or some of its parts, about reasons or normativity. Kantian Constructivism, Baseball and Christian Ethics One can be a constructivist about any or all of a number of domains: about mathematics or some part of it, about physics, about morality or some of

More information

Kant and his Successors

Kant and his Successors Kant and his Successors G. J. Mattey Winter, 2011 / Philosophy 151 The Sorry State of Metaphysics Kant s Critique of Pure Reason (1781) was an attempt to put metaphysics on a scientific basis. Metaphysics

More information

In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of

In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of Glasgow s Conception of Kantian Humanity Richard Dean ABSTRACT: In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of the humanity formulation of the Categorical Imperative.

More information

On the Rawlsian Anthropology and the "Autonomous" Account

On the Rawlsian Anthropology and the Autonomous Account University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor Critical Reflections Essays of Significance & Critical Reflections 2017 Mar 31st, 10:30 AM - 11:00 AM On the Rawlsian Anthropology and the "Autonomous" Account

More information

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality. On Modal Personism Shelly Kagan s essay on speciesism has the virtues characteristic of his work in general: insight, originality, clarity, cleverness, wit, intuitive plausibility, argumentative rigor,

More information

A Contractualist Reply

A Contractualist Reply A Contractualist Reply The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Scanlon, T. M. 2008. A Contractualist Reply.

More information

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1 DOUBTS ABOUT UNCERTAINTY WITHOUT ALL THE DOUBT NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH Norby s paper is divided into three main sections in which he introduces the storage hypothesis, gives reasons for rejecting it and then

More information

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000) Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000) One of the advantages traditionally claimed for direct realist theories of perception over indirect realist theories is that the

More information

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements ANALYSIS 59.3 JULY 1999 Moral requirements are still not rational requirements Paul Noordhof According to Michael Smith, the Rationalist makes the following conceptual claim. If it is right for agents

More information

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism 1 Dogmatism Last class we looked at Jim Pryor s paper on dogmatism about perceptual justification (for background on the notion of justification, see the handout

More information

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES Bart Streumer b.streumer@rug.nl In David Bakhurst, Brad Hooker and Margaret Little (eds.), Thinking About Reasons: Essays in Honour of Jonathan

More information

Evolution and the Possibility of Moral Realism

Evolution and the Possibility of Moral Realism Evolution and the Possibility of Moral Realism PETER CARRUTHERS 1 University of Maryland SCOTT M. JAMES University of Kentucky Richard Joyce covers a great deal of ground in his well-informed, insightful,

More information

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law Marianne Vahl Master Thesis in Philosophy Supervisor Olav Gjelsvik Department of Philosophy, Classics, History of Arts and Ideas UNIVERSITY OF OSLO May

More information

Two Approaches to Natural Law;Note

Two Approaches to Natural Law;Note Notre Dame Law School NDLScholarship Natural Law Forum 1-1-1956 Two Approaches to Natural Law;Note Vernon J. Bourke Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.nd.edu/nd_naturallaw_forum

More information

Philosophical Review.

Philosophical Review. Philosophical Review Review: [untitled] Author(s): John Martin Fischer Source: The Philosophical Review, Vol. 98, No. 2 (Apr., 1989), pp. 254-257 Published by: Duke University Press on behalf of Philosophical

More information

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI Michael HUEMER ABSTRACT: I address Moti Mizrahi s objections to my use of the Self-Defeat Argument for Phenomenal Conservatism (PC). Mizrahi contends

More information

To link to this article:

To link to this article: This article was downloaded by: [University of Chicago Library] On: 24 May 2013, At: 08:10 Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office:

More information

The form of relativism that says that whether an agent s actions are right or wrong depends on the moral principles accepted in her own society.

The form of relativism that says that whether an agent s actions are right or wrong depends on the moral principles accepted in her own society. Glossary of Terms: Act-consequentialism Actual Duty Actual Value Agency Condition Agent Relativism Amoralist Appraisal Relativism A form of direct consequentialism according to which the rightness and

More information

Here's a rough guide to topics that we discussed in class and that may come up in the exam.

Here's a rough guide to topics that we discussed in class and that may come up in the exam. Contemporary Civilization ~ Fall 2004 STUDY GUIDE FOR FINAL EXAM Here's a rough guide to topics that we discussed in class and that may come up in the exam. Mediaeval Philosophy General problem common

More information

A lonelier contractualism A. J. Julius, UCLA, January

A lonelier contractualism A. J. Julius, UCLA, January A lonelier contractualism A. J. Julius, UCLA, January 15 2008 1. A definition A theory of some normative domain is contractualist if, having said what it is for a person to accept a principle in that domain,

More information

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory Western University Scholarship@Western 2015 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2015 Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory David Hakim Western University, davidhakim266@gmail.com

More information

PRÉCIS THE ORDER OF PUBLIC REASON: A THEORY OF FREEDOM AND MORALITY IN A DIVERSE AND BOUNDED WORLD

PRÉCIS THE ORDER OF PUBLIC REASON: A THEORY OF FREEDOM AND MORALITY IN A DIVERSE AND BOUNDED WORLD EuJAP Vol. 9 No. 1 2013 PRÉCIS THE ORDER OF PUBLIC REASON: A THEORY OF FREEDOM AND MORALITY IN A DIVERSE AND BOUNDED WORLD GERALD GAUS University of Arizona This work advances a theory that forms a unified

More information

Is God Good By Definition?

Is God Good By Definition? 1 Is God Good By Definition? by Graham Oppy As a matter of historical fact, most philosophers and theologians who have defended traditional theistic views have been moral realists. Some divine command

More information

In this response, I will bring to light a fascinating, and in some ways hopeful, irony

In this response, I will bring to light a fascinating, and in some ways hopeful, irony Response: The Irony of It All Nicholas Wolterstorff In this response, I will bring to light a fascinating, and in some ways hopeful, irony embedded in the preceding essays on human rights, when they are

More information

Knowledge and True Opinion in Plato s Meno

Knowledge and True Opinion in Plato s Meno Knowledge and True Opinion in Plato s Meno Ariel Weiner In Plato s dialogue, the Meno, Socrates inquires into how humans may become virtuous, and, corollary to that, whether humans have access to any form

More information

Rawls, rationality, and responsibility: Why we should not treat our endowments as morally arbitrary

Rawls, rationality, and responsibility: Why we should not treat our endowments as morally arbitrary Rawls, rationality, and responsibility: Why we should not treat our endowments as morally arbitrary OLIVER DUROSE Abstract John Rawls is primarily known for providing his own argument for how political

More information

A CONSEQUENTIALIST RESPONSE TO THE DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Nicholas R. Baker, Lee University THE DEMANDS OF ACT CONSEQUENTIALISM

A CONSEQUENTIALIST RESPONSE TO THE DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Nicholas R. Baker, Lee University THE DEMANDS OF ACT CONSEQUENTIALISM 1 A CONSEQUENTIALIST RESPONSE TO THE DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Nicholas R. Baker, Lee University INTRODUCTION We usually believe that morality has limits; that is, that there is some limit to what morality

More information

Does law have to be effective in order for it to be valid?

Does law have to be effective in order for it to be valid? University of Birmingham Birmingham Law School Jurisprudence 2007-08 Assessed Essay (Second Round) Does law have to be effective in order for it to be valid? It is important to consider the terms valid

More information

Equality, Fairness, and Responsibility in an Unequal World

Equality, Fairness, and Responsibility in an Unequal World Equality, Fairness, and Responsibility in an Unequal World Thom Brooks Abstract: Severe poverty is a major global problem about risk and inequality. What, if any, is the relationship between equality,

More information

Convergence liberalism and the problem of disagreement concerning public justification*

Convergence liberalism and the problem of disagreement concerning public justification* Convergence liberalism and the problem of disagreement concerning public justification* Paul Billingham Christ Church, University of Oxford Abstract The convergence conception of political liberalism has

More information

BERNARD WILLIAMS S INTERNALISM: A NEW INTERPRETATION. Micah J Baize

BERNARD WILLIAMS S INTERNALISM: A NEW INTERPRETATION. Micah J Baize BERNARD WILLIAMS S INTERNALISM: A NEW INTERPRETATION By Copyright 2012 Micah J Baize Submitted to the graduate degree program in Philosophy and the Graduate Faculty of the University of Kansas in partial

More information

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords ISBN 9780198802693 Title The Value of Rationality Author(s) Ralph Wedgwood Book abstract Book keywords Rationality is a central concept for epistemology,

More information

Mark Schroeder. Slaves of the Passions. Melissa Barry Hume Studies Volume 36, Number 2 (2010), 225-228. Your use of the HUME STUDIES archive indicates your acceptance of HUME STUDIES Terms and Conditions

More information

CLIMBING THE MOUNTAIN SUMMARY CHAPTER 1 REASONS. 1 Practical Reasons

CLIMBING THE MOUNTAIN SUMMARY CHAPTER 1 REASONS. 1 Practical Reasons CLIMBING THE MOUNTAIN SUMMARY CHAPTER 1 REASONS 1 Practical Reasons We are the animals that can understand and respond to reasons. Facts give us reasons when they count in favour of our having some belief

More information

A note on reciprocity of reasons

A note on reciprocity of reasons 1 A note on reciprocity of reasons 1. Introduction Authors like Rainer Forst and Stephan Gosepath claim that moral or political normative claims, widely conceived, depend for their validity, or justification,

More information

Agreement-Based Practical Justification: A Comment on Wolff

Agreement-Based Practical Justification: A Comment on Wolff SYMPOSIUM PUBLIC ETHICS Agreement-Based Practical Justification: A Comment on Wolff BY FABIENNE PETER 2014 Philosophy and Public Issues (New Series), Vol. 4, No. 3 (2014): 37-51 Luiss University Press

More information

8 Internal and external reasons

8 Internal and external reasons ioo Rawls and Pascal's wager out how under-powered the supposed rational choice under ignorance is. Rawls' theory tries, in effect, to link politics with morality, and morality (or at least the relevant

More information

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism What is a great mistake? Nietzsche once said that a great error is worth more than a multitude of trivial truths. A truly great mistake

More information

Adam Smith and the Limits of Empiricism

Adam Smith and the Limits of Empiricism Adam Smith and the Limits of Empiricism In the debate between rationalism and sentimentalism, one of the strongest weapons in the rationalist arsenal is the notion that some of our actions ought to be

More information

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary Moral Objectivism RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary The possibility, let alone the actuality, of an objective morality has intrigued philosophers for well over two millennia. Though much discussed,

More information

Reasons With Rationalism After All MICHAEL SMITH

Reasons With Rationalism After All MICHAEL SMITH book symposium 521 Bratman, M.E. Forthcoming a. Intention, belief, practical, theoretical. In Spheres of Reason: New Essays on the Philosophy of Normativity, ed. Simon Robertson. Oxford: Oxford University

More information

1/12. The A Paralogisms

1/12. The A Paralogisms 1/12 The A Paralogisms The character of the Paralogisms is described early in the chapter. Kant describes them as being syllogisms which contain no empirical premises and states that in them we conclude

More information

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141 Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141 Dialectic: For Hegel, dialectic is a process governed by a principle of development, i.e., Reason

More information

PHL271 Handout 2: Hobbes on Law and Political Authority. Many philosophers of law treat Hobbes as the grandfather of legal positivism.

PHL271 Handout 2: Hobbes on Law and Political Authority. Many philosophers of law treat Hobbes as the grandfather of legal positivism. PHL271 Handout 2: Hobbes on Law and Political Authority 1 Background: Legal Positivism Many philosophers of law treat Hobbes as the grandfather of legal positivism. Legal Positivism (Rough Version): whether

More information

Scanlon on Double Effect

Scanlon on Double Effect Scanlon on Double Effect RALPH WEDGWOOD Merton College, University of Oxford In this new book Moral Dimensions, T. M. Scanlon (2008) explores the ethical significance of the intentions and motives with

More information

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge Colorado State University BIBLID [0873-626X (2012) 33; pp. 459-467] Abstract According to rationalists about moral knowledge, some moral truths are knowable a

More information

We recommend you cite the published version. The publisher s URL is:

We recommend you cite the published version. The publisher s URL is: Cole, P. (2014) Reactions & Debate II: The Ethics of Immigration - Carens and the problem of method. Ethical Perspectives, 21 (4). pp. 600-607. ISSN 1370-0049 Available from: http://eprints.uwe.ac.uk/27941

More information

A CONTRACTUALIST READING OF KANT S PROOF OF THE FORMULA OF HUMANITY. Adam Cureton

A CONTRACTUALIST READING OF KANT S PROOF OF THE FORMULA OF HUMANITY. Adam Cureton A CONTRACTUALIST READING OF KANT S PROOF OF THE FORMULA OF HUMANITY Adam Cureton Abstract: Kant offers the following argument for the Formula of Humanity: Each rational agent necessarily conceives of her

More information

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Res Cogitans Volume 5 Issue 1 Article 20 6-4-2014 Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Kevin Harriman Lewis & Clark College Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans

More information

TWO APPROACHES TO INSTRUMENTAL RATIONALITY

TWO APPROACHES TO INSTRUMENTAL RATIONALITY TWO APPROACHES TO INSTRUMENTAL RATIONALITY AND BELIEF CONSISTENCY BY JOHN BRUNERO JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY VOL. 1, NO. 1 APRIL 2005 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT JOHN BRUNERO 2005 I N SPEAKING

More information

A Social Practice View of Natural Rights. Word Count: 2998

A Social Practice View of Natural Rights. Word Count: 2998 A Social Practice View of Natural Rights Word Count: 2998 Hume observes in the Treatise that the rules, by which properties, rights, and obligations are determin d, have in them no marks of a natural origin,

More information

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY DISCUSSION NOTE BY JONATHAN WAY JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE DECEMBER 2009 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT JONATHAN WAY 2009 Two Accounts of the Normativity of Rationality RATIONALITY

More information

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature Introduction The philosophical controversy about free will and determinism is perennial. Like many perennial controversies, this one involves a tangle of distinct but closely related issues. Thus, the

More information

Compatibilist Objections to Prepunishment

Compatibilist Objections to Prepunishment Florida Philosophical Review Volume X, Issue 1, Summer 2010 7 Compatibilist Objections to Prepunishment Winner of the Outstanding Graduate Paper Award at the 55 th Annual Meeting of the Florida Philosophical

More information

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran Abstract In his (2015) paper, Robert Lockie seeks to add a contextualized, relativist

More information

Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan

Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan 1 Possible People Suppose that whatever one does a new person will come into existence. But one can determine who this person will be by either

More information

Ethical Theory for Catholic Professionals

Ethical Theory for Catholic Professionals The Linacre Quarterly Volume 53 Number 1 Article 9 February 1986 Ethical Theory for Catholic Professionals James F. Drane Follow this and additional works at: http://epublications.marquette.edu/lnq Recommended

More information

Socratic and Platonic Ethics

Socratic and Platonic Ethics Socratic and Platonic Ethics G. J. Mattey Winter, 2017 / Philosophy 1 Ethics and Political Philosophy The first part of the course is a brief survey of important texts in the history of ethics and political

More information

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1 310 Book Review Book Review ISSN (Print) 1225-4924, ISSN (Online) 2508-3104 Catholic Theology and Thought, Vol. 79, July 2017 http://dx.doi.org/10.21731/ctat.2017.79.310 A Review on What Is This Thing

More information

Legitimacy, Democracy and Public Justification: Rawls Political Liberalism Versus Gaus Justificatory Liberalism

Legitimacy, Democracy and Public Justification: Rawls Political Liberalism Versus Gaus Justificatory Liberalism Res Publica (2014) 20:9 25 DOI 10.1007/s11158-013-9223-9 Legitimacy, Democracy and Public Justification: Rawls Political Liberalism Versus Gaus Justificatory Liberalism Enzo Rossi Published online: 13

More information

Universal Injuries Need Not Wound Internal Values A Response to Wysman

Universal Injuries Need Not Wound Internal Values A Response to Wysman A Response to Wysman Jordan Bartol In his recent article, Internal Injuries: Some Further Concerns with Intercultural and Transhistorical Critique, Colin Wysman provides a response to my (2008) article,

More information