Norva Y S Lo Produced by Norva Y S Lo Edited by Andrew Brennan

Similar documents
Norva Y S Lo Produced by Norva Y S Lo Edited by Andrew Brennan

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

Validity & Soundness LECTURE 3! Critical Thinking. Summary: In this week s lectures, we will learn! (1) What it is for an argument to be valid.

HANDBOOK. IV. Argument Construction Determine the Ultimate Conclusion Construct the Chain of Reasoning Communicate the Argument 13

2016 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions

b) The meaning of "child" would need to be taken in the sense of age, as most people would find the idea of a young child going to jail as wrong.

Part II: How to Evaluate Deductive Arguments

Critical Reasoning: A Romp Through the Foothills of Logic

Norva Y S Lo Produced by Norva Y S Lo Edited by Andrew Brennan. Fallacies of Presumption, Ambiguity, and Part-Whole Relations

A. Problem set #3 it has been posted and is due Tuesday, 15 November

2017 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions

What are Truth-Tables and What Are They For?

A Short Course in Logic Example 3

Critical Thinking. The Four Big Steps. First example. I. Recognizing Arguments. The Nature of Basics

Lecture 2.1 INTRO TO LOGIC/ ARGUMENTS. Recognize an argument when you see one (in media, articles, people s claims).

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy

2.1 Review. 2.2 Inference and justifications

Also, in Argument #1 (Lecture 11, Slide 11), the inference from steps 2 and 3 to 4 is stated as:

In general, the simplest of argument maps will take the form of something like this:

THE BASIC STRUCTURE OF AN ACADEMIC ESSAY

Kindergarten-2nd. June 6-7, Creation. Genesis 1; Philippians 4:6 Adv. Bible for Early Readers (pp. 2-3, 1382)

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

Philosophical Arguments

1.2. What is said: propositions

Use the following checklist to make sure you have revised everything.

National Quali cations

Lecture 4.2 Aquinas Phil Religion TOPIC: Aquinas Cosmological Arguments for the existence of God. Critiques of Aquinas arguments.

Follow Will of the People. Your leftist h. b. ave often d1sgusted b h

Artificial Intelligence Prof. P. Dasgupta Department of Computer Science & Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Kharagpur

Improving Students' "Dialectic Tracking" Skills (Diagramming Complex Arguments) Cathal Woods for 2010 AAPT Meeting.

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 1. Background Material for the Exercise on Validity

6.041SC Probabilistic Systems Analysis and Applied Probability, Fall 2013 Transcript Lecture 3

A Compatibilist Account of Free Will and Moral Responsibility

A man lives on the twelfth floor of an apartment building. Every morning he takes the elevator down to the lobby and leaves the building.

Meeting 2: Meeting Mr. No and drawing conclusions

Academic Writing and Logical Thinking

Kripke on the distinctness of the mind from the body

Christ LET ME SHOW YOU

Introduction to Logic

Am I free? Freedom vs. Fate

Ethics is subjective.

Test Item File. Full file at

Lecture 1: The Nature of Arguments

Cosmological Arguments

A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC FOR METAPHYSICIANS

A Judgmental Formulation of Modal Logic

November 1/2, 2008 Flee Sexual Immorality Living Like a Christian 1 Corinthians 6:12-20 Pastor Bryan Clark

1. What is Philosophy?

Argument. What is it? How do I make a good one?

PLEASE DO NOT WRITE ON THIS QUIZ

BONUS SCENE IN CONNOR S PERSPECTIVE. Copyright 2016 by Chelsea Field All rights reserved.

Fallacies. Definition: The premises of an argument do support a particular conclusion but not the conclusion that the arguer actually draws.

Lecture 7.1 Berkeley I

How Will I Be Graded in This Class?

Ethics and Science. Obstacles to search for truth. Ethics: Basic Concepts 1

Outline of today s lecture

Intro to Philosophy. Review for Exam 2

DIRECT AND INDIRECT SPEECH WITH BACKSHIFT OF TENSES

Relevance. Premises are relevant to the conclusion when the truth of the premises provide some evidence that the conclusion is true

The Philosopher s World Cup

Christ in Prophecy Apologetics 12: Barger on Questions from Non-Believers

MORRISON ZION EVANGELICAL LUTHERAN CHURCH zluth.org

A CHRISTIAN AND AN AMERICAN

A R G U M E N T S I N A C T I O N

Statements, Arguments, Validity. Philosophy and Logic Unit 1, Sections 1.1, 1.2

CRITICAL THINKING: THE VERY BASICS - HANDBOOK

Everything You Need to Know, or Almost, about Integrating Quotations Effectively

Universals. If no: Then it seems that they could not really be similar. If yes: Then properties like redness are THINGS.

Home with the children Ephesians 6:1-4

Chapter 1 Why Study Logic? Answers and Comments

20 November post-cabinet press conference page 1 of 7

Lecture 8 Keynes s Response to the Contradictions

Science and the Christian Faith. Brent Royuk June 11, 2006

Suppressed premises in real life. Philosophy and Logic Section 4.3 & Some Exercises

Kripke s Naming and Necessity. The Causal Picture of Reference

Please note I ve made some minor changes to his English to make it a smoother read KATANA]

Jesus in the Wilderness. January 10-11, Jesus showed us how to fight sin. Matthew 4:1-11, 1 John 4:19

Lemon Bay High School AP Language and Composition ENC 1102 Mr. Hertz

Why I Will Never Stop Teaching Unbliblical Things

Quinn s Doctrine of Doing and Allowing (DDA)

DIRECT AND INDIRECT SPEECH WITH BACKSHIFT OF TENSES

File Name: A6R Animals are Smart Argument/Opinion Grade 6 Range of Writing

Washington Post Interview with Rona Barrett by Robert Samuels. Robert Samuels: So let me tell you a little bit about what

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican,, Hertford College. Lecture 4: Two Cartesian Topics

Critical Thinking Session Three. Fallacies I: Problems to do with the Source

Keeping Your Kids On God s Side - Natasha Crain

SEVEN WOMEN ON HOLY SATURDAY JAMES HANVEY, SJ

Now in his 1st letter to the Corinthians St Paul has quite a barney about court cases:

Academic Writing and Logical Thinking

The Potential of Relational Discipleship! Acts 2:42; 1 John 1:1-4; 2:7-11!

Our scripture passages for today, for those listening later online, are. Numbers 11:4-6, 10-16, 24-29, Psalm 19, James 4:7-5:6, Mark 9:38-48

What is an argument? PHIL 110. Is this an argument? Is this an argument? What about this? And what about this?

About What Matters a short, pointed play between two women by Jennie Webb

On Freeman s Argument Structure Approach

Be Strong in the Lord by Rev. Kathy Sides (Preached at Fort Des Moines UMC )

Libertarian Free Will and Chance

SHORT ANSWER. Write the word or phrase that best completes each statement or answers the question.

How Big Is An Ark, Anyway? James E. Bogoniewski, Jr.

Transcription:

ritical Thinking Norva Y S Lo Produced by Norva Y S Lo Edited by Andrew Brennan LETURE 2! Arguments Summary In this week s lectures, you will learn (1) Argument (ollection of statements, some of which (the premises) are put forward as reasons to support one other (the conclusion)) (2) Inference (To make an inference is to move from the premises to the conclusion) (3) Inference indicators (Words or phrases that indicate the direction of inference) (4) Putting arguments in Standard Form (5) Drawing Argument Maps (6) Simple Argument vs. omplex Argument

Part I. What is an argument? Argument = df Set of statements, some of which (the premises) are put forward as reasons to support one other (the conclusion). Example #1: The following passage contains an argument. The reason why we should not eat meat from battery farms is that battery farming is cruel and we should not encourage any cruel practice. c a b Three statements (labelled as a, b, c ) are being put forward in the argument. Question: Answer: Which statements are put forward (i.e., intended by the author) as the premises and which statement is put forward as the conclusion? We need to look for inference indicators (i.e., words or phrases that indicate what the author intends to be reasons to support what). 1st 2nd 3rd The phrase the reason why is that and indicates that the statements in the 2nd and 3rd positions are intended as the premises (i.e., reasons) to support the statement inthe 1st position, the conclusion. onsider the inference indicator again: 1st 2nd 3rd The reason why is that and In fact, any statements occupying the 2nd and 3rd positions are the premises, and any statement occupying the 1st position is the conclusion. Example #2 The reason why today is Tuesday is that yesterday was Monday and tomorrow will be Wednesday. Premise: m Premise: w onclusion: t Premise: i Premise: p onclusion: g t m w Example #3 (Descartes s osmological Argument for the existence of God ) The reason why it is true that God exists is that I am an imperfect being who has a clear and distinct idea of God as a perfect being and only a perfect being can put the idea of a perfect being in an imperfect being. g p i

Important The same argument can be put in different ways where the order in which premises and conclusions are put forward can vary using different inference indicators. Examples (1) The reason why we should not eat meat from battery farms is that battery farming is cruel and we should not encourage any cruel practice. (2) Because we should not encourage any cruel practice and battery farming is cruel, we should not eat meat from battery farms. (3) Battery farming is cruel. So, we should not eat meat from battery farms, as we should not encourage any cruel practice.! All three passages express the same argument.! The conclusion comes before the two premises in passage (1), but after them in passage (2), and between them in passage (3). Part II. Inference Indicators As we have seen, in order to decide which statements in an argument are premises and which the conclusion, we need to look for inference indicators. They indicate what the author intends to be reasons to support what. Premise indicators indicate the presence of a premise. onclusion indicators indicate the presence of a conclusion. Premise Indicators: Since. because. Given that. For. Arguments formulated using premise indicators: Since it is raining outside (premise), we should stay inside. We should stay inside because it is raining outside (premise). Given that it is raining outside (premise), we should stay inside. We should stay inside. For it is raining outside (premise).! The statement appearing after a premise indicator is a premise. onclusion Indicators: Therefore So It follows that Accordingly Arguments formulated using conclusion indicators: He is a pathological liar. Therefore you should not trust him (conclusion). He is a pathological liar. So you should not trust him (conclusion). He is a pathological liar. It follows that you should not trust him (conclusion). He is a pathological liar. Accordingly, you should not trust him (conclusion).! The statement appearing after a conclusion indicator is a conclusion.! But some inference indicators indicate the presence of both premises and conclusion. For example (as we have seen): the reason why is that and.

ase 1: Is an argument being put forward? Yesterday was Monday. Today is Tuesday. Tomorrow will be Wednesday. Ans: No Or at least: there is no indication that the author intends to use any of the statements as reasons to support any other. So, we do not need to treat it as an argument. ase 2: Is an argument being put forward? Your cat is dead. Therefore, your cat is dead. Ans: Yes This argument is circular and therefore a bad argument. But a bad argument is still an argument. ase 3: Is an argument being put forward? Ans: Yes. ase 4: Is an argument being put forward? Ans: No. God exists. Therefore, Hell exists. The first statement God exists is put forward as a reason to support the second statement Hell exists as indicated by the inference indicator therefore. If God exists then Hell exists. To put forward a conditional statement (i.e., an if then claim) is not the same as putting forward an argument. In ase 3, when the author puts forward the argument, the author is committed to two claims God exists (the premise) and Hell exists (the conclusion). In ase 4, the author only puts forward a single statement, a conditional one. The author is committed only to the whole if-then claim if God exists then Hell exists, but not committed to the if-clause God exists itself, nor the then-clause Hell exists itself.

Part III. Standard Form conclusion premise premise The reason why we should not eat meat from battery farms is that battery farming is cruel and we should not encourage any cruel practice. After identifying the premises and conclusion in an argument, we can put the whole argument in Standard Form. Instructions! Draw a line to separate the premises and the (final) conclusion: premises above and conclusion below the line.! Label the premise using the capital letter P, or P1, P2, etc., if there are more than one premise.! Label the (final) conclusion using the capital letter.! Put a bracket at the end of the conclusion to indicate from where it gets support. Standard Form P1. P2. Battery farming is cruel. We should not encourage any cruel practice. -----------------------------------------------------------------------------. We should not eat meat from battery farms. (from P1 & P2) Part IV. Argument Map Standard Form P1. Battery farming is cruel. P2. We should not encourage any cruel practice. ---------------------------------------------------------------------------------------. We should not eat meat from battery farms. (from P1 & P2) After putting the argument in standard form, we draw an Argument Map for it. Argument Map P1 P2 It is up to you to draw an argument map vertically or horizontally. The arrow represents the direction of inference. The line joining P1 and P2 indicates that the two jointly (not individually) support. P1 P2 P1 P2

Question: What is it to make an argument (or put it forward, advance it, or endorse it)? Answer: That involves doing two things at the same time: (1) To claim that all the premises and conclusion are true (or more likely to be true than false), AND (2) To claim that the premises give good reasons to support the conclusion (i.e., to claim that the move from the premises to the conclusion is legitimate). We call the move from premises to conclusion an inference.! When you use statement A as a reason to support statement B, we say that you make an inference from A to B, or that you infer B from A.! By definition, premises are those statements used as reasons to support the conclusion. So, the direction of inference always goes from the premises to the conclusion.! If an inference from A to B is legitimate, we say that B is inferable from A, or that B follows from A. Note: One can make an inference from A to B without endorsing A or B.! From Barack Obama lives in London, you can legitimately infer Barack Obama lives in UK. But you don t need to endorse either statement as true. In fact, both statements are false.! To infer B from A is only to claim that B follows from A. Whether A or B itself is true is a separate matter.! Hence, making an argument is more than making an inference.! To make an argument from A to B, one needs to claim that A supports B and that both A and B are true.! To make an inference from A to B, one only needs to claim that A supports B. Recall our earlier definition of argument : Argument = df Set of statements, some of which (the premises) are put forward as reasons to support one other (the conclusion). Given the concepts of inference and following from, we can also define argument in the alternative ways below: Argument = df Set of statements, one of which (the conclusion) is meant to be inferable from the others (the premises). Argument = df Set of statements, one of which (the conclusion) is meant to follow from the others (the premises).

Question: What is it to accept an argument? It is to (1) accept all the premises and conclusions as true (or more likely to be true than false) and (2) accept the inference from the premises to the conclusion as legitimate. Question: What is it to reject an argument? It is to (1) reject at least one of the premises or the conclusion as false (or more likely to be false than true) or (2) reject the inference from the premises to the conclusion as illegitimate or do both (1) and (2) above. Note: You may do both if you wish, but that is not necessary in order to reject an argument. Just doing one of the two is sufficient to reject the entire argument.) A simple argument is one that contains only one inference. A complex argument is one that contains two or more inferences. The simpler arguments within a complex one are called sub-arguments. Example #1: The following passage contains a complex argument. Any reasonable person will agree with the creationist theory that some benevolent being created the universe. Why? Because this theory can explain the universe s being full of 'bright and beautiful things (e.g., little flowers, little birds). Now, the word God refers to whoever created the universe. So, it further follows that God exists. (Rebuttal: 'All things dull and ugly - Monty Python) Standard form Argument Map omplex argument P1. The creationist theory that some benevolent being created the universe can explain the universe s being full of bright and beautiful things. P2. The creationist theory, that some benevolent being created the universe, is true. (intermediate conclusion, from P1) P3. The word God refers to whoever created the universe. (definition) --------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------. God exists. (final conclusion, from P2 & P3) P1 P2 Simple arguments P3

Example #2: The following passage contains another complex argument. There are two facts. First, abortion is the killing of the fetus. Second, the fetus is an innocent human being. learly, from these two facts it follows that 3 abortion is the killing of an innocent human being. But we all know that it is always wrong to kill an innocent human being. As a result, abortion is wrong. The passage makes five claims: (1) Abortion is the killing of the fetus. (2) The fetus is an innocent human being. (3) Abortion is the killing of an innocent human being. (4) It is always wrong to kill an innocent human being. (5) Abortion is wrong. Given the inference indicators (marked in red), we can see that statements (1) and (2) are put forward as supportive reasons for statement (3), which are then put together with statement (4) to support statement (5). Standard form 1 2 4 5 Argument Map P1. Abortion is the killing of the fetus. P2. The fetus is an innocent human being. P3. Abortion is the killing of an innocent human being. (intermediate conclusion, from P1 & P2) P4. It is always wrong to kill an innocent human being. --------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------. Abortion is wrong. (final conclusion, from P3 & P4) P1 P3 P2 P4 Example #3 Reporter: Rumour says that you hope to take part in Donald Trump s reality show. Is that true? 1 Well, you know, only people who are desperate to get rich or famous would want to take 2 3 part in that show. But I am not desperate to get rich or famous because I already am. So, 4 why would I want to appear in that show? Ha-ha! Label all the statements used in the argument.! Look for inference indicators and identify the premises and conclusion. - The position of the word because indicates that (3) is used to support (2). - The position of the word so indicates that (4) is the final conclusion.! Rewrite the argument in Standard Form. - larify references. - All premises and conclusions must be put in the form of statements. Argument Map 3 1 2 4 (3) I am already rich and famous. (2) I am not desperate to get rich or famous. (intermediate conclusion, from (3)) (1) Only people who are desperate to get rich and famous would want to take part in Donald Trump s reality show. (4) I would not want to take part in Donald Trump s reality show. (final conclusion, from (1) & (2))

Example #4 P1 In morality, isn t one s intention all that matters!? Therefore, if an action is accompanied by a good intention then it is a right action. learly, euthanasia is accompanied by a good P3 intention, for its intention is to end suffering, and it is a good intention to end suffering. P4 So, why shouldn t euthanasia be permitted!? P5 P2 P1. In morality all that matters is one s intention. (rewritten as statement) P2. If an action is accompanied by a good intention then it is a right action. (intermediate conclusion, from P1) P3. The accompanying intention of euthanasia is to end suffering. P4. It is a good intention to end suffering. P5. Euthanasia is accompanied by a good intention. (intermediate conclusion, from P3 & P4) ------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------. Euthanasia should be permitted. (rewritten as statement, from P2 & P5) complex argument sub-arguments P1 P3 P2 P5 P4 Summary: How to detect arguments " When you try to decide whether a passage contains an argument, look for inference indicators. They help you identify what the author intends to be premises and conclusions. " An argument is made up of statements (premises and conclusions) which can be true or false. But sometimes a premise or conclusion is put in the form of a rhetorical question or disguised in some other way. When you put an argument in Standard Form, rewrite any disguised premise or conclusion in the form of a statement. " Not all words in the passage are relevant to the arguments being presented. Ignore the irrelevant words when you rewrite the arguments in Standard Form. " You may be given a passage which contains multiple complex arguments for different conclusions. For example, one passage may start by presenting an argument for a certain view, and then somewhere along the way offers a counter-argument against that view. You need to be able to tell one argument apart from another.

Example #5 According to Holmes, all natural things are good because God loves them. Why does God love all natural things? According to Holmes again, that is because all natural things are created by God and H4 God loves all his creations. However, Holmes is wrong. Some natural things (e.g., natural disasters) are actually created by Satan. But we all agree that everything created by Satan is bad. It follows that A3 H1 some natural things are bad. So, sorry Holmes, not all natural things are good. A4 A2 A1 H2 H3 There are two separate complex arguments in the above passage. The first one argues for the claim that all natural things are good. The second one argues against the claim. H4 H3 H2 H1 A4 A3 A1 A2 H4. God loves all his creations. H3. All natural things are created by God. H2. God loves all natural things. (from H1&H2) ---------------------------------------------------------------- H1. All natural things are good. (from H3) A1. Some natural things are created by Satan. A2. Everything created by Satan is bad. A3. Some natural things are bad. (from A1&A2) ----------------------------------------------------------------- A4. Not all natural things are good. (from A3) Example #6: The orey Delaney Worthington interview But orey is more of a smart ass than a dickhead, as analysis of his responses will show

Finding the arguments 2 4 5 6 I: Are you sorry? orey: Yeah, yeah, I am. I: You don t sound very sorry. Statement 1 orey: Well I can t be exactly blamed for everything that happened, because it wasn t in the house. It was out in the street, and 3 I didn t do it, like. The police said: You stay inside so you don t get in trouble, and I did what he said, so [shrugs] Premises onclusion 2 3 4 5 6 Genuine question Answer = statement orey can t be blamed for everything that happened Look for any more premise or conclusion... elsewhere in the interview. Argument orey: Yeah, but I don t think it s fair they ll be fined it, because what happened it was my party but it could have just been any random person walking in the street doing it. {What?} it happens all the time. There are two more statements here important to the argument. Start by listing the statements 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 orey can t be blamed for everything that happened It didn t happen in the house It happened in the street orey didn t do it The police told orey to stay inside so as not to get into trouble orey obeyed the police instructions Some outsider could have done the damage The damage to cars and property 8 It s not fair to fine orey or his parents Final ONLUSION Next, tidy them up by clarifying reference of pronouns... and add in the extra statements. Next, try to identify the conclusions and premises. Intermediate ONLUSION If there is no best way to do this because there are not enough inference indicators, then use your good sense to give the argument the most convincing interpretation.

OK - are we getting there? 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 orey can t be blamed for all the damage The damage didn t happen in the house The damage happened in the street orey didn t do the damage The police told orey to stay inside so as not to get into trouble orey obeyed the police instructions Some outsider could have done the damage It s not fair to fine orey or his parents Now you can map out the argument as a series of SUB-ARGUMENTS 4 and 7 independently support statement 1, from which the final conclusion, statement 8, follows orey isn t such a dickhead after all... Reminder: An atomic/simple argument contains only 1 inference. A compound/complex argument contains more than 1 inference. An inference is represented by an arrow in an argument map. 2 3 7 1 5 6 4 11 sub-arguments in total, some of which are atomic/simple while some others are compound/complex. an you identify the rest, and tell which is atomic, which is compound? 8 whole argument Summary In this week s lectures, you have learnt (1) Argument (ollection of statements, some of which (the premises) are put forward as reasons to support one other (the conclusion)) (2) Inference (To make an inference is to move from the premises to the conclusion) (3) Inference indicators (Words or phrases that indicate the direction of inference) (4) Putting arguments in Standard Form (5) Drawing Argument Maps (6) Simple Argument vs. omplex Argument

Discussion Question #2 Please answer the following question in at most 280 words. Question #2: For each passage below, determine and state whether it contains an argument. If the passage contains an argument, then identify the final conclusion and put the whole argument in the Standard Form. If the passage doesn t contain an argument, then explain why it doesn t. If you think that it cannot be determined whether the passage contains an argument, then explain why not. (Passage I) We know three things about God by definition of the term "God". First, God is all-knowing. It follows that if God exists then God must know that there is unnecessary suffering in the world. Second, God is all-loving. It follows that if God knows that unnecessary suffering exists then God must want to eliminate it. Third, we know that God is all-powerful. It follows that if God wants to eliminate any unnecessary suffering in the world then God must have done that by now. Therefore, we can conclude that if God exists then there cannot be any unnecessary suffering in the world. But the fact is that the world is full of unnecessary suffering. Doesn t this show that God does not exist? (Passage II) It is raining outside. Some people are carrying wet umbrellas. (Passage III) If it is raining outside, then some people are carrying wet umbrellas. Extra Question In the news article Europeans lead the push to wave the waif goodbye (click here), David Brown, owner of a model agency, defends the fashion industry against the view that it is a promoter of anorexia. What is his argument? Put it in the Standard Form. Is it a good argument? Why? Or why not? BAK TO ritical Thinking Homepage