Rethinking the Republic

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Rethinking the Republic"

Transcription

1 Rethinking the Republic The stated purpose of Plato s Republic is to address the nature of justice. The conventional scholarly view is that Plato makes claims (via Socrates) about two instantiations of justice: justice of the ideal city and justice of the soul. In other words, Plato makes a political claim and ethical claim. The conventional view also asserts that the claim about justice in the city helps support the claim about justice in the soul. Thus, the political claim is made both for its own sake and in support of the ethical claim. In what follows I propose that the conventional view is correct on these overarching points but fails to adequately treat a certain aspect of the Republic: the (seemingly) dystopian elements that Socrates includes in his description of the ideal city. Drawing upon the treatment of these elements by a rival interpretation that espoused by Leo Strauss I conclude that the presence of these features in Socrates account of justice can actually bolster both the central intuitions of the conventional interpretation and the core argument that it attributes to Plato. I The purpose of the political elements of the Republic is typically held to be two-fold: Plato intends through the argumentation of Socrates to demonstrate both that the aristocratic city is the ideal city and that it is feasible. 1 This aristocratic city is the ideal city if and only if it is in every way just and in no way unjust. 2 It is feasible if there is a reasonable chance that it could come into being at the present time or some future time given the conditions of the phenomenal world. 3 Socrates commitment to the first goal is seen clearly at 368d-369a and his commitment to the second at 540d. 4 In the latter passage he poses the question, Do you agree that the things we have said about the city and its constitution are not altogether wishful thinking; that it is difficult for them to come about, but possible in a way? 5 Socrates proposed ideal city, the Kallipolis, would be ruled exclusively by a group of philosopher kings whose unique access to the Form of the Good gives them and them alone the requisite knowledge to rule in a maximally just fashion. Taken together, 473b and 473d suggest that Socrates holds the rule of philosopher kings to be both a necessary and sufficient condition for the ideal city. 6 It will only be the maximally just city if they rule, and their rule alone is enough to make it maximally just. Scholars tend to agree, however, that something is amiss in Socrates aristocratic city. At the least, several specific policies that he proposes for the city appear quite radical and have been identified as such by some of the foremost thinkers in the discourse. Karl Popper asserts that the Republic is nothing short of a carefully crafted blueprint for the imposition of a rigid class hierarchy through downright totalitarian means. 7 Julia Annas claims something similar when she 1 Morrison Ibid. 3 See Marshall Ibid. 5 Plato 540d. Herein I quote from Reeve s translation of the Republic. 6 Morrison Schofield 195.

2 says, Plato has no real notion of rights. 8 Even C.D.C. Reeve, who defends Socrates proposal with considerable rigor, admits that the city appears at least prima facie to be authoritarian and repressive. 9 And it is hard to deny White s claim that the residents of Kallipolis would object to the institutions in force there. 10 Criticisms of the dystopian elements of the Socratic proposal are common, but one voice in particular moves from criticism to a decidedly deeper level of analysis. This voice is Leo Straus, who holds that the result of Plato s attempt to conceive of the just city is so radical and unappealing (especially for his time) that his efforts cannot possibly be serious. Rather, he has depicted a comic fantasy designed to lead us to the conclusion that any attempt to reconstruct the realm of the political on rationalist lines would generate a dystopia built on injustice, as one commentator has put it. 11 Strauss holds that Plato s true purpose is to purge the attentive reader of unrealistic utopian ideals by presenting the monstrous absurdity that such aspirations ultimately lead to. What, specifically, are these unsavory characteristics of Kallipolis? At the very least, they include the proposal for communal sexual and familial relations 12 and the pseudo-eugenic policies 13 proposed by Socrates and his interlocutors. The former notion has women and children held in common among the men of the guardian class, and the latter has persons with unfit bodies left to die and persons with unfit souls executed. The banishment of poetry 14 and Socrates proposed constraints on imitative art in general are also objected to by some readers. Additionally, there is the issue of female guardians. 15 In modern society such a thing is of course normal and accepted, but in Plato s day it would have been quite a radical proposal. There is some debate in contemporary scholarship with regard to this last point, but it is at least still a candidate for inclusion. (At any rate, the argument that the Republic contains significant dystopian elements does not hinge upon this last point.) Even if the presence of female guardians in the city would have been acceptable to Plato s contemporaries, the other elements present a great difficulty. They are extreme proposals, and Plato would have known this. The Straussian contention is that he can therefore not have made them seriously. This suggestion carries at least some initial plausibility and is further strengthened by the conventional interpretation s rather monolithic suggestion that Plato simply held the views in question. The conventional take on these questions is certainly not out of bounds as a possibility, but Strauss demand that we not be so hasty in the face of an intellect as formidable as Plato s is difficult to resist. The Straussian view is itself problematic as well, however, though this is not because it asserts that there are ironical claims in the Republic when it comes to certain facets of the city. On the contrary, Strauss has strong reasons for proceeding as he does. The difficulty with his view is rather that it moves too hastily from this recognition to a generalization about Plato s entire project. The identification of sexual communism, eugenics, censorship, and female guardianship as arguments from absurdity is would certainly seem tenable given Plato s 8 Annas 334. She here makes an assumption typical of modern interpretation of Plato, namely that the views espoused by Socrates are Plato s own. I follow suit in this essay, at least initially (for reasons that will become clear in what follows). 9 Reeve White Schofield Plato 5.457c-d. 13 Ibid a. 14 Annas Plato 5.451d-452a.

3 intelligence. 16 It is a mistake, though, to imply that intentional absurdity of this sort could serve only the function that Strauss ascribes to it: conveying the point that the political proposals in the Republic are wholly misguided. If we are to treat the absurdities as evidence for some claim one Plato s part, the question as to what that claim is remains an open one. Strauss rigidly allows for only one conclusion: that a city ruled by philosopher kings is unjust and unrealistic. It is well worth investigating, though, whether there is a different conclusion that the dystopian features might lead to. II It is important to first identify the general thrust of both the conventional and Straussian interpretations of the Republic and to establish which assumptions they have in common and where they part company with one other. The conventional interpretation takes Socrates at his word and equates his views in the narrative with Plato s, and so attributes to Plato the following aristocratic thesis: A city ruled by philosopher kings would be maximally just. The Straussian interpretation takes Socrates to be speaking ironically throughout the dialogue, and so attributes to Plato the following dystopian thesis: The city described by Socrates is not maximally just. Despite initial appearances, these two theses are in themselves perfectly compatible with one another. Both can be attributed to Plato without attributing to him a logical contradiction. A contradiction arises only when they are combined with an additional claim, namely, the following consequence thesis: The city described by Socrates would in fact result from the rule of philosopher kings. Together, of course, the three theses would entail a contradiction. Assuming that Plato would have been aware of this, he cannot be interpreted as having sincerely made all three claims. For the reasons mentioned above, Strauss denies that Plato genuinely holds the consequence thesis. The Straussian interpretation thus attributes both the dystopian and consequence theses to Plato. The conventional scholarship, by contrast, denies that Plato should be regarding as assenting to the dystopian thesis. It may be granted that some of the apparently dystopian aspects of the Republic are unsavory, but Plato either did not recognize this or did but held that they were justified because they attained some greater good, such as unity in the city. The conventional scholarship, then, attributes to him the aristocracy and consequence theses. Of course, in assessing the truth of the three views most scholars hold some combination of the aristocracy and consequence theses be false and the dystopian thesis to be true. 17 But the issue here is not the truth of the views, but whether or not they can be rightly attributed to Plato, and the possibility that he may have sincerely held both the aristocracy and dystopian theses seems to have been largely overlooked. The initial temptation is to identify the two as in tension 16 Only tenable, though: some greater intuitive similarity between Plato and contemporary thinkers would be necessary to close this loop. See Editor s Note after this essay for more. Ed. 17 Morrison 242.

4 with one another. However, further examination reveals a simple explanation for why this is the case. It is only because both sides take the consequence thesis to be axiomatic that the tension appears. The conventional scholarship provides strong reasons for attributing the aristocracy to him, and Strauss provides strong reasons for attributing the dystopian thesis as well. But what grounds are there for attributing the consequence thesis to Plato? It seems that what basis there may be does not outweigh the strength of the reasons in favor of attributing the aristocracy and dystopian theses to him. So it would seem, prima facie, that of the three claims, the consequence thesis could easily be jettisoned to avoid contradiction. III Consider, first, Plato s method of locating justice in the city through Socrates. There will be justice within the individual, but also in the city as a whole. 18 Because the city is larger, the task will be easier if conducted there. Socrates plan is therefore to find justice first in the city, which will in turn allow him to locate it within the soul. 19 The political claim is thus intended to provide support for the ethical claim. 20 However, this does not entail that the ethical investigation will not likewise bear on its political counterpart. On the contrary, only once justice has been identified in both places through the overall investigative method will Socrates be certain that he found justice in either of them. The implication of this is crucial: comparing the two instances of justice will help us better understand not only justice itself, but also each instantiation. The next natural step is to examine the Platonic view of the soul, which has it consisting of three parts: the appetitive, the spirited, and the rational. In the same way that Kallipolis is maximally just only when each group performs its proper role, the tripartite soul is maximally just only when each part performs its proper function. The appetitive part deals with base desires like hunger and thirst, yearning to fulfill them. The spirited part deals with social desires and so yearns for such things as fame and honor. The rational part, though, concerns itself only with goodness. Each part thus has its own important domain, just as each class of the Kallipolis has its own important social role. But as in the Kallipolis, the soul must have a ruler, and this ruler must be concerned only with goodness itself. Thus reason is the proper ruler of the soul, and it follows that the just soul is ruled by reason. It will still have appetitive and spirited urges that need to be fulfilled, of course, but this fulfillment will come in a way consistent with the dictates of reason in the same way that the warriors and producers of the Kallipolis perform their functions in a way consistent with the rule and policies of the philosopher kings. IV In contrast to much of modern moral philosophy, Plato s theory is agent-centered. The call to a just life is purported to be an intelligible demand on human nature, something in accordance with our potentialities for living creative and fulfilling lives. 21 For Plato, virtuous actions are a natural product of well-developed character it matters, and matters morally, what kind of person you are. 22 This breaks radically with action-centered moral theories, which place an arbitrary set of external demands on human nature with little attention to that nature itself. 23 Action-centered theories focus on obligatory actions. Plato, by contrast, concerns himself with the character of the agent. Those with a just soul will act justly. There is little need for an 18 Plato 368e. 19 Ibid. 368e-369a. 20 Reeve Ibid. 22 Ibid Ibid 331.

5 account of just action (indeed, the difficulties involved in formulating such an account are a major motivation for Plato s view); the focus is instead on how one becomes internally just. Once this is achieved, proper external conduct will follow. Plato is thus a character-utilitarian, to use C.D.C. Reeves term. 24 Where there are just souls, there is moral goodness. Where there are unjust souls, there is moral wrongness. In practice, this moral value will be manifested both internally and externally. The just soul is good both because it exists as a valuable entity and because it performs just actions. The soul and its outworking both have moral status; Plato s key move, though, is to make the status of the outworking largely dependent on that of the soul. In doing so, he escapes the need for an exhaustive account of just external action because in a sense, one has already been provided: put the soul in the right state, says Plato, and what follows will be just action. It will now be helpful to recall that each instantiation of justice allows us to better understand the other, and that this is an explicit claim of the text. Socrates does not merely offer the political claim in support of the ethical claim, but offers the ethical claim in such a way that it can shed additional light on its political counterpart. The relevant lesson of the ethical claim is this: internal justice of the soul leads to just external action, and internal justice is achieved through the rule of reason. The precise form that this just external action will actually take is not a primary concern. Indeed, one will not be in a position to know what that form will be until one possesses a just soul. In the same way, the justice of the city has its basis in the rule of the philosopher kings. It is this internal feature of the city alone that makes it just. V The methods by which the philosopher kings governs will be just by virtue of the fact that they are policies of philosopher kings in a properly organized city; the actions of a soul will be just if they stem from the dictates of reason in a properly organized soul. In other words, the policies of the philosopher kings are analogous to choices that a soul governed by reason will perform. The policies themselves are not a primary concern, however, because their precise nature cannot be reliably expounded until philosopher kings are actually in power to implement them. Indeed, this was the whole point of putting philosopher kings in power in the first place: they are far better equipped to rule than anyone else. The implications of this are far-reaching. This means that for the city as well as the soul, there are two sorts of claims: claims about how to organize the city justly (in other words, who to place in positions of power), and claims about how the city will be ruled once it is so organized. Socrates asserts that he is able to offer reliable claims of the first type. But it is difficult to see how he could make the second sort of claim with a similar degree of reliability. The ethical theory he advocates does not concern itself with claims of the second sort. Such reliability comes only when one s soul is properly organized. In the same way, his political theory cannot concern itself with the second sort of claims either. Socrates can plausibly be said to have reliable information about how to organize a city such that it will be maximally just: by putting philosophers in power. But he cannot make reliable claims regarding how the philosopher kings will rule, because, as he repeatedly insists, he does not know the Good, whereas philosopher kings would. 25 Indeed, the need for the philosopher kings is predicated upon their having knowledge of how to rule that all others lack. If Socrates either the 24 Reeve Morrison 240.

6 historical figure or the Platonic character were made tyrant, he would make a mess of things straightaway according to his very own assertions. 26 As one who is not a philosopher king, Socrates cannot (on his own view) claim to be a reliable guide to issues of this second sort. Yet he seemingly does just that. He advocates specific policies that he allegedly holds to be best for the city, namely, sexual communism, eugenics, censorship, and guardianship of women. But to a philosopher king, Socrates conception of the city would be of little use. 27 He lacks the privileged access to the Forms that philosopher kings are supposed to have, and so is not in a position to assert with reliability what policies they would put into effect. This follows so clearly from the central argument (as well as Socrates stated reasons for making the central argument in the first place) that it would be quite farfetched to hold that Plato is not aware of it. It seems equally strange, then, to attribute the consequence thesis to Plato. A satisfactory interpretation will need to chart a different path. VI Straussian readings can of course present this implication as another piece of support for their dystopian conclusion. But this causes them to fall quite short in accounting for the evidence that Plato s overarching goal of giving an account of justice is a sincere one. Thus they cannot attribute the aristocracy thesis to Plato even though it seems very hard to make sense of the narrative structure of the text without so doing. Conventional commentators deal with the dystopian features in a number of ways, ranging from the claim that Socrates conception is intended to motivate political action on the part of his interlocutors to the view that it is to serve as a rough outline to be improved upon by the philosopher kings who come to power. This, however, precludes attribution of the dystopian thesis to Plato. As the previous section has shown, this is nearly as problematic as the Straussian failure to leave room for attribution of the aristocracy thesis. As should be clear by this point, a view that synthesizes the conventional interpretation s attribution of the aristocracy thesis and the Straussian interpretation s attribution of the dystopian thesis is therefore in order. Jettisoning the consequence thesis makes such a position possible. VII The question, then, is this: how can one hold that Plato is genuine in his overall project of describing justice in the city but ironic in furnishing certain examples of that justice? The answer may be the general political claims about the composition of the just city are sincere and the specific political claims about what the policies of a city so composed would be are not sincere. The specific political claims are purposefully made radical and unappealing in order to illustrate the need for philosopher kings. They highlight the futility of even attempting to fully conceive of the ideal city without the noetic access (knowledge of the Good) that Socrates insists he lacks. Just as Plato s ethics are concerned almost exclusively with getting one s soul in the right sort of state, so Plato s political theory is concerned almost exclusively with getting the right sort of ruler in power. His primary political concern is not with the actions such a ruler will take in a precise set of circumstances in the same way that his primary ethical concern is not with the actions that a just soul will take in a precise set of circumstances. The specific political claims thus turn out to be arguments from absurdity after all: they illustrate the absurdity of playing philosopher king when one lacks the requisite knowledge of the Form of the Good. The results are preposterous and even dangerous. 26 Ibid. 27 Ibid 244.

7 Only a fool would pretend to have knowledge that he or she does not when the stakes are as high as there are in the case of Kallipolis. By asserting that each instantiation of justice can be of assistance in understanding the other, Plato allows the attentive reader to use the epistemic limitations of the ethical theory to confirm his or her suspicions about similar limits on the political theory. Coupled with his statements about the unique position of philosopher kings with regard to ruling, this casts Socrates specific political claims as absurdities. The question of whether or not the character Socrates is himself aware of this remains open. Does Plato make Socrates look foolish for pedagogical reasons, or does Socrates knowingly make foolish claims for pedagogical reasons? Given that Socrates usually speaks for Plato but does not always do so 28, either answer is defensible. Neither is particularly problematic, as the conclusions that follow are nearly identical. Either way, the result is that the specific political claims of the Republic are not sincere, but dramatize the pressing need for rule by philosopher kings. VIII We might, however, object as follows: it may true that attributing both the aristocracy and consequence theses to Plato in their current forms is problematic, but there is a way of amending AT and CT such that the conventional interpretation avoids the problems outlined so far. 29 The amendments would look like this: (AT*) A city ruled by philosopher kings of all generations beyond the first would be maximally just. (CT*) The city described by Socrates would in fact result from the rule of the first generation of philosopher kings. This would make sense of the apparent tension between Socrates various statements by asserting that they have two distinct referents: the first group of philosopher kings that come to power, on the one hand, and all subsequent generations of philosopher kings, on the other hand. The first generation would not have the benefit of Socrates aristocratic education and would thus lack knowledge of the Good. Subsequent generations of philosopher kings would have the benefit of the education program, and so would possess knowledge of the Good. Socrates is therefore in a position to make reliable statements about the rule of a certain class of philosopher kings, namely, those who are initially granted power in the city. They are not in the privileged epistemic position that their successors will be, lacking as they do the rigorous education that allows one to obtain knowledge of the Good. It would therefore be plausible for Socrates to view himself as an epistemic peer of this first generation and so be justified in making statements about the policies that they would enact. We can then take his statements to refer exclusively to actions that would be taken by this initial class of rulers. I have three replies to this modified rival interpretation. The first difficulty is this: it seems strange to call the city s first generation of rulers philosopher kings at all given that they lack the privileged noetic access that make philosopher kings ideal rulers. It might be natural to refer to them as something like provisional philosopher kings, but even this seems forced, as they lack the one relevant criterion that makes philosopher kings effective rulers: their noetic access. This makes their status dubious at best. More straightforwardly, this distinction is 28 Kraut I am indebted to [omitted for blind review] for this point.

8 nowhere indicated in the text. Given how much weight it carries on this proposed account, its absence is conspicuous. My second reply is, I think, more decisive. There is a point in the text where Socrates makes a statement that simply cannot be reconciled with this modified conventional position. Speaking of the philosopher kings, he says: If good education makes them moderate men, they will easily discover all this for themselves and everything else that we are now omitting, such as the possession of women, marriages, and the procreation of children, and how all these must be governed as far as possible by the old proverb that friends share everything in common. (423e-424a) The importance of this passage is that it has Socrates referring to 1) the philosopher kings, 2) their aristocratic education, and 3) his seemingly dystopian proposals all in one place. Aristocratic education is here set in a direct causal relationship with Socrates specific political claims, the success of the former leading to an embrace of the latter. Socrates therefore cannot be speaking of the first generation of philosopher kings, for they will not receive his aristocratic education. He can only be referring to subsequent generations of philosopher kings, and in doing so makes explicit the claim that they will put the relevant policies into effect. There is no getting around it; Socrates is claiming to have reliable knowledge of the way in which philosopher kings would rule, and yet elsewhere disavows such knowledge. The modified conventional interpretation, therefore, cannot stand. Additional support can be found in the dialectical structure of the text. Socrates repeatedly implies that he has finished defending his account of justice only to have his interlocutors express dissatisfaction and demand a more detailed treatment of various issues that they take to be unsettled. Socrates reaction is consistent in each instance, invoking a disavowal of certainty and then proceeding anyway. At 450d-e, for example, he states the following: If I were confident that I was speaking with knowledge, your encouragement would be all very well. When one is among knowledgeable and beloved friends, and one is speaking what one knows to be the truth about the most important and most beloved things, one can feel both secure and confident. But to produce arguments when one is uncertain and searching, as I am doing, is a frightening thing and makes one feel insecure. This casts significant doubt on Socrates subsequent statements, and it turns out that those statements regard precisely what is at issue: the seemingly dystopian elements of his account. We see the same situation again at 506c, where Socrates again suggests that continuing down the dialectical path proposed by his interlocutors will leave their conclusions on shaky (or even nonexistent) epistemic foundations: What? Do you think it is right to speak about things you do not know as if you do know them? Haven t you noticed that beliefs without knowledge are all shameful and ugly things, since the best of them are blind? Do you think that those who have a true belief without understanding are any different from blind people who happen to travel the right road? Socrates would seem to be here implying a kind of futility in continuing further on the proposed course, but his interlocutors encourage him to continue anyway. By Zeus, Socrates, do not stop

9 now, with the end in sight, so to speak! We will be satisfied if you discuss the good the way you discussed justice, temperance, and the rest, Adeimantus replies (506d). There are the makings of a pattern here: Socrates expresses misgivings about proceeding further, is seemingly goaded into doing so by his interlocutors anyway, and makes various radical statements. This state of affairs brings with it strong suspicions of sarcasm on Socrates part, and the proximity of his dystopian statements to his professions of ignorance at 450d-e are particularly forceful. It would be a great coincidence for the narrative structure to simply happen to take this course in exactly the way we would expect it were Socrates simply speaking sarcastically. IX This treatment allows us to account for the dystopian elements of the Republic without giving up any of the crucial contributions of the conventional interpretation. It also makes room for recognition of Strauss contribution without giving quarter to the problematic and overreaching conclusions that he draws from it. The overarching intuitions of the conventional interpretation are vindicated, one of the most significant barriers to their acceptance having been diffused. This renders Plato s presumed view far less objectionable (both for his contemporaries and modern readers) while allowing it to remain a significant contribution to political theory. In some ways, it becomes even more significant. His call becomes not one to eugenics or sexual communism but to humility. It takes a wise thinker to craft complex political policies, but it takes an even wiser one to admit that such policies are good but not good enough, or at the very least that he or she cannot be sure that they are. True political wisdom will thus rest in training (or locating) and then deferring to the only truly qualified candidate who can serve as the philosopher king.

10 Works Cited Annas, Julia. An Introduction to Plato s Republic. New York: Oxford UP, Kraut, Richard. "Introduction to the Study of Plato." The Cambridge Companion to Plato. Ed. Richard Kraut. New York: Cambridge UP, Marshall, Mason. "The Possibility Requirement in Plato's Republic." Ancient Philosophy no. 1 (2008): Morrison, Donald R. "The Utopian Character of Plato's Ideal City." The Cambridge Companion to Plato's Republic. Ed. G.R.F. Ferrari. New York: Cambridge UP, Plato. Republic. Trans. C.D.C. Reeve. Indianapolis: Hackett, Reeve, C.D.C. Philosopher-Kings: The Argument of Plato's Republic. Princeton: Princeton UP, Schofield, Malcolm. Plato. New York: Oxford UP, White, Nicholas P. A Companion to Plato s Republic. Indianapolis: Hackett, 1979.

Synopsis of Plato s Republic Books I - IV. From the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Synopsis of Plato s Republic Books I - IV. From the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Synopsis of Plato s Republic Books I - IV From the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy 1 Introduction Since the mid-nineteenth century, the Republic has been Plato s most famous and widely read dialogue.

More information

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory Western University Scholarship@Western 2015 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2015 Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory David Hakim Western University, davidhakim266@gmail.com

More information

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst [Forthcoming in Analysis. Penultimate Draft. Cite published version.] Kantian Humility holds that agents like

More information

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. The Physical World Author(s): Barry Stroud Source: Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, Vol. 87 (1986-1987), pp. 263-277 Published by: Blackwell Publishing on behalf of The Aristotelian

More information

Spinoza, the No Shared Attribute thesis, and the

Spinoza, the No Shared Attribute thesis, and the Spinoza, the No Shared Attribute thesis, and the Principle of Sufficient Reason * Daniel Whiting This is a pre-print of an article whose final and definitive form is due to be published in the British

More information

Gale on a Pragmatic Argument for Religious Belief

Gale on a Pragmatic Argument for Religious Belief Volume 6, Number 1 Gale on a Pragmatic Argument for Religious Belief by Philip L. Quinn Abstract: This paper is a study of a pragmatic argument for belief in the existence of God constructed and criticized

More information

proper construal of Davidson s principle of rationality will show the objection to be misguided. Andrew Wong Washington University, St.

proper construal of Davidson s principle of rationality will show the objection to be misguided. Andrew Wong Washington University, St. Do e s An o m a l o u s Mo n i s m Hav e Explanatory Force? Andrew Wong Washington University, St. Louis The aim of this paper is to support Donald Davidson s Anomalous Monism 1 as an account of law-governed

More information

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central TWO PROBLEMS WITH SPINOZA S ARGUMENT FOR SUBSTANCE MONISM LAURA ANGELINA DELGADO * In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central metaphysical thesis that there is only one substance in the universe.

More information

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Kent State University BIBLID [0873-626X (2014) 39; pp. 139-145] Abstract The causal theory of reference (CTR) provides a well-articulated and widely-accepted account

More information

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become Aporia vol. 24 no. 1 2014 Incoherence in Epistemic Relativism I. Introduction In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become increasingly popular across various academic disciplines.

More information

What God Could Have Made

What God Could Have Made 1 What God Could Have Made By Heimir Geirsson and Michael Losonsky I. Introduction Atheists have argued that if there is a God who is omnipotent, omniscient and omnibenevolent, then God would have made

More information

The Problem of Freedom. Taylor Thompson, Columbia University

The Problem of Freedom. Taylor Thompson, Columbia University Thompson: The Problem of Freedom Thompson 1 The Problem of Freedom Taylor Thompson, Columbia University The main argument in Plato's Republic is first sketched through the attempt to define and characterize

More information

Practical Wisdom and Politics

Practical Wisdom and Politics Practical Wisdom and Politics In discussing Book I in subunit 1.6, you learned that the Ethics specifically addresses the close relationship between ethical inquiry and politics. At the outset, Aristotle

More information

Socratic and Platonic Ethics

Socratic and Platonic Ethics Socratic and Platonic Ethics G. J. Mattey Winter, 2017 / Philosophy 1 Ethics and Political Philosophy The first part of the course is a brief survey of important texts in the history of ethics and political

More information

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system Floris T. van Vugt University College Utrecht University, The Netherlands October 22, 2003 Abstract The main question

More information

Unpacking the City-Soul Analogy

Unpacking the City-Soul Analogy Res Cogitans Volume 8 Issue 1 Article 9 2017 Unpacking the City-Soul Analogy Kexin Yu University of Rochester, kyu15@u.rochester.edu Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans

More information

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an John Hick on whether God could be an infinite person Daniel Howard-Snyder Western Washington University Abstract: "Who or what is God?," asks John Hick. A theist might answer: God is an infinite person,

More information

WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY

WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY Miłosz Pawłowski WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY In Eutyphro Plato presents a dilemma 1. Is it that acts are good because God wants them to be performed 2? Or are they

More information

what makes reasons sufficient?

what makes reasons sufficient? Mark Schroeder University of Southern California August 2, 2010 what makes reasons sufficient? This paper addresses the question: what makes reasons sufficient? and offers the answer, being at least as

More information

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible? Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible? Anders Kraal ABSTRACT: Since the 1960s an increasing number of philosophers have endorsed the thesis that there can be no such thing as

More information

- 1 - Outline of NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, Book I Book I--Dialectical discussion leading to Aristotle's definition of happiness: activity in accordance

- 1 - Outline of NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, Book I Book I--Dialectical discussion leading to Aristotle's definition of happiness: activity in accordance - 1 - Outline of NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, Book I Book I--Dialectical discussion leading to Aristotle's definition of happiness: activity in accordance with virtue or excellence (arete) in a complete life Chapter

More information

What conditions does Plato expect a good definition to meet? Is he right to impose them?

What conditions does Plato expect a good definition to meet? Is he right to impose them? What conditions does Plato expect a good definition to meet? Is he right to impose them? In this essay we will be discussing the conditions Plato requires a definition to meet in his dialogue Meno. We

More information

City and Soul in Plato s Republic. By G.R.F. Ferrari. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, Pp $17.00 (paper). ISBN

City and Soul in Plato s Republic. By G.R.F. Ferrari. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, Pp $17.00 (paper). ISBN 174 good cannot be friends does much to illuminate Socratic eudaimonism. The translation of the dialogue is an outstanding work of scholarship. The authors either transliterate the Greek or discuss the

More information

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Ralph Wedgwood 1 Two views of practical reason Suppose that you are faced with several different options (that is, several ways in which you might act in a

More information

Reading Euthyphro Plato as a literary artist

Reading Euthyphro Plato as a literary artist The objectives of studying the Euthyphro Reading Euthyphro The main objective is to learn what the method of philosophy is through the method Socrates used. The secondary objectives are (1) to be acquainted

More information

IS GOD "SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?''

IS GOD SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?'' IS GOD "SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?'' Wesley Morriston In an impressive series of books and articles, Alvin Plantinga has developed challenging new versions of two much discussed pieces of philosophical theology:

More information

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg 1 In Search of the Ontological Argument Richard Oxenberg Abstract We can attend to the logic of Anselm's ontological argument, and amuse ourselves for a few hours unraveling its convoluted word-play, or

More information

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Author: Terence Rajivan Edward, University of Manchester. Abstract. In the sixth chapter of The View from Nowhere, Thomas Nagel attempts to identify a form of idealism.

More information

LODGE VEGAS # 32 ON EDUCATION

LODGE VEGAS # 32 ON EDUCATION Wisdom First published Mon Jan 8, 2007 LODGE VEGAS # 32 ON EDUCATION The word philosophy means love of wisdom. What is wisdom? What is this thing that philosophers love? Some of the systematic philosophers

More information

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge Colorado State University BIBLID [0873-626X (2012) 33; pp. 459-467] Abstract According to rationalists about moral knowledge, some moral truths are knowable a

More information

Plato s Republic. Important Terms

Plato s Republic. Important Terms 1 Plato s Republic The Republic (Greek: Πολιτεία, Politeia; Latin: Res Publica) is a Socratic dialogue, written by Plato around 380 BC, concerning justice (δικαιοσύνη), the order and character of the just

More information

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise Religious Studies 42, 123 139 f 2006 Cambridge University Press doi:10.1017/s0034412506008250 Printed in the United Kingdom Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise HUGH RICE Christ

More information

Does the Third Man Argument refute the theory of forms?

Does the Third Man Argument refute the theory of forms? Does the Third Man Argument refute the theory of forms? Fine [1993] recognises four versions of the Third Man Argument (TMA). However, she argues persuasively that these are similar arguments with similar

More information

BOOK REVIEWS. The arguments of the Parmenides, though they do not refute the Theory of Forms, do expose certain problems, ambiguities and

BOOK REVIEWS. The arguments of the Parmenides, though they do not refute the Theory of Forms, do expose certain problems, ambiguities and BOOK REVIEWS Unity and Development in Plato's Metaphysics. By William J. Prior. London & Sydney, Croom Helm, 1986. pp201. Reviewed by J. Angelo Corlett, University of California Santa Barbara. Prior argues

More information

Plato s Defense of Justice in the Republic. Rachel G.K. Singpurwalla

Plato s Defense of Justice in the Republic. Rachel G.K. Singpurwalla Plato s Defense of Justice in the Republic Rachel G.K. Singpurwalla We have a strong intuition that considerations of moral rightness or justice play a central role in the good life an intuition, that

More information

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords ISBN 9780198802693 Title The Value of Rationality Author(s) Ralph Wedgwood Book abstract Book keywords Rationality is a central concept for epistemology,

More information

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen Stance Volume 6 2013 29 Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen Abstract: In this paper, I will examine an argument for fatalism. I will offer a formalized version of the argument and analyze one of the

More information

Deontology, Rationality, and Agent-Centered Restrictions

Deontology, Rationality, and Agent-Centered Restrictions Florida Philosophical Review Volume X, Issue 1, Summer 2010 75 Deontology, Rationality, and Agent-Centered Restrictions Brandon Hogan, University of Pittsburgh I. Introduction Deontological ethical theories

More information

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational Joshua Schechter Brown University I Introduction What is the epistemic significance of discovering that one of your beliefs depends

More information

Conditions of Fundamental Metaphysics: A critique of Jorge Gracia's proposal

Conditions of Fundamental Metaphysics: A critique of Jorge Gracia's proposal University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor Critical Reflections Essays of Significance & Critical Reflections 2016 Mar 12th, 1:30 PM - 2:00 PM Conditions of Fundamental Metaphysics: A critique of Jorge

More information

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University With regard to my article Searle on Human Rights (Corlett 2016), I have been accused of misunderstanding John Searle s conception

More information

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Olav Gjelsvik, University of Oslo The thesis. Among people writing about rationality, few people are more rational than Wlodek Rabinowicz. But are there reasons for being

More information

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY 1 CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY TORBEN SPAAK We have seen (in Section 3) that Hart objects to Austin s command theory of law, that it cannot account for the normativity of law, and that what is missing

More information

INTERPRETATION AND FIRST-PERSON AUTHORITY: DAVIDSON ON SELF-KNOWLEDGE. David Beisecker University of Nevada, Las Vegas

INTERPRETATION AND FIRST-PERSON AUTHORITY: DAVIDSON ON SELF-KNOWLEDGE. David Beisecker University of Nevada, Las Vegas INTERPRETATION AND FIRST-PERSON AUTHORITY: DAVIDSON ON SELF-KNOWLEDGE David Beisecker University of Nevada, Las Vegas It is a curious feature of our linguistic and epistemic practices that assertions about

More information

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006 In Defense of Radical Empiricism Joseph Benjamin Riegel A thesis submitted to the faculty of the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of

More information

Edinburgh Research Explorer

Edinburgh Research Explorer Edinburgh Research Explorer Review of Remembering Socrates: Philosophical Essays Citation for published version: Mason, A 2007, 'Review of Remembering Socrates: Philosophical Essays' Notre Dame Philosophical

More information

A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel

A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel Abstract Subjectivists are committed to the claim that desires provide us with reasons for action. Derek Parfit argues that subjectivists cannot account for

More information

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows:

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows: 9 [nt J Phil Re115:49-56 (1984). Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, The Hague. Printed in the Netherlands. NATURAL EVIL AND THE FREE WILL DEFENSE PAUL K. MOSER Loyola University of Chicago Recently Richard Swinburne

More information

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW DISCUSSION NOTE BY CAMPBELL BROWN JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE MAY 2015 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT CAMPBELL BROWN 2015 Two Versions of Hume s Law MORAL CONCLUSIONS CANNOT VALIDLY

More information

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements ANALYSIS 59.3 JULY 1999 Moral requirements are still not rational requirements Paul Noordhof According to Michael Smith, the Rationalist makes the following conceptual claim. If it is right for agents

More information

We have a strong intuition that considerations of moral rightness or

We have a strong intuition that considerations of moral rightness or 13 Plato s Defense of Justice in the Republic Rachel G. K. Singpurwalla We have a strong intuition that considerations of moral rightness or justice play a central role in the good life an intuition, that

More information

BOOK REVIEWS. Justice in Love, by Nicholas Wolterstorff. William B. Eerdmann s Publishing Company, ix pages. $35.00 (hardcover).

BOOK REVIEWS. Justice in Love, by Nicholas Wolterstorff. William B. Eerdmann s Publishing Company, ix pages. $35.00 (hardcover). BOOK REVIEWS Justice in Love, by Nicholas Wolterstorff. William B. Eerdmann s Publishing Company, 2011. ix + 284 pages. $35.00 (hardcover). PAUL WEITHMAN, Department of Philosophy, University of Notre

More information

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience A solution to the problem of hijacked experience Jill is not sure what Jack s current mood is, but she fears that he is angry with her. Then Jack steps into the room. Jill gets a good look at his face.

More information

The Many Problems of Memory Knowledge (Short Version)

The Many Problems of Memory Knowledge (Short Version) The Many Problems of Memory Knowledge (Short Version) Prepared For: The 13 th Annual Jakobsen Conference Abstract: Michael Huemer attempts to answer the question of when S remembers that P, what kind of

More information

Templates for Writing about Ideas and Research

Templates for Writing about Ideas and Research Templates for Writing about Ideas and Research One of the more difficult aspects of writing an argument based on research is establishing your position in the ongoing conversation about the topic. The

More information

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between Lee Anne Detzel PHI 8338 Revised: November 1, 2004 The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between philosophy

More information

No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships

No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships In his book Practical Ethics, Peter Singer advocates preference utilitarianism, which holds that the right

More information

A CRITIQUE OF THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. A Paper. Presented to. Dr. Douglas Blount. Southwestern Baptist Theological Seminary. In Partial Fulfillment

A CRITIQUE OF THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. A Paper. Presented to. Dr. Douglas Blount. Southwestern Baptist Theological Seminary. In Partial Fulfillment A CRITIQUE OF THE FREE WILL DEFENSE A Paper Presented to Dr. Douglas Blount Southwestern Baptist Theological Seminary In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for PHREL 4313 by Billy Marsh October 20,

More information

Knowledge and True Opinion in Plato s Meno

Knowledge and True Opinion in Plato s Meno Knowledge and True Opinion in Plato s Meno Ariel Weiner In Plato s dialogue, the Meno, Socrates inquires into how humans may become virtuous, and, corollary to that, whether humans have access to any form

More information

Was Berkeley a Rational Empiricist? In this short essay I will argue for the conclusion that, although Berkeley ought to be

Was Berkeley a Rational Empiricist? In this short essay I will argue for the conclusion that, although Berkeley ought to be In this short essay I will argue for the conclusion that, although Berkeley ought to be recognized as a thoroughgoing empiricist, he demonstrates an exceptional and implicit familiarity with the thought

More information

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI Michael HUEMER ABSTRACT: I address Moti Mizrahi s objections to my use of the Self-Defeat Argument for Phenomenal Conservatism (PC). Mizrahi contends

More information

Skepticism and Internalism

Skepticism and Internalism Skepticism and Internalism John Greco Abstract: This paper explores a familiar skeptical problematic and considers some strategies for responding to it. Section 1 reconstructs and disambiguates the skeptical

More information

Plato s political community and human nature

Plato s political community and human nature Plato s political community and human nature Simon Marcus March 2010 In what way do Plato s views on a desirable political community rest on a particular conception of human nature? In Republic, Plato

More information

Plato's Republic: Books I-IV and VIII-IX a VERY brief and selective summary

Plato's Republic: Books I-IV and VIII-IX a VERY brief and selective summary Plato's Republic: Books I-IV and VIII-IX a VERY brief and selective summary Book I: This introduces the question: What is justice? And pursues several proposals offered by Cephalus and Polemarchus. None

More information

Plato s Philosopher Kings. The Sun, Line, and Cave

Plato s Philosopher Kings. The Sun, Line, and Cave Plato s Philosopher Kings The Sun, Line, and Cave An Analysis of Justice Justice in the city = df each of the three parts of the city (rulers, soldiers, productive classes) does its own work, deferring

More information

God s Personal Freedom: A Response to Katherin Rogers

God s Personal Freedom: A Response to Katherin Rogers God s Personal Freedom: A Response to Katherin Rogers Kevin M. Staley Saint Anselm College This paper defends the thesis that God need not have created this world and could have created some other world.

More information

Reasons With Rationalism After All MICHAEL SMITH

Reasons With Rationalism After All MICHAEL SMITH book symposium 521 Bratman, M.E. Forthcoming a. Intention, belief, practical, theoretical. In Spheres of Reason: New Essays on the Philosophy of Normativity, ed. Simon Robertson. Oxford: Oxford University

More information

PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY

PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY Paper 9774/01 Introduction to Philosophy and Theology Key Messages Most candidates gave equal treatment to three questions, displaying good time management and excellent control

More information

One of the central concerns in metaphysics is the nature of objects which

One of the central concerns in metaphysics is the nature of objects which Of Baseballs and Epiphenomenalism: A Critique of Merricks Eliminativism CONNOR MCNULTY University of Illinois One of the central concerns in metaphysics is the nature of objects which populate the universe.

More information

12. A Theistic Argument against Platonism (and in Support of Truthmakers and Divine Simplicity)

12. A Theistic Argument against Platonism (and in Support of Truthmakers and Divine Simplicity) Dean W. Zimmerman / Oxford Studies in Metaphysics - Volume 2 12-Zimmerman-chap12 Page Proof page 357 19.10.2005 2:50pm 12. A Theistic Argument against Platonism (and in Support of Truthmakers and Divine

More information

5 A Modal Version of the

5 A Modal Version of the 5 A Modal Version of the Ontological Argument E. J. L O W E Moreland, J. P.; Sweis, Khaldoun A.; Meister, Chad V., Jul 01, 2013, Debating Christian Theism The original version of the ontological argument

More information

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism Mathais Sarrazin J.L. Mackie s Error Theory postulates that all normative claims are false. It does this based upon his denial of moral

More information

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism 48 McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism T om R egan In his book, Meta-Ethics and Normative Ethics,* Professor H. J. McCloskey sets forth an argument which he thinks shows that we know,

More information

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy.

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy. To appear in The Journal of Philosophy. Lucy Allais: Manifest Reality: Kant s Idealism and his Realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015, pp. xi + 329. 40.00 (hb). ISBN: 9780198747130. Kant s doctrine

More information

The Divided Line from The Republic, Book VII by Plato (~380 BC) translated by G.M.A. Grube (1974), revised by C.D.C. Reeve (1992)

The Divided Line from The Republic, Book VII by Plato (~380 BC) translated by G.M.A. Grube (1974), revised by C.D.C. Reeve (1992) The Divided Line from The Republic, Book VII by Plato (~380 BC) translated by G.M.A. Grube (1974), revised by C.D.C. Reeve (1992) Socrates: You ve often heard it said that the form of the good is the most

More information

On happiness in Locke s decision-ma Title being )

On happiness in Locke s decision-ma Title being ) On happiness in Locke s decision-ma Title (Proceedings of the CAPE Internatio I: The CAPE International Conferenc being ) Author(s) Sasaki, Taku Citation CAPE Studies in Applied Philosophy 2: 141-151 Issue

More information

The Zygote Argument remixed

The Zygote Argument remixed Analysis Advance Access published January 27, 2011 The Zygote Argument remixed JOHN MARTIN FISCHER John and Mary have fully consensual sex, but they do not want to have a child, so they use contraception

More information

COURSE SYLLABUS. Office: McInnis Hall 214 MW 1:00-2:00, T&R 9:00-9:50, and by appointment Phone:

COURSE SYLLABUS. Office: McInnis Hall 214 MW 1:00-2:00, T&R 9:00-9:50, and by appointment Phone: COURSE SYLLABUS HON 102 Justice, the Common Good, and Contemporary Issues MWF 11:00-11:50 am FWLR 4 Spring 2010 Instructor: R.J. Snell Office: McInnis Hall 214 Office Hours: MW 1:00-2:00, T&R 9:00-9:50,

More information

Plato's Doctrine Of Forms: Modern Misunderstandings

Plato's Doctrine Of Forms: Modern Misunderstandings Bucknell University Bucknell Digital Commons Honors Theses Student Theses 2013 Plato's Doctrine Of Forms: Modern Misunderstandings Chris Renaud Bucknell University, cdr009@bucknell.edu Follow this and

More information

R. M. Hare (1919 ) SINNOTT- ARMSTRONG. Definition of moral judgments. Prescriptivism

R. M. Hare (1919 ) SINNOTT- ARMSTRONG. Definition of moral judgments. Prescriptivism 25 R. M. Hare (1919 ) WALTER SINNOTT- ARMSTRONG Richard Mervyn Hare has written on a wide variety of topics, from Plato to the philosophy of language, religion, and education, as well as on applied ethics,

More information

The Qualiafications (or Lack Thereof) of Epiphenomenal Qualia

The Qualiafications (or Lack Thereof) of Epiphenomenal Qualia Francesca Hovagimian Philosophy of Psychology Professor Dinishak 5 March 2016 The Qualiafications (or Lack Thereof) of Epiphenomenal Qualia In his essay Epiphenomenal Qualia, Frank Jackson makes the case

More information

Wolterstorff on Divine Commands (part 1)

Wolterstorff on Divine Commands (part 1) Wolterstorff on Divine Commands (part 1) Glenn Peoples Page 1 of 10 Introduction Nicholas Wolterstorff, in his masterful work Justice: Rights and Wrongs, presents an account of justice in terms of inherent

More information

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions Christopher Menzel Texas A&M University March 16, 2008 Since Arthur Prior first made us aware of the issue, a lot of philosophical thought has gone into

More information

Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII. Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS. Book VII

Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII. Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS. Book VII Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS Book VII Lesson 1. The Primacy of Substance. Its Priority to Accidents Lesson 2. Substance as Form, as Matter, and as Body.

More information

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality. On Modal Personism Shelly Kagan s essay on speciesism has the virtues characteristic of his work in general: insight, originality, clarity, cleverness, wit, intuitive plausibility, argumentative rigor,

More information

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to Haruyama 1 Justin Haruyama Bryan Smith HON 213 17 April 2008 Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to geometry has been

More information

Rashdall, Hastings. Anthony Skelton

Rashdall, Hastings. Anthony Skelton 1 Rashdall, Hastings Anthony Skelton Hastings Rashdall (1858 1924) was educated at Oxford University. He taught at St. David s University College and at Oxford, among other places. He produced seminal

More information

Plato and the art of philosophical writing

Plato and the art of philosophical writing Plato and the art of philosophical writing Author: Marina McCoy Persistent link: http://hdl.handle.net/2345/3016 This work is posted on escholarship@bc, Boston College University Libraries. Pre-print version

More information

latter case, if we offer different concepts by which to define piety, we risk no longer talking about piety. I.e., the forms are one and all

latter case, if we offer different concepts by which to define piety, we risk no longer talking about piety. I.e., the forms are one and all Socrates II PHIL301 The Euthyphro - Setting and cast o Socrates encounters Euthyphro as both proceed to court. Socrates is to hear whether he will be indicted. Euthyphro is prosecuting his father for murder.

More information

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981). Draft of 3-21- 13 PHIL 202: Core Ethics; Winter 2013 Core Sequence in the History of Ethics, 2011-2013 IV: 19 th and 20 th Century Moral Philosophy David O. Brink Handout #14: Williams, Internalism, and

More information

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism Felix Pinkert 103 Ethics: Metaethics, University of Oxford, Hilary Term 2015 Cognitivism, Non-cognitivism, and the Humean Argument

More information

IDOLATRY AND RELIGIOUS LANGUAGE

IDOLATRY AND RELIGIOUS LANGUAGE IDOLATRY AND RELIGIOUS LANGUAGE Richard Cross Upholding a univocity theory of religious language does not entail idolatry, because nothing about univocity entails misidentifying God altogether which is

More information

Huemer s Problem of Memory Knowledge

Huemer s Problem of Memory Knowledge Huemer s Problem of Memory Knowledge ABSTRACT: When S seems to remember that P, what kind of justification does S have for believing that P? In "The Problem of Memory Knowledge." Michael Huemer offers

More information

Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions. David Braun. University of Rochester

Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions. David Braun. University of Rochester Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions by David Braun University of Rochester Presented at the Pacific APA in San Francisco on March 31, 2001 1. Naive Russellianism

More information

Topic III: Sexual Morality

Topic III: Sexual Morality PHILOSOPHY 1100 INTRODUCTION TO ETHICS FINAL EXAMINATION LIST OF POSSIBLE QUESTIONS (1) As is indicated in the Final Exam Handout, the final examination will be divided into three sections, and you will

More information

DISCUSSION THE GUISE OF A REASON

DISCUSSION THE GUISE OF A REASON NADEEM J.Z. HUSSAIN DISCUSSION THE GUISE OF A REASON The articles collected in David Velleman s The Possibility of Practical Reason are a snapshot or rather a film-strip of part of a philosophical endeavour

More information

Anthony P. Andres. The Place of Conversion in Aristotelian Logic. Anthony P. Andres

Anthony P. Andres. The Place of Conversion in Aristotelian Logic. Anthony P. Andres [ Loyola Book Comp., run.tex: 0 AQR Vol. W rev. 0, 17 Jun 2009 ] [The Aquinas Review Vol. W rev. 0: 1 The Place of Conversion in Aristotelian Logic From at least the time of John of St. Thomas, scholastic

More information

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Chapter 98 Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Lars Leeten Universität Hildesheim Practical thinking is a tricky business. Its aim will never be fulfilled unless influence on practical

More information

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS [This is the penultimate draft of an article that appeared in Analysis 66.2 (April 2006), 135-41, available here by permission of Analysis, the Analysis Trust, and Blackwell Publishing. The definitive

More information

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism At each time t the world is perfectly determinate in all detail. - Let us grant this for the sake of argument. We might want to re-visit this perfectly reasonable assumption

More information