Wittgenstein s On Certainty Lecture 2

Similar documents
This handout follows the handout on The nature of the sceptic s challenge. You should read that handout first.

Wittgenstein s Refutation of Idealism. philosophers concerned with knowledge and scepticism. 1 But in my view, Wittgenstein s

10 CERTAINTY G.E. MOORE: SELECTED WRITINGS

Lecture 25 Hume on Causation

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 2. Background Material for the Exercise on Inference Indicators

EPISTEMOLOGY for DUMMIES

Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence. Abstract

Hume s emotivism. Michael Lacewing

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican,, Hertford College. Lecture 4: Two Cartesian Topics

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

The Rejection of Skepticism

Cartesian Rationalism

356 THE MONIST all Cretans were liars. It can be put more simply in the form: if a man makes the statement I am lying, is he lying or not? If he is, t

Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox

G.E. Moore A Refutation of Skepticism

Duty and Categorical Rules. Immanuel Kant Introduction to Ethics, PHIL 118 Professor Douglas Olena

Cartesian Rationalism

Chance, Chaos and the Principle of Sufficient Reason

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

A Lecture on Ethics By Ludwig Wittgenstein

The New Wittgenstein, ed. Alice Crary and Rupert Read, London and New York, 2000, pp. v + 403, no price.

Judith Jarvis Thomson s Normativity

What is Wittgenstein s View of Knowledge? : An Analysis of the Context Dependency

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Metaphysical Language, Ordinary Language and Peter van Inwagen s Material Beings *

The Meaning of Judgment. Excerpts from the Workshop held at the Foundation for A Course in Miracles Temecula CA. Kenneth Wapnick, Ph.D.

Mistaking Category Mistakes: A Response to Gilbert Ryle. Evan E. May

Debate on the mind and scientific method (continued again) on

The purpose of this paper is to introduce the problem of skepticism as the

Do we have knowledge of the external world?

Faith and Reason Thomas Aquinas

Study Guide and Commentary ACIM Text, Chapter 18, Section V The Happy Dream

Review: The Objects of Thought, by Tim Crane. Guy Longworth University of Warwick

Religious belief, hypothesis and attitudes

Russell s Problems of Philosophy

Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory.

What Is Science? Mel Conway, Ph.D.

Knowledge and Authority

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

An Epistemological Assessment of Moral Worth in Kant s Moral Theory. Immanuel Kant s moral theory outlined in The Grounding for the Metaphysics of

How Subjective Fact Ties Language to Reality

PHILOSOPHY IN RELATION

RULES, RIGHTS, AND PROMISES.

Early Modern Moral Philosophy. Lecture 5: Hume

INTRODUCTION. This week: Moore's response, Nozick's response, Reliablism's response, Externalism v. Internalism.

NOTES ON WILLIAMSON: CHAPTER 11 ASSERTION Constitutive Rules

Proofs of Non-existence

Faith and Philosophy, April (2006), DE SE KNOWLEDGE AND THE POSSIBILITY OF AN OMNISCIENT BEING Stephan Torre

Simplicity and Why the Universe Exists

How and How Not to Take on Brueckner s Sceptic. Christoph Kelp Institute of Philosophy, KU Leuven

LODGE VEGAS # 32 ON EDUCATION

STILL NO REDUNDANT PROPERTIES: REPLY TO WIELENBERG

Reid s dilemma and the uses of pragmatism

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things:

Why Worry about the Tractatus?

SENSE-DATA G. E. Moore

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

spring 05 topics in philosophy of mind session 7

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 1

The Assurance of God's Faithfulness

only from photographs. Even the very content of our thought requires an external factor. Clarissa s thought will not be about the Eiffel Tower just in

But we may go further: not only Jones, but no actual man, enters into my statement. This becomes obvious when the statement is false, since then

Wittgenstein on Mathematics and Certainties

Emotivism. Meta-ethical approaches

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle

Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa

Templates for Research Paper

The Extended Mind. But, what if the mind is like that? That is, what if the mind extends beyond the brain?

Thomas Reid on personal identity

"Are Eyebrows Going to Be Talked of in Connection with the Eye of God?" Wittgenstein and Certainty in the Debate between Science and Religion

24.00: Problems of Philosophy Prof. Sally Haslanger November 16, 2005 Moral Relativism

The Relationship between the Truth Value of Premises and the Truth Value of Conclusions in Deductive Arguments

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

Russell s Problems of Philosophy

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Judgment. Thomas Reid

HUME'S THEORY. THE question which I am about to discuss is this. Under what circumstances

Is Klein an infinitist about doxastic justification?

Chadwick Prize Winner: Christian Michel THE LIAR PARADOX OUTSIDE-IN

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

ON WRITING PHILOSOPHICAL ESSAYS: SOME GUIDELINES Richard G. Graziano

Ethical non-naturalism

"Can We Have a Word in Private?": Wittgenstein on the Impossibility of Private Languages

Mackie s Error Theory of Moral Judgments

Does the Third Man Argument refute the theory of forms?

DEGREES OF CERTAINTY AND SENSITIVE KNOWLEDGE: A REPLY TO SOLES. Samuel C. Rickless. [Penultimate version of a paper published in Locke Studies (2015)]

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Correct Beliefs as to What One Believes: A Note

Wittgenstein and the Skeptical Paradoxes

Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

Constructing the World

Phil 435: Philosophy of Language. P. F. Strawson: On Referring

Calisthenics November 1982

Lecture 1 The Concept of Inductive Probability

Reply to Brooke Alan Trisel James Tartaglia *

Free Will and Morality. Can we people morally accountable for the actions? Do we really have a free will?

Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is

Moore s Paradox and the Norm of Belief

Transcription:

Wittgenstein s On Certainty Lecture 2 Recap and Plan: Four sentiments of On Certainty expressed towards Moore s A Defence of Common Sense and Proof of an External World : 1. Moore fails to engage with the sceptic/idealist. 2. Moore doesn t know what he claims to know. 3. Moore, nonetheless, has focused on the right kind of proposition. 4. Moore is right to have claimed that he has conclusive evidence for these propositions and, yet, that he may, in some sense, be wrong concerning them. Today we ll focus on Sentiment 2 and ask, Why are Moore-type propositions (e.g., that here is a hand, that there is a tree, that my name is N.N., that I have never been in the stratosphere ) unknowable? A caveat: Wittgenstein doesn t unwaveringly claim that they are unknowable. Now, can one enumerate what one knows (like Moore)? Straight off like that, I believe not. - For otherwise the expression I know gets misused. And through this misuse a queer and extremely important mental state seems to be revealed. (OC 6) Moore has every right to say he knows there s a tree there in front of him. (OC 520) In its language-game [ I know ] is not presumptuous. There, it has no higher position than, simply, the human language-game. For there it has its restricted application. But as soon as I say this sentence outside its context, it appears in a false light. For then it is as if I wanted to insist that there are things that I know. God himself can t say anything to me about them. (OC 554) Non-Knowing Non-Scepticism? Why it s unclear what Wittgenstein means in saying Moore-type propositions are unknowable: - The sceptic says the same. - Wittgenstein often discusses his alternative (viz., certainty) as similar to faith; but that our relation to Moore-type propositions is one of faith is also what the sceptic says. Faith/trust/certainty s foundational role: As children we learn facts; e.g., that every human being has a brain, and we take them on trust. I believe that there is an island, Australia, of such-and-such a shape, and so on and so on; I believe that I had great-grandparents, that the people who gave themselves out as my parents really were my parents, etc. (OC 159) I did not get my picture of the world by satisfying myself of its correctness; nor do I have it because I am satisfied of its correctness. (OC 94) 1

I really want to say that a language-game is only possible if one trusts something. (OC 509) Knowledge and Doubt: An argument for the claim that Moore-type propositions are unknowable: P1. A proposition can only be known if it would be intelligible to doubt it. P2. It would not be intelligible to doubt Moore-type propositions. C. Thus, Moore-type propositions are unknowable. (Jumping ahead of ourselves ) The above argument would seem to give us an answer to the question How does Wittgenstein deny that we know Moore-type propositions and, yet, avoid being a sceptic? Here (one might think) is how: P1. Doubting Moore-type propositions is unintelligible. P2. Doubting is a necessary (if not sufficient) condition for being sceptical. C. Thus, being sceptical about Moore-type propositions is unintelligible, too. Two reasons to think Wittgenstein does not argue against scepticism in this way: 1. Seems he would be failing to engage with the sceptic (much like he accuses Moore of doing). 2. He wants (as we ll see) to distinguish between philosophical doubt and real/practical doubt, in which case real doubt being unintelligible need not rule out sceptical doubt. ( Now back to the argument.) A wrinkle to re-acknowledge: The conclusion that we don t know Moore-type propositions isn t a categorical statement. Wittgenstein thinks that some of us, sometimes, do know Moore-type propositions. [W]hen Moore says I know that that s a I want to reply you don t know anything! and yet I would not say that to anyone who was speaking without philosophical intention. (OC 407) But speaking with philosophical intention should be the same as stating such a proposition when doubt would be unintelligible, so we can focus on doubt. Evidence that Wittgenstein makes the argument: I know that a sick man is lying here? Nonsense! I am sitting at his bedside, I am looking attentively into his face. - So I don t know, then, that there is a sick man lying here? Neither the question nor the assertion makes sense. Any more than the assertion I am here, which I might yet use at any moment, if suitable occasion presented itself I know that there s a sick man lying here, used in an unsuitable situation, seems [to you] not to be nonsense but rather seems matter-of-course, only because one can fairly easily imagine a situation to fit it, and one thinks that the words I know that... are always in place where there is no doubt, and hence even where the expression of doubt would be unintelligible. (OC 10) 2

A first tempting response: We know this if we know anything! A second tempting response: The passage says not that we don t know the thing in question, just that we can t say that we know (or don t know) the thing in question. Wittgenstein disagrees with both. My difficulty can also be shown like this: I am sitting talking to a friend. Suddenly I say: I knew all along that you were so-and-so. Is that really just a superfluous, though true, remark? I feel as if these words were like Good morning said to someone in the middle of a conversation. (OC 464) Why does he think that doubting Moore-type propositions is unintelligible? 1. Doubt requires grounds, and we have no grounds for doubting Moore-type propositions. I know I have a brain? Can I doubt it? Grounds for doubt are lacking! (OC 4) Doesn t one need grounds for doubt? Wherever I look, I find no ground for doubting that (OC 122-123) I know, not just that the earth existed long before my birth, but also that it is a large body, that this has been established, that I and the rest of mankind have forebears, that there are books about all this, that such books don t lie, etc. etc. etc. And I know all this? I believe it. This body of knowledge has been handed on to me and I have no grounds for doubting it, but, on the contrary, all sorts of confirmation. (OC 288) What if the pupil refused to believe that this mountain had been there beyond human memory? We should say that he had no grounds for this suspicion. (OC 322) One doubts on specific grounds. (OC 458) What kind of grounds have I for trusting text-books of experimental physics? I have no grounds for not trusting them. (OC 600) 2. Our doubts and certainties form a system. Doubt requires certainty about something. If you tried to doubt everything you would not get as far as doubting anything. The game of doubting itself presupposes certainty. (OC 115) If I wanted to doubt the existence of the earth long before my birth, I should have to doubt all sorts of things that stand fast for me. (OC 234) [T]he questions that we raise and our doubts depend on the fact that some propositions are exempt from doubt, are as it were like hinges on which those turn. (OC 341) A doubt that doubted everything would not be a doubt. (OC 450) 3

3. Anyone who gave the appearance of doubt in the relevant scenarios would themselves be unintelligible to us. It s not a matter of Moore s knowing that there s a hand there, but rather we should not understand him if he were to say Of course I may be wrong about this. (OC 32) There are cases such that, if someone gives signs of doubt where we do not doubt, we cannot confidently understand his signs as signs of doubt. (OC 154) Suppose a man could not remember whether he had always had five fingers or two hands? Should we understand him? Could we be sure of understanding him? (OC 157) 4. Anyone who seemed to us to doubt these things would seem actually insane. If my friend were to imagine one day that he had been living for a long time past in such and such a place, etc. etc., I should not call this a mistake, but rather a mental disturbance (OC 71) I, L.W., believe, am sure, that my friend hasn t sawdust in his body or in his head, even though I have no direct evidence of my senses to the contrary. I am sure, by reason of what has been said to me, of what I have read, and of my experience. To have doubts about it would seem to me madness (OC 281) N.N. cannot be mistaken about his having flown from America to England a few days ago. Only if he is mad can he take anything else to be possible. (OC 674) (Other passages re-read as expressing madness:) Suppose a man could not remember whether he had always had five fingers or two hands? (OC 157) [In the middle of talking to a friend ] I knew all along that you were so-and-so. (OC 464) [While sitting at a man s bedside and looking attentively into his face ] I know that a sick man is lying here. (OC 10) Real Doubt and Philosophical Doubt: A seeming counterexample to the madness hypothesis: The philosopher. But Wittgenstein admits a difference here. I am sitting with a philosopher in the garden; he says again and again I know that that s a tree, pointing to a tree that is near us. Someone else arrives and hears this, and I tell him: This fellow isn t insane. We are only doing philosophy. (OC 467) Real doubt comes out in practice. Philosophical doubt doesn t. But if anyone were to doubt it, how would his doubt come out in practice? And couldn t we peacefully leave him to doubt it, since it makes no difference at all? (OC 120) 4

[T]here are people who say that it is merely extremely probable that water over a fire will boil and not freeze, and that therefore strictly speaking what we consider impossible is only improbable. What difference does this make in their lives? Isn t it just that they talk rather more about certain things than the rest of us? (OC 338) Wittgenstein thinks that even a sceptic/idealist would admit a distinction between their doubt and normal doubt, just that they re wrong about what that distinction is. I know often means: I have the proper grounds for my statement. So if the other person is acquainted with the language-game, he would admit that I know. The other, if he is acquainted with the language-game, must be able to imagine how one may know something of the kind. The statement I know that here is a hand may then be continued: for it s my hand that I m looking at. Then a reasonable man will not doubt that I know. - Nor will the idealist; rather he will say that he was not dealing with the practical doubt which is being dismissed, but there is a further doubt behind that one. - That this is an illusion has to be shown in a different way. (OC 18-19) One gives oneself a false picture of doubt. (OC 249) Why, though, does real doubt infect practice but philosophical doubt doesn t? (Another way of asking for a deeper answer to the question What s the difference between the two? ) The answer should be that the sceptic does not have grounds for doubt. But the sceptic gives grounds and concludes that, based on those grounds, we ought to doubt. Wittgenstein, though, claims that he can t doubt these things, implying that we don t have grounds for doubt. Can I believe for one moment that I have ever been in the stratosphere? [i.e., Can I doubt that I have never been in the stratosphere?] No. (OC 218) I cannot at present imagine a reasonable doubt as to the existence of the earth during the last 100 years. (OC 261) I cannot seriously suppose that I am at this moment dreaming. [i.e., I cannot doubt that I am not dreaming.] (OC 676) Why, though, are the sceptic s grounds not grounds for doubt? (A transition to the next lecture ) For Wittgenstein: In cases where doubt is unintelligible, making a mistake is unintelligible. If you were to find out that one of the sceptic s scenarios obtains, were you (before) making a mistake in believing that it doesn t obtain? (i.e., Should you have known better? Were you to blame?) Wittgenstein thinks not, for the sceptic s own reason that things would seem to you exactly as they do now. So you may be wrong, but you needn t change anything, needn t doubt in response to the sceptic s reasons. 5