Rethinking the Buddha: Early Buddhist Philosophy as Meditative Perception by Eviatar Shulman (review)

Similar documents
Phenomenal Consciousness and Intentionality<1>

There are three tools you can use:

A Philosophical Critique of Cognitive Psychology s Definition of the Person

Empty Words: Buddhist Philosophy and Cross-Cultural Interpretation (review)

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Craig on the Experience of Tense

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things:

RECENT WORK THE MINIMAL DEFINITION AND METHODOLOGY OF COMPARATIVE PHILOSOPHY: A REPORT FROM A CONFERENCE STEPHEN C. ANGLE

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

Access provided by National Taiwan University (10 Aug :00 GMT)

New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon

RETHINKING THE BUDDHA

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between

Religious Studies. Name: Institution: Course: Date:

Chapter Six. Aristotle s Theory of Causation and the Ideas of Potentiality and Actuality

To Provoke or to Encourage? - Combining Both within the Same Methodology

cetovimutti - Christina Garbe 1

Two Styles of Insight Meditation

On the Cultivation of Confucian Moral Practices

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

An Article for Encyclopedia of American Philosophy on: Robert Cummings Neville. Wesley J. Wildman Boston University December 1, 2005

Aniccå Vata Sa khårå

Informalizing Formal Logic

Past Lives - How To Prove Them

Christian Coseru University of Charleston, USA

Is phenomenal character out there in the world?

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

The Problem of the Inefficacy of Knowledge in Early Buddhist Soteriology

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

This book, Wisdom Wide and Deep, follows my first, Focused. Approaching Deep Calm and Insight

Part I: The Structure of Philosophy

PRELIMINARY. Asian Mahayana (Great Vehicle) traditions of Buddhism, Nagarjuna. easily resorted to in our attempt to understand the world.

Relative Merits of Samatha and Vipassana Techniques of Meditation.

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

CLARIFYING MIND An Introduction to the Tradition of Pramana

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

REVIEW. St. Thomas Aquinas. By RALPH MCINERNY. The University of Notre Dame Press 1982 (reprint of Twayne Publishers 1977). Pp $5.95.

William Meehan Essay on Spinoza s psychology.

Western Buddhist Review: Vol. 5. khuddhaka nikāya (Sutta-Nipāta, Udāna, Dhammapada, Thera- and Therī-gāthās, Jātakas and so on).

Studies in Buddhist Philosophy by Mark Siderits (review)

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

THE BENEFITS OF WALKING MEDITATION. by Sayadaw U Silananda. Bodhi Leaves No Copyright 1995 by U Silananda

UNCORRECTED PROOF GOD AND TIME. The University of Mississippi

Perceiving Particulars-as-such Is Incoherent--A Reply to Mark Siderits

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use

Skepticism and Internalism

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

THE NATURE OF NORMATIVITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC REBECCA V. MILLSOP S

Meaning of the Paradox

Buddhist Psychology: The Mind That Mindfulness Discloses

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

Evangelism: Defending the Faith

The Ethics of Śaṅkara and Śāntideva: A Selfless Response to an Illusory World

Yuval Dolev, Time and Realism, MIT Press, 2007

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

LIBERTY: RETHINKING AN IMPERILED IDEAL. By Glenn Tinder. William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company Pp. xiv, 407. $ ISBN: X.

Asian Philosophy Timeline. Chan Buddhism. Two Verses in the Platform Sutra. Themes. Liu. Shen-xiu's! There s not a single thing.!

Chan Buddhism. Asian Philosophy Timeline

Russell s Problems of Philosophy

The Five Spiritual Faculties ('Panca Indriyadhamma' පඤ චඉන ද ර යධම ම - in Pali)

On happiness in Locke s decision-ma Title being )

Notes: The Wings To Awakening. Introduction

Brother Teoh s Thusday class dated 25 th October 2018 outline short notes

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

only from photographs. Even the very content of our thought requires an external factor. Clarissa s thought will not be about the Eiffel Tower just in

The Appeal to Reason. Introductory Logic pt. 1

cetovimutti - Christina Garbe 1 Dependent origination Paṭiccasamuppāda Christina Garbe

Buddhism s Engagement with the World. April 21-22, University of Utah

BENEDIKT PAUL GÖCKE. Ruhr-Universität Bochum

Horwich and the Liar

Nagel, T. The View from Nowhere. New York: Oxford University Press, 1986.

Mindfulness and Awareness

Emptiness Appraised: A Critical Study of Nagarjuna's Philosophy (review)

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Philosophy East and West, Volume 65, Number 3, July 2015, pp (Review) DOI: /pew

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

The Critical Mind is A Questioning Mind

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

Kant s Copernican Revolution

book-length treatments of the subject have been scarce. 1 of Zimmerman s book quite welcome. Zimmerman takes up several of the themes Moore

How Subjective Fact Ties Language to Reality

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

Sophia International Journal of Philosophy and Traditions ISSN SOPHIA DOI /s

1990 Conference: Buddhism and Modern World

Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle

Indian Philosophy. Prof. Dr. Satya Sundar Sethy. Department of Humanities and Social Sciences. Indian Institute of Technology, Madras. Module No.

xiv Truth Without Objectivity

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic

Lesson 2 Student Handout 2.2 Confucius (Kong Fuzi), BCE

Time travel and the open future

Why Buddha was Discontent with the Eighth Jhana

As always, it is very important to cultivate the right and proper motivation on the side of the teacher and the listener.

BOOK REVIEWS. The arguments of the Parmenides, though they do not refute the Theory of Forms, do expose certain problems, ambiguities and

Transcription:

Rethinking the Buddha: Early Buddhist Philosophy as Meditative Perception by Eviatar Shulman (review) David Nowakowski Philosophy East and West, Volume 67, Number 1, January 2017, pp. 283-288 (Review) Published by University of Hawai'i Press DOI: https://doi.org/10.1353/pew.2017.0022 For additional information about this article https://muse.jhu.edu/article/643875 Access provided by National Taiwan University (12 Jan 2017 02:21 GMT)

John Berthrong s A Lexicography of Zhu Xi s Metaphysics, after reviewing some suggestions by Roger Ames and David Hall, presents a detailed analysis of four metaphysical domains within which Zhu Xi developed his philosophy, each domain embracing an array of concepts. The domains are (1) states, conditions, fields, formats, and textures; (2) dynamic functions or processes; (3) civilizing cultural outcomes; and (4) axiological values and virtues. John Makeham s Xiong Shili s Understanding of the Relationship between the Ontological and the Phenomenal shows how Xiong s movement from his original Yogācāra Buddhism to developing the founding ideas of twentieth-century New Confucianism brought him to identify the ontological with the phenomenal. Makeham neatly traces Xiong s changing interpretations of what the ontological and the phenomenal mean. To a remarkable degree this volume displays exciting and subtle metaphysics in the Confucian, Buddhist, and Daoist strains of Chinese philosophy, from the earliest texts to Xiong Shili in the early twentieth century. Of course, each of these essays is but a sample of metaphysical problematics that might be analyzed. But there is one glaring omission that deserves comment. There is no sample here of contemporary Chinese metaphysics, only essays about other thinkers. Several of the authors Vincent Shen and Roger Ames, for instance are known for their own metaphysical views, but these are not expressed here. What would contemporary Chinese metaphysics look like? As the New Confucians have known, contemporary Chinese metaphysics needs to reformulate the classic language to take into account both recent science and the engagement with non-chinese traditions of philosophy. The metaphysical themes so neatly analyzed in this volume need to be given contemporary language and argumentative forms to engage in the current global philosophical dialogue. As Ames says in his essay here and in many other writings, Chinese philosophy excels at ars contextualis, the art of thinking in context. The context for any contemporary metaphysics is the global situation with its multiplicity of cultures and raw wounds of intercultural brutalization. A study of past metaphysics is incomplete for a contemporary metaphysics whose context is the global situation. Can we not expect from the Chinese metaphysical traditions a new metaphysician? Rethinking the Buddha: Early Buddhist Philosophy as Meditative Perception. By Eviatar Shulman. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2014. Pp. xviii + 206. isbn 978-1-107-06239-9. Reviewed by David Nowakowski Union College nowakowd@union.edu Eviatar Shulman s Rethinking the Buddha: Early Buddhist Philosophy as Meditative Perception offers an important reminder to take early Buddhist texts seriously as Philosophy East & West Volume 67, Number 1 January 2017 283 288 283 2017 by University of Hawai i Press

meaning (no more than) what they say, with regard to the four noble truths, dependent origination, and selflessness (anatta). Shulman s book ably makes this interpretive point, but is frustratingly unclear in its more general discussion of the relationship between philosophy and meditation. Shulman s main thesis is that the four noble truths, as they are customarily taught today (i.e., as universal claims about the world or about all human experiences: life is suffering, [all] suffering is caused by craving /desire, etc.), are a younger philosophical elaboration of an original set of four observations (or, as Shulman sometimes calls them, four truths, without the adjective noble ), which were to be employed as a technique in meditative observation. They take the form of presently indexed observations about an individual s mental life: this is suffering, et cetera. The four observations are then used within meditation, considering individual mental phenomena as they occur. In Shulman s reading of the Pali texts ( 3.1 and chapter 4), the central meditative processes of the early Buddhist community proceed in three stages. First, prior to beginning mindfulness (Pali sati, akin to Sanskrit smṛti ) practice, the student learns the Buddhist conceptual and categorical schemata, particularly as these apply to naming and categorizing mental phenomena and observing the arising and cessation of these phenomena. Second, in the practice of sati, the student learns (and becomes habituated to) direct experience of his own mental life according to these schemata. In this way, he moves from an initial practice of recalling these schemata and consciously applying them to his present experience, to a more advanced meditative experience, which is structured according to these categories without any conscious effort to conceptualize them in that way. The student is thus practicing toward liberation. Finally, the meditator progresses to samādhi, characterized by the embodied perception of impermanence (p. 189), which comprises liberation itself. Such an account, which emerges slowly from Shulman s study, is both highly plausible and quite consistent with the practice of later Buddhist communities in India, Tibet, and elsewhere, for whom there is no sharp disconnect between doctrine, reasoned argument, and contemplative practice. Indeed, Shulman himself has little difficulty in showing the essential continuity of Buddhist thought and practice; he struggles, rather, in his attempts to set out a tension between them in the first place. We can identify four main elements to Shulman s thesis: (1) We should understand the mindfulness practice of sati to be intentionally contentful, (2) we should take seriously the common phrasing of the four truths as this is suffering, this is the cause of suffering, et cetera, while (3) disregarding the account of the Noble Truths in the received texts of the Buddha s first sermon, the Dhammacakkappavattanasutta, and (4) we should emphasize the tight connection between the four observations as phrased with this and the accounts of dependent origination and anatta. In his discussion of the first of these elements, Shulman emphasizes the root meaning of sati/smṛti as memory or recollection, and produces a range of texts giving instructions on sati in which the meditator is to consider himself or his experi- 284 Philosophy East & West

ence with a certain affective valence (as in the charnel ground meditations), or as composed of a precise list of elements, or in terms of the five aggregates, and so on. More than simply passive witnessing, such practices help the meditator to develop the habit of perceiving in certain ways, which will be conducive to liberation. In support of the second element, Shulman notes the overwhelming frequency of this formulation of the four observations in the Pali canon, and cites a variety of texts illustrating how to make use of such observations in practice. Against the phrasing of the Noble Truths in the Dhammacakkappavattana-sutta, Shulman notes the problems in the grammar of the received text, and the difficulty in finding a single solution that renders the statements of the second, third, and fourth noble truths both sensible and grammatical. Further, he suggests that the term ariyasacca ( noble truth ) is a historically late one, which tends to appear in contexts in which we have good reason to assume that the text has been manipulated (p. 142). If Shulman is correct about the later editing of the text of the first sermon, then the way is clear for his own interpretation of the four truths. But even if this textual conjecture were judged to be implausible, Shulman s work in the other portions of the book has at least demonstrated that there is substantial evidence for a strong tradition (even if not the only tradition) of observations of the style this is suffering, et cetera. Reflecting on dependent origination and the four truths, Shulman notes that both of these sets of formulae, as they are expressed in an overwhelming number of texts, feature reflection on the arising and cessation of this, as well as a four-step statement which analyzes this in terms of the causes of its arising and ceasing. The second and third truths are frequently phrased, or explained, in the language of dependent origination. And so, Shulman concludes, the principles are complementary and represent aspects of one and the same reflection (p. 161) on the present contents of one s experience. Likewise for selflessness, where impermanence (which just is arising and passing away) is not an argument in favor of anatta but a direct perception of its reality (p. 165). The initial conceptual understanding of selflessness is followed, through meditative practice, by the direct perception of selflessness, which in turn has the full impact of uprooting attachment to the notion of a self. The meditator is liberated precisely through habitually seeing his present experiences in terms of the Buddhist analysis of reality. To this point, I have not employed the term philosophy in my review of Shulman s main claims. Indeed, it is with regard to this term that the book stumbles most significantly. At the outset of his first chapter, Shulman suggests a prima facie tension between philosophy and meditation, which his work will resolve. In the first chapter, Shulman is explicit about his use of the term meditation to encompass both mindfulness (sati) as the intense observation of mental content, which is aided by a familiarity with Buddhist conceptual schemas (p. 4) and which is the topic of chapter 3, and concentration (samādhi), the deeply concentrated, distraction-free meditative state characterized by one-pointedness, which is examined throughout chapters 1 and 4. The intended meaning of meditation, then, is clear and consistent throughout the book: it is the group of mental states or activities that includes both sati and samādhi. Book Reviews 285

A univocal reading of philosophy is much more difficult to obtain. We can identify at least four distinct usages of this term throughout Shulman s book: (1) the mere holding of a thesis; (2) any form of conceptual thinking; (3) abstract, syllogistic reasoning; and (4) a transformative mode of living, characterized by spiritual exercises. I will consider each of these in turn. First, Shulman at times employs the term philosophy to mean simply holding a thesis, or, more strongly (though without any principled basis for this restriction), holding a thesis in metaphysics. We see such a sense in the discussion of the central teachings (p. 104) or early Buddhist philosophical doctrines (p. 105) at the conclusion of chapter 2. Such philosophical doctrines include the ten unanswered questions, the teaching of anatta, and the theory of dependent origination. When Shulman claims that his study of mindfulness meditation (sati) will help us to see how philosophy can be integrated into one s vision so that it becomes a spontaneous form of perception (p. 105), he must be using the term philosophy in this sense; I am certainly not integrating syllogistic reasoning into my perception as such. In this reading of the word philosophy, the apparent contrast with certain meditative states is clear, but the remaining characterization of philosophy, as the mere making of claims about practically anything, will doubtless be unsatisfying to those who wish to bound off the practice of philosophy from other domains. The key insight from the first sense of philosophy might be better captured by emphasizing philosophy in a second sense, as something conceptual. Shulman expresses a contrast between states of mind that are either more conceptual and philosophical, or more quiet and meditative (p. 170). Yet Shulman cannot really intend to place the philosophical, understood as more conceptual, and the meditative, understood as more quiet or less conceptual, at opposite ends of some spectrum. To do so would be to include in the very definitions of the terms the unbridgeable opposition that Shulman intends to overcome in his book on Buddhist philosophy as meditative perception, and would contradict his own definition of sati, cited above, from the opening pages of the book. Such a usage would also be radically at odds with the later Indian philosophical traditions both Buddhist and non- Buddhist and may stem from Shulman s uncritical rendering of the Pali ñāṇa (= Sanskrit jñāna) as knowledge. As Shulman observes, the fourth jhāna the stage of samādhi during which, according to the ostensibly autobiographical accounts, the Buddha s own liberation took place is characterized by the destruction of negative inflows (āsava), which occurs by means of ñāṇa (p. 36). The alleged tension between philosophy and meditation may only arise if we try to pack too much into the meaning of this term by supposing that knowledge (ñāṇa) is necessarily some kind of structured propositional awareness, which plays a starring role in abstract theorizing. Such an assumption would be shocking, if not entirely incomprehensible, to philosophers of the Dignāga/Dharmakīrti school in the later Indian Buddhist tradition. As they employ the equivalent Sanskrit term, jñāna most accurately means something like cognition, and encompasses any contentful event in one s mental life, from non-conceptual (nirvikalpaka) perception to conceptual (savikalpaka) linguistic/inferential modes of thought. 1 So the readings of knowledge 286 Philosophy East & West

and philosophy as being what is essentially conceptual and non-meditative are inconsistent both with Shulman s own thesis and with the wider Indian philosophical tradition. A more careful rendering of ñāṇa/jñāna also eliminates at the outset any tension that may have arisen between meditative awareness and philosophy in the first sense of holding a thesis. Cognitive states, including those that arise in meditation, are conditioned by our exposure to Buddhist (or any other) classificatory schemata. It is only when we have learned that mental phenomena are impermanent and composed of the five aggregates that we begin to experience our own inner lives in these terms. A third alternative is to define philosophy not as a corpus of conceptually expressed doctrines, but in terms of the process by which one arrives at these doctrines. Shulman suggests such a definition by way of example: This is nothing but concrete, forceful, philosophical reasoning: everything one perceives is ephemeral and hence no view can capture the nature of reality (p. 66). Here, philosophical reasoning seems to be nothing more than proceeding from premise(s) to conclusion. Its concreteness seems to consist in being an explicit syllogism. In this context, Shulman suggests that a contrasting approach would be more pragmatic than philosophical (p. 67 n. 14), that is, given over more to acting in the world than to reflecting about the world. This leads into the fourth of Shulman s definitions, according to which we may consider philosophy to be a mode of living, a way of transformatively engaging with oneself and the world. Early in chapter 1, Shulman appeals to Pierre Hadot s characterization of ancient Greek philosophy as spiritual exercises leading to selftransformation (p. 5). While this is the closest Shulman comes to offering an ex plicit definition of philosophy, it is a definition that fails to capture many of his own uses of that term, including (but not only) those mentioned above. If philosophy were characterized only in this fourth way, without requiring any additional features (such as those implicated in the first three definitions), there would be no basis at all for a tension between philosophy and meditation. Clearly, meditation could very well be part of spiritual exercises leading to self-transformation. As I hope to have suggested in my characterization of Shulman s main claims, the question of what counts as philosophy is confusing, irrelevant, and deeply unhelpful. Unfortunately, it is also an issue over which Shulman expends a great deal of verbiage, especially in the first two chapters, which together comprise more than half the book. We would be better served to abandon the oppositions (whether implicit or explicit) in the first three definitions, and accept that the positive components of all four definitions capture important elements. Let us simply say that the practices of the early Buddhist community, as expressed in the Pali discourses, included the teaching of important doctrines, conceptual schemata for describing and analyzing lived experience, reasoning from premises to conclusions, and spiritual exercises leading to liberation. To attempt to expand on such a description, by calling one or more of these elements philosophy, only to be shocked when that element turns out to be connected with the rest of the community s practice, adds nothing but unclarity. This more fruitful description of interrelated elements can indeed be teased Book Reviews 287

out of Shulman s work, along with the ample evidence that all of these elements were tightly integrated with each other and with the meditative practices of that Buddhist community, culminating in liberation. In conclusion, Shulman s Rethinking the Buddha succeeds as a description of the integrated elements of teaching, reflection, argument, and observation of the early Buddhist community, and the importance of reading the statements of the four truths and related teachings on selflessness and dependent origination as local observations on a meditator s present experience: this is suffering, this is the cause of suffering, et cetera. Yet the book stumbles in its attempt to bracket off and evaluate a distinct domain of philosophy. Note 1 The Naiyāyika rivals of Dignāga and Dharmakīrti would, of course, acknowledge even some perceptual states that are in their essence conceptual. Whose Tradition? Which Dao? Confucius and Wittgenstein on Moral Learning and Reflection. By James F. Peterman. Albany: State University of New York Press, 2015. Pp. xx + 319. isbn 978-1-4384-5419-1. Reviewed by Galia Patt-Shamir Tel-Aviv University galiap@tau.ac.il Whose Tradition? Which Dao? Confucius and Wittgenstein on Moral Learning and Reflection by James F. Peterman addresses the valuable position that Confucius dao can and has to be understood within the useful framework of Wittgensteinian forms of life, their concrete language games, and the mastery of techniques and rulefollowing, and that Wittgenstein s forms of life embody critical therapeutic interventions that can be better understood through Confucian ideas of moral practice and reflection, most significantly as the practice of ritual ( 禮 li ). Placing Confucianism in a global philosophical context is necessary, since the self-sufficiency of Confucianism demands that it should be possible to have the Confucian message in discourse with other intellectual points of view. Wittgenstein s ideas introduce a method of looking at texts as integral to human life, and demand that we reflect on the life that the texts represent. If his ideas about language games and forms of life are true, they should apply to particular traditions. Confucian moral practice and its significance in one s reflection on life expands the understanding of forms of life. In this way Confucianism and Wittgensteinianism support each other. The dialogue between the two philosophies demands of us that we open ourselves to others in order to better understand their philosophies as well 288 Philosophy East & West Volume 67, Number 1 January 2017 288 291 2017 by University of Hawai i Press