In the preface to Law and Justice in Community the authors say:

Similar documents
Comment on Martha Nussbaum s Purified Patriotism

Take Home Exam #2. PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert

Philosophical Review.

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

Dworkin on the Rufie of Recognition

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

Morally Adaptive or Morally Maladaptive: A Look at Compassion, Mercy, and Bravery

Chapter 2 Reasoning about Ethics

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

Chapter 2 Ethical Concepts and Ethical Theories: Establishing and Justifying a Moral System

WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY

J.f. Stephen s On Fraternity And Mill s Universal Love 1

On the Rawlsian Anthropology and the "Autonomous" Account

Why economics needs ethical theory

To link to this article:

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Computer Ethics. Normative Ethics and Normative Argumentation. Viola Schiaffonati October 10 th 2017

Altruism. A selfless concern for other people purely for their own sake. Altruism is usually contrasted with selfishness or egoism in ethics.

Reasons With Rationalism After All MICHAEL SMITH

Zdenko Kodelja HOW TO UNDERSTAND EQUITY IN HIGHER EDUCATION? (Draft)

Scanlon on Double Effect

(i) Morality is a system; and (ii) It is a system comprised of moral rules and principles.

Chapter 2: Reasoning about ethics

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law

Legal positivism represents a view about the nature of law. It states that

Two Kinds of Moral Relativism

Many Faces of Virtue. University of Toronto. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research

Merricks on the existence of human organisms

The view that all of our actions are done in self-interest is called psychological egoism.

RESOLVING THE DEBATE ON LIBERTARIANISM AND ABORTION

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

2018 Philosophy of Management Conference Paper submission NORMATIVITY AND DESCRIPTION: BUSINESS ETHICS AS A MORAL SCIENCE

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Ronald Dworkin, Religion without God, Harvard University Press, 2013, pp. 192, 16.50, ISBN

The role of ethical judgment based on the supposed right action to perform in a given

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN SCIENCE, RELIGION AND ARISTOTELIAN THEOLOGY TODAY

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

Right to Life: a Principle of Equality

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

A lonelier contractualism A. J. Julius, UCLA, January

The Social Nature in John Stuart Mill s Utilitarianism. Helena Snopek. Vancouver Island University. Faculty Sponsor: Dr.

AS Religious Studies. 7061/1 Philosophy of Religion and Ethics Mark scheme June Version: 1.0 Final

Legal Positivism: the Separation and Identification theses are true.

Routledge Lecture, University of Cambridge, March 15, Ideas of the Good in Moral and Political Philosophy. T. M. Scanlon

Ethics Handout 19 Bernard Williams, The Idea of Equality. A normative conclusion: Therefore we should treat men as equals.

Historic Roots. o St. Paul gives biblical support for it in Romans 2, where a law is said to be written in the heart of the gentiles.

David E. Alexander and Daniel Johnson, eds. Calvinism and the Problem of Evil.

Rawls, rationality, and responsibility: Why we should not treat our endowments as morally arbitrary

Sample. 2.1 Introduction. Outline

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

Practical Rationality and Ethics. Basic Terms and Positions

Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social

Justice and Ethics. Jimmy Rising. October 3, 2002

A New Argument Against Compatibilism

Self-Evidence in Finnis Natural Law Theory: A Reply to Sayers

Does law have to be effective in order for it to be valid?

Genre Guide for Argumentative Essays in Social Science

University of York, UK

Socratic and Platonic Ethics

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Law and Authority. An unjust law is not a law

Externalism and a priori knowledge of the world: Why privileged access is not the issue Maria Lasonen-Aarnio

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Louisiana Law Review. Cheney C. Joseph Jr. Louisiana State University Law Center. Volume 35 Number 5 Special Issue Repository Citation

REASONING ABOUT REASONING* TYLER BURGE

220 CBITICAII NOTICES:

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

The Right to Equal Concern and Respect: The Foundation of Affirmative Action

Moral Relativism Defended

Two Conceptions of Reasons for Action Ruth Chang

The philosophy of human rights II: justifying HR. HUMR 5131 Fall 2017 Jakob Elster

THE OBLIGATIONS CONSECRATION

The ontology of human rights and obligations

5 A Modal Version of the

Phil 114, April 24, 2007 until the end of semester Mill: Individual Liberty Against the Tyranny of the Majority

BOOK REVIEW: CONTEMPORARY MORAL PROBLEMS

Conversation with Prof. David Bohm, Birkbeck College, London, 31 July 1990

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

Courses providing assessment data PHL 202. Semester/Year

Positivism, Natural Law, and Disestablishment: Some Questions Raised by MacCormick's Moralistic Amoralism

Happiness and Personal Growth: Dial.

Attfield, Robin, and Barry Wilkins, "Sustainability." Environmental Values 3, no. 2, (1994):

PRESS DEFINITION AND THE RELIGION ANALOGY

Rawlsian Values. Jimmy Rising

The Kant vs. Hume debate in Contemporary Ethics : A Different Perspective. Amy Wang Junior Paper Advisor : Hans Lottenbach due Wednesday,1/5/00

A Coherent and Comprehensible Interpretation of Saul Smilansky s Dualism

Craig on the Experience of Tense

What Part of the Soul Does Justice Perfect? Shane Drefcinski Department of Humanities/Philosophy University of Wisconsin Platteville

The title of this collection of essays is a question that I expect many professional philosophers have

PHIL 202: IV:

Higher-Order Approaches to Consciousness and the Regress Problem

Transcription:

The paper focuses on equality as a primary principle of human interaction. Human beings have basic needs, physical and mental, the fulfilment of which is necessary for a flourishing life. These needs transfer into so-called fundamental rights. Humans are entitled to a life as conscious, autonomous actors in respect to those needs. In this respect all humans are equal. It is proposed here that equality in this sense promotes a situation from which fundamental rights are derived. Thus equality is primary to and the reason why recognition of fundamental rights cannot be left to the chance of social development. In the preface to Law and Justice in Community the authors say: This work is a study in jurisprudence that considers the proper function of law to be the promotion of a context in which, without impeding one another, we can lead our lives together in peace and justice.[1] In this vision of the proper function of law the authors capture the core purpose of a legal system, as a tool to support a good and just society, for example by promoting the common good and defining social order. The law evolves in a moral context which instructs that to act reasonably and responsibly is the demand intrinsic to our moral experience as humans. [2] Natural justice or intrinsic moral behavior, such as to consider the interests of others, is cultivated and expressed in the living or communal law of a society. Humans, the authors insist, are social animals and live by necessity in communities[3] and the ways of doing things in the community, customs, practices, expectations, develop in time into jural relationships the living law normative principles generally approved of by the community. Thus, they deduct, law in fact existed in all human communities before it ever was expressed in a formal way. Law is thus a product of evolution and in no way that of any social contract.[4] Rights and duties are not based on a consensus, they are entitlements that must be mutually valued for a society to survive, discoverable objects of justice. The authors adopt a classical theory of rights, maintaining that rights are a function of justice understood as the giving to each what is due. [5] However, they denounce a subjective understanding of rights, thus a right only exists if it can be defined as an entitlement that has been accepted or acknowledged in the society.[6] Until it has been recognized it is only an as yet unsubstantiated claim. So far I have more or less been in agreement with the authors, here I have to pause however, because they explicitly note that this view of the nature of rights applies to all rights, not just positive legal rights, or rights to a tangible object. It also applies to natural rights and human

rights like those rights listed in the Universal Declaration of Human Rights: in so far as the respective society of a proposed right-holder has not recognized the Declaration or the entitlement as such, there is no right to speak of.[7] I have to doubt that an entitlement to a fundamental right depends on its acceptance; that claim seems to go against the very essence of the nature of fundamental rights. But I am not going to dwell on criticisms; rather I want to propose a vision of the initial status and interaction in human community and its consequences. The concept of living law as presented by the authors is plausible, but it does not, it seems to me, suffice to promote a context in which, without impeding one another, we can lead our lives together in peace and justice. [8] This is so because the darker elements of human nature or simply the differences in physical and mental strength are bound to have had an influence on the development and acceptance of the living law. That is to say, if this development is left to chance and no conscious measures are taken to guard a natural balance, an error in society s harmony may result. Humanity Before proceeding I must reflect on a few theses about human nature. Many scholars have tried to define what exactly being human implies and its moral implications. Some want, for example, to describe the concept from the perspective of an inner self or consciousness, others emphasise psychological qualities such as memory and mind. Thomas Nagel stresses the transcendental nature when he says: People can come to feel, when they are part of something bigger, that it is part of them too. [9] Nagel sees the capacity of insight to transcend oneself in thought as the cause of our feeling that life is absurd, which, in turn, he holds is the most human thing about us.[10] He acknowledges the circularity of referring to such arguments but adds: We adhere to them because of the way we are put together; what seems to us important or serious or valuable would not seem so if we were differently constituted. [11] Nagel captures here, I think, the essence of the human nature, the mystery of the conscious mind as it is expressed through imagination and desire. Another distinctive capacity human beings share is rationality. The Stoics compared rationality with a creature which forms and controls the individual it resides in as if it has a will of its own, but is at the same time like a bird in a cage, bound within the human individual.[12] In other words it needs to be cultivated and nourished and tamed so it may control the impulses to less virtuous actions rooted in our natural drive of self-preservation.

The degree to which human beings have this capacity or use it is irrelevant in this context, as well as the fact that it may be partly or completely lost on some, because this does not change the overall picture of how human beings are constituted. It is a characteristic of human beings that they are capable of virtue and rationality; and in this sense all men are equal, or as Johnny Christensen puts it: Parity of natural potentiality is implied by the very definition of man. Therefore there can be no natural differences between Greek and Barbarian, man and woman, noble and commoner, free man and slave.[13] And finally I would like to refer to Bernard Williams, who argues in his essay The Idea of Equality [14] that it is neither trivial nor a platitude to say that men s common humanity constitutes their equality. Any difference in the way men are treated must be justified, he says, and this is seen by many to imply an essential element of morality itself.[15] Human needs Now, a reflection on the needs of the human being. Aristotle said that man needs certain living conditions to flourish and to perfect his human nature learning virtue and good manners. Thus, the human being needs relations with other human beings; but moreover she needs to experience autonomy in respect to her options and status,[16] this must be so because of her sense of the individual self, sense of well-being and sorrow, sense of right and wrong, etc. It is this somewhat mysterious characteristic of the human being that calls for a society in which equal consideration and respect are essential elements. In such a society fundamental rights, as we call them, are intended to protect those values of a human life that we see as essential to the sense of existence and the autonomy of everyone: and for these we constantly struggle. In ancient Greece, where the law was based, in part at least, on convention or the living law, philosophers saw the role of motherhood as a reason to doubt the full humanity of females[17] and ever since this has significantly contributed to their subjugation. Women have been, as Kymlicka says, associated with the merely animal functions of domestic labour, whereas men achieve truly human lives by choosing activities according to cultural goals, not natural instincts.[18] When a certain group of people has been displaced in society for any reason, such as has for example been the case with black people and women, it is clear that their fundamental equal status has been violated, and their human status has not been respected. Today we call this discrimination; something must have gone wrong in the development of law and that implies the living law has not sufficed to secure a good and just society in the absence of guiding principles.

What we know about the inner life of human beings is sufficient to provide us with a compelling reason for acting at least in one certain fashion, and that is to treat all human beings with equal consideration and respect. To act otherwise amounts to abusing the common needs of all human beings. Barden and Murphy might want to qualify that assertion by saying that we must not discriminate unjustly.[19] They also criticize Ronald Dworkin s thesis about a right to equality of concern and respect[20] by reference to their down to earth relativistic view of the law.[21] Their relativism nevertheless misses an important point about the nature of fundamental rights. In line with Dworkin I would now like to further suggest that equality is the fundamental principle of human interaction, and that any thesis that does not embody it is therefore fundamentally flawed. Hypothesis: a platform of equality a principle of human interaction In this final section of my paper, I want to propose an argument. In substance it holds that equality must have an even stronger and, in particular, a more fundamental role in a just and flourishing community in which we can lead our lives together in peace and justice.[22] I will venture a strong approach to a principle of equal consideration and respect as a rationale for any fundamental rights human beings may have.[23] On this understanding, the conception of equality is prior and primary to, as well as being in a causal relationship with, the existence of the values we call fundamental rights of human beings; not the other way around. This is so, because when we have defined the characteristic elements of human nature, as above, and reflected on them, we can agree, I think, that there can be no justification at hand for discrimination in respect to those elements. Follow me now in a little thought experiment. Imagine a platform, like a huge derrick or an outdoor stage, or the starting square in a game. On this platform we have all the human beings there are. Maybe this is at the very beginning of human existence, it does not make a difference. They are landed there in their capacity as human beings; before the game starts; before they begin to fend for themselves in the state of nature or in society. I like to call this position the Platform of Equality. We may be looking from high above, so we cannot see the details. We only see human beings and as such they are all the same. In fact one may talk louder than another, one may be physically stronger than another, one may be equipped with a better tool to reason. Because of such differences we sometimes say that men are approximately equal,[24] but the important question is: do these differences entitle them to a head start in the game, or in life in fact? I think we can agree that they do not, so let s imagine that the human beings on the Platform have not yet themselves realized these differences. They are qua human beings all in equal need of the basic necessities that bring a flourishing human life. There at the Platform there is no ruler, and

as yet no rules. It is here that the living law begins to develop, and the important question is by what norms it will be guided. Will it be by the understanding and respect for mutual human needs, or will this understanding an essential condition for a peaceful society in which everyone may flourish be lost on many when they have started to fend for themselves and individual strengths prevail, thus unduly influencing the development of the living law? The point being stressed here is simply that human nature requires that everyone is equally ensured the opportunity to be in control of those matters in her or his life that are the most important for human living. On this understanding, it is not just having the same fundamental rights that constitutes the parity of human beings, but that human beings more importantly have these rights because they are equal in a fundamental and natural sense; it is the sameness that inspired the Stoic s teachings of brotherhood or solidarity. We can imagine that we draw a circle around each and every individual on which those items most important for human living are located. They may then be seen like electrons circling an atom, bound to its core by an invisible force. And they cannot be removed without consequences: the disruption of the individual as an autonomous entity. If we make a list of these needs and values we will obviously find security of life, liberty, food and shelter and most likely other elements and values which today are acknowledged in human rights clauses and conventions. But in spite of the fact that all humans are fundamentally the same in regard to these basic elements, they are still different in their individuality and strength, and that fact makes it essential to recognize and find a way to protect their equality in respect to these fundamental elements, as humans diverge from the Platform of Equality. From the Platform of Equality we continue to build a society, applying a theory of the development of laws or some contract theory of fairness; but a primary premise must always be that the citizens already have those properties we can call them rights equally allocated, and that those cannot be obliterated or curtailed by our actions, customs or the rules we set. On those terms a society evolves from the grounds of that which is essential for the development and wellbeing of everyone who lives in it. That is the idea of the Platform of Equality; building society on the conception of fundamental equality. From there other interactions may develop. If society is a necessity for humans, as the authors hold, that must only be true in so far as the individuals are not harmed by it. Who has a need (perhaps mere survival aside) for being in a group where he is ill-treated or subjected to the domination of another, or subjected to lifelong poverty, or not treated with equal concern and respect to other members of the group? To stay with an analogy from physics, interaction is meant to transfer energy, not destroy it. If we take equality of humans in this sense seriously it leads us to an awareness of the

necessity of protecting certain fundamental rights and to provide certain conditions based on respect for the values these protect. In the case where these are not acknowledged as valid entitlements action is needed to correct the situation. Government power, official institutions and private enterprises must follow suit, and experience shows we cannot leave this entirely to development. These principles should always have been clear, but they have not been, or not opted on. We have realized that things are not right, and tried to define how they should be by using the hypothetical methods of natural or positive law, social contract theories or the concept of the living law; but, I believe our documented failure lies, among other things, in never defining properly what went wrong, the situation at the very beginning, at the Platform of Equality and the development of society from there on. We have failed to recognize how the principle of equal consideration and respect is derived from our very nature. And the necessity of protecting certain fundamental rights and living conditions come from that fact, not the other way around. It is of course complicated to turn around in the real world where we have obviously started down a terribly wrong path, a long, long time ago, but to think it over and realize the mistake may be taking the first step to rectification. Hopefully we have not created a web of rules so entangled that we cannot disentangle it for the cause of a just society. That seems necessary if the law is ever to fulfil its proper function of promoting a context in which, without impeding one another, we can lead our lives together in peace and justice. [25] [1] Garret Barden and Tim Murphy, Law and Justice in Community, Oxford University Press Inc, New York, 2010, p. vx. [2] Ibid. p. 9 [3] Ibid, p. 20. [4] Ibid. pp. 20-22. [5] Ibid. p. 16, cf. pp. 206, 210. [6] Ibid. p. xiv, pp.205-212. [7] Ibid. p. xiv. [8] Ibid. p. vx [9] Nagel, T., Mortal Questions, Cambridge University Press 1979, p. 16. [10] Ibid. p. 23. [11] Ibid. pp. 17-18.

[12] Christensen, J., Equality of Man and Stoic Social Thought, Comm. Hum. Litt. 75 (1984), pp. 45-54, at pp. 45-6. [13] Ibid. p. 46. [14] Williams, B.A.O., The Idea of Equality in Justice and Equality, Bedau, H.A., (ed.), Prentice Hall, New Jersey 1971, pp. 116-137, at pp. 116-117. [15] Ibid. p. 117. [16] It is this sense of life we mean when we talk about human beings flourishing as the beings they are. A good society provides such conditions. Good society is governed by good laws, said Aristotle, but will be destroyed by bad. The laws are to proscribe and guard those elements that entice welfare and happiness. And in so far as the law is good, one who infringes it does injustice. Aristotle discusses these matters in his Ethica Nicomachea and Politica, e.g. NE I 4 1095a. [17] Aristotle, De Generatione Animalium, Book IV, 767b, cf. 775a. [18] Kymlicka, W., Contemporary Political Philosophy: An Introduction, Oxford University Press, Oxford 1990, p. 255. [19] Barden and Murphy, p. 210. The principle to treat everyone with equal concern and respect they argue demands [...] that one not discriminate unjustly between people. [20] Barden and Murphy quote Dworkin: We may therefore say that justice as fairness rests on the assumption of a natural right of all men and women to equality of concern and respect, a right they possess not by virtue of birth or characteristic or merit or excellence but simply as human beings with the capacity to make plans and give justice. Dworkin R., Taking Rights Seriously, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 1977, p. 182. [21] Barden and Murphy, pp. 209-210. [22] Barden and Murphy, p. vx. [23] In my approach I have in particular been influenced by two conceptions. One is Ronald Dworkin s thesis that governments ought to treat people as equals and not merely equally. His theory of equality is complex but importantly he seems to see equality as a fundamental value and liberty and equality as inseparable. See e.g., Dworkin, R., Liberalism, in Public and Private Morality, Stuart Hampshire (ed.), Cambridge University Press, Cambridge 1978, p. 113ff, at p. 125; and Taking Rights Seriously, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts 1977, p. 227.The other is the respect principle Tom Regan spells out in his The Case for Animal Rights, University of California Press, Berkeley 1984, pp. 326-327. [24] Hart, H.L.A., The Concept of Law, Clarendon Press, Oxford, second edition, paperback, 1998, p. 195.

Powered by TCPDF (www.tcpdf.org) Vol. 6, no. 2 (2011) [25] Barden and Murphy, p. vx.