John Stuart Mill ( ) is widely regarded as the leading English-speaking philosopher of

Similar documents
Annotated List of Ethical Theories

Moral Theory. What makes things right or wrong?

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6

The Exeter College Summer Programme at Exeter College in the University of Oxford. Good Life or Moral Life?

24.01: Classics of Western Philosophy

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

Creative Genius and the Rights of the Individual: From Romanticism to Utilitarianism

Tuesday, September 2, Idealism

Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

Hoong Juan Ru. St Joseph s Institution International. Candidate Number Date: April 25, Theory of Knowledge Essay

Course Syllabus Ethics PHIL 330, Fall, 2009

PHIL 2000: ETHICS 2011/12, TERM 1

No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships

MILL ON LIBERTY. 1. Problem. Mill s On Liberty, one of the great classics of liberal political thought,

CURRICULUM VITAE of Joshua Hoffman. Department of Philosophy, University of North Carolina at Greensboro, Greensboro, N.C.,

Naturalism and is Opponents

The hallmark of a good moral theory is that it agrees with and improves

What is the "Social" in "Social Coherence?" Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious Freedom in an Egalitarian Age

DEMOCRACY, DELIBERATION, AND RATIONALITY Guido Pincione & Fernando R. Tesón

Philosophical Review.

Phil 114, April 24, 2007 until the end of semester Mill: Individual Liberty Against the Tyranny of the Majority

Philosophy 2: Introduction to Philosophy Section 4170 Online Course El Camino College Spring, 2015

사회학영문강독 제 12 강. 전광희교수

Moral Philosophy : Utilitarianism

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Philosophy 101: Introduction to Philosophy Section 4152 Online Course El Camino College Spring, 2017

Chapter 2 Reasoning about Ethics

NORTH SOUTH UNIVERSITY DEPARTMENT OF HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY DHAKA, BANGLADESH

Introduction to Ethics

Deontology: Duty-Based Ethics IMMANUEL KANT

PROFESSIONAL ETHICS IN SCIENCE AND ENGINEERING

Ethics is subjective.

SANDEL ON RELIGION IN THE PUBLIC SQUARE

Chapter Summaries: A Christian View of Men and Things by Clark, Chapter 1

EL CAMINO COLLEGE Behavioral & Social Sciences Philosophy Introduction to Philosophy, Summer 2016 Section 2510, MTWTh, 8:00-10:05 a.m.

Introduction: Goddess and God in Our Lives

Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1

Phil 104: Introduction to Philosophy

PL 406 HISTORY OF MODERN PHILOSOPHY Fall 2009

Honors Ethics Oral Presentations: Instructions

NON-RELIGIOUS PHILOSOPHIES OF LIFE AND THE WORLD Support Materials - GMGY

Philosophy 1100: Ethics

PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT FALL SEMESTER 2009 COURSE OFFERINGS

The Principle of Sufficient Reason and Free Will

Deontology: Duty-Based Ethics IMMANUEL KANT

ABSTRACT of the Habilitation Thesis

John Stuart Mill on suicide. 1 Íñigo Álvarez Gálvez 2

MILL ON JUSTICE: CHAPTER 5 of UTILITARIANISM Lecture Notes Dick Arneson Philosophy 13 Fall, 2005

Introduction to Ethics

West Los Angeles College. Philosophy 1 Introduction to Philosophy. Spring Instructor. Rick Mayock, Professor of Philosophy

Knowledge, Reality, and Values CORC 1210 SYLLABUS

University of International Business and Economics International Summer Sessions. PHI 110: Introduction to Philosophy

CHAPTER 2. The Classical School

Orienting Social Epistemology 1 Francis Remedios, Independent Researcher, SERRC

HOUSTON COMMUNITY COLLEGE SYSTEM Northeast College NOLN

By the end of this course, students will be able to:

HSTR th Century Europe

Course Syllabus Political Philosophy PHIL 462, Spring, 2017

Philosophical Ethics. Distinctions and Categories

Christian Evidences. The Verification of Biblical Christianity, Part 2. CA312 LESSON 06 of 12

Course Syllabus. CALIFORNIA STATE UNIVERSITY, NORTHRIDGE Contemporary Ethical Issues (RS 361 ONLINE #14955) Spring 2018

Wed., 6:30-9:00 Office hours: Mon./Wed., 4:30-5:30 Packard Seminar Room Packard Hall 109

Introduction to Philosophy

Pihlström, Sami Johannes.

On Liberty by John Stuart Mill

MAP, Spring, 2011: SYLLABUS: V Texts and Ideas: Freedom and Oppression

Plantinga, Van Till, and McMullin. 1. What is the conflict Plantinga proposes to address in this essay? ( )

Chapter Summaries: Introduction to Christian Philosophy by Clark, Chapter 1

5AANA005 Ethics II: History of Ethical Philosophy 2014/15. BA Syllabus

Mill s Utilitarian Theory

Who Has the Burden of Proof? Must the Christian Provide Adequate Reasons for Christian Beliefs?

NOTE: Courses, rooms, times and instructors are subject to change; please see Timetable of Classes on HokieSpa for current information

Rashdall, Hastings. Anthony Skelton

Moral Belief on Utilitarianism toward Misused Approach to Moral Evaluation

Do we have responsibilities to future generations? Chris Groves

Kane is Not Able: A Reply to Vicens Self-Forming Actions and Conflicts of Intention

Two Approaches to Natural Law;Note

The Divine Command Theory

Philosophy Courses-1

The Experience Machine and Mental State Theories of Wellbeing

Address 307 Valley Street Purdue University, Department of Philosophy

Kantian Deontology. A2 Ethics Revision Notes Page 1 of 7. Paul Nicholls 13P Religious Studies

Conceptual Levels: Bringing It Home to

CHAPTER 2 Test Bank MULTIPLE CHOICE

Critical Reasoning and Moral theory day 3

Philosophy Quiz 12 The Age of Descartes

Ladies and Gentlemen, welcome to my talk. My topic is "Theory of knowledge - Thomas S. Kuhn and Paul Feyerabend" I want to tell you simple story

A Review of Norm Geisler's Prolegomena

UC Davis Philosophy Department Expanded Course Descriptions Fall, 2009

To link to this article:

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have

Religious Studies. Name: Institution: Course: Date:

Florida State University Libraries

The Problem of Evil Chapters 14, 15. B. C. Johnson & John Hick Introduction to Philosophy Professor Doug Olena

Curriculum Vitae. Joseph Mendola

SYLLABUS. Business and Social Sciences Department: History/Philosophy

Areas of Specialization and Competence Philosophy of Language, History of Analytic Philosophy

Philosophy 2: Introduction to Philosophy Section 2511, Room SOCS 205, 7:45-9:10am El Camino College Fall, 2014

INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY

Transcription:

[DRAFT: please do not cite without permission. The final version of this entry will appear in the Encyclopedia of the Philosophy of Religion (Wiley-Blackwell, forthcoming), eds. Stewart Goetz and Charles Taliaferro] Title Mill, John Stuart Your Name Piers Norris Turner Affiliation Ohio State University Email Address turner.894@osu.edu Main Text John Stuart Mill (1806-1873) is widely regarded as the leading English-speaking philosopher of the nineteenth century. His contributions ranged over epistemology, scientific method, the social sciences, metaphysics, philosophy of language, and moral and political philosophy. His great systematic treatises, A System of Logic (1843) and Principles of Political Economy (1848) were standard textbooks for decades. But his most enduring works On Liberty (1859), Utilitarianism (1861), and The Subjection of Women (1869) all concern moral and political philosophy. In those fields, he is recognized as the leading expositor and defender of the utilitarian theory of morality and a core figure of the liberal political tradition. Mill was also a social and political activist, a civil servant in the East India Company, and briefly a member of the British parliament, where he is remembered as the first person to introduce legislation to grant women

the right to vote. He remains a key inspiration and touchstone for contemporary moral and political theory. Mill followed Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832) and his father James Mill (1773-1836) as a proponent of utilitarianism. They argued that morality requires a public standard to replace appeals to intuition that merely reflect people s likes and dislikes. Their proposal, the Greatest Happiness Principle (CW X.214), holds that the fundamental standard of right and wrong actions, rules, policies, or institutions is their contribution to the general happiness, that is, to the overall balance of pleasure and pain. As a form of consequentialism, utilitarians hold that moral evaluation is solely a matter of the value produced by performing some action or enacting some policy. Utilitarians then argue that what is ultimately of value is happiness. Bentham and Mill emphasized that each person s happiness is to count equally or impartially, and that the suffering of non-human animals should also be taken into account. Mill revised Bentham s utilitarianism primarily by emphasizing that character development was itself a means to promoting utility. Bentham had focused on institutional structures to incentivize people to produce good outcomes. Mill argued instead that people were capable of developing a sense of duty or fellow-feeling, that the cultivation of the intellect and the sentiments were themselves important elements of individual happiness, and that happiness should not be confused with mere contentment or preference satisfaction. The focus on character also informed Mill s liberal political philosophy. In On Liberty, he argued that principled limits on state and social authorities, even in a democracy, were vital for the development of what he called individuality (CW XVIII.260) or self-determination. He maintained the importance of diverse experiments in living (CW XVIII.281) not only for individual happiness but as a means to social progress. Despotism, even of a majority, is

incompatible with the discussion and experience that provide the rational basis for improvement. His defense of freedom of discussion in On Liberty that it is always better to allow people to raise contrary viewpoints in a sincere and truth-oriented spirit than to stifle dissent remains one of the most important essays on that topic. Mill also articulated what is now commonly referred to as the harm principle or liberty principle, the core idea of which is that an individual s actions (or the actions of consenting adults) that do not risk harm to others should not be open to state or social interference. Mill s version of the harm principle is strictly anti-paternalistic: state or social coercion cannot be justified by appeal to the individual s own good, but must refer to the social good. This principle continues to influence law and policy, not least with respect to sexual morality. In his democratic theory, Mill argued that only democracy could provide the check on power necessary for progress, but also that measures should be taken to promote the competence of political authorities and the education of the democratic public. In Considerations on Representative Government (1861), he therefore advocated for universal suffrage and democratic participation, but also for proportional representation and plural votes for those with demonstrated aptitude. As a political economist, Mill favored free trade but also a form of democratic socialism defined by worker cooperatives, the regulation of property rights, and redistributive taxation. His work on the stationary state (CW III.752-7) continues to influence economists concerned about the effects of economic growth on environmental sustainability. In The Subjection of Women, he provided one of the first sustained arguments for women s full equal rights. On this and other matters he was greatly influenced by his close collaborator and wife, Harriet Taylor Mill (1807 1858). Mill also vehemently criticized slavery and repeatedly argued that differences among groups were the result of circumstantial or cultural

factors, and not due to differences in their natures. His very qualified support for colonialism as a temporary measure for societies that he thought needed the guidance of leading-strings (CW XIX.396) followed from his general view that all societies needed such guidance at one point or another. But he was more alive to the evils of British rule over Ireland than over India, and his role as a high-ranking administrator in the East India Company has deserved close scrutiny. In general, Mill campaigned for the rights of minorities and the disadvantaged, and endured criticism for his progressive views. Mill s views on religion were, for the most part, revealed only posthumously with the publication of his Autobiography (1873) and the essays Utility of Religion (1874) and Theism (1874). For most of his career, he had avoided commenting publicly on the rationality of religious belief because, despite his criticism of the Church as a dogmatic social institution, he intended his liberal proposals about freedom of discussion and experiments in living to include religious doctrines and believers. In a few places, he clarified that he did not believe utilitarianism to be at odds with religious belief if one appreciated the lesson of Plato s Euthyphro (see EOPR0134) that right and wrong are not constituted by the will of God. He also admired the moral teachings of Jesus. However, Mill borrowed from Auguste Comte (1798-1857; see EOPR0080) the idea of a religion of humanity that could supplant the role of supernatural religion in sustaining a shared social morality. He also offered a naturalist theory of knowledge (see EOPR0262) in which the phenomena of experience proceed according to laws of nature and do not require any supernatural explanation. And he defended a compatibilist account of free will according to which human freedom, properly understood, is reconcilable with determinism.

In private letters and in his posthumously published writings, Mill argued that, given the evil in the world, God could not be both omnipotent and perfectly benevolent. He sometimes framed the problem of evil in terms of the many centuries of suffering endured by humans prior to establishing anything like a pleasant existence. Moreover, he thought eternal perdition in Hell for the faults of a finite life to be incompatible with an omnipotent and perfectly benevolent God. Mill argued that the most respectable theism would accept that God is not all-powerful, and is therefore unable to make the world the best it could be. Mill was skeptical of a priori arguments for the existence of God. He accepted that the argument from design provides some support for God s existence, but he concluded that the evidence simply is not strong enough to justify belief. He also noted that the work of Charles Darwin (1809-1882; see EOPR0092) provides an alternative explanation to design. Although he argued that belief in God is not rationally supported, he thought one might permissibly entertain ideas of God as a matter of hope or imagination (see CW X.419, 426-7, 483-5; CW XVI.1196). While his personal views did not appeal to supernatural religious ideas, he allowed that hope in God, falling short of belief, could play a salutary role in one s moral life. References Mill, John Stuart. The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill. Edited by J. M. Robson. 33 vols. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1963 91. Accessible online at http://oll.libertyfund.org/titles/165. [CW]

Further Readings Berger, Fred R. 1984. Happiness, Justice and Freedom. Berkeley: University of California Press. MacLeod, Christopher, and Dale E. Miller (eds.) 2017. A Companion to Mill. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. Skorupski, John. 2010. John Stuart Mill [reprint]. New York: Routledge. Turner, Piers Norris. 2018. Social Morality in Mill. In Public Reason in Political Philosophy: Classic Sources and Contemporary Commentaries, edited by Piers Norris Turner and Gerald Gaus, 375-400. New York: Routledge. Varouxakis, Georgios. 2013. Liberty Abroad: J. S. Mill on International Relations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.