Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

Similar documents
Philosophical Review.

International Phenomenological Society

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

History of Education Society

Bayesian Probability

Bayesian Probability

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Journal of Philosophy, Inc.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

IS IT ALWAYS RATIONAL TO SATISFY SAVAGE S AXIOMS?

The Problem with Complete States: Freedom, Chance and the Luck Argument

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Degrees of Belief II

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

PROSPECTIVE TEACHERS UNDERSTANDING OF PROOF: WHAT IF THE TRUTH SET OF AN OPEN SENTENCE IS BROADER THAN THAT COVERED BY THE PROOF?

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Probability Foundations for Electrical Engineers Prof. Krishna Jagannathan Department of Electrical Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

You submitted this quiz on Mon 14 Oct :41 PM PDT (UTC -0700). You got a score of out of

Detachment, Probability, and Maximum Likelihood

ON THE TRUTH CONDITIONS OF INDICATIVE AND COUNTERFACTUAL CONDITIONALS Wylie Breckenridge

Introduction to Statistical Hypothesis Testing Prof. Arun K Tangirala Department of Chemical Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Journal of Philosophy, Inc.

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview

McDougal Littell High School Math Program. correlated to. Oregon Mathematics Grade-Level Standards

Reductio ad Absurdum, Modulation, and Logical Forms. Miguel López-Astorga 1

Prentice Hall The American Nation: Beginnings Through 1877 '2002 Correlated to: Chandler USD Social Studies Textbook Evaluation Instrument (Grade 8)

Oxford University Press and The Analysis Committee are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Analysis.

Uncertainty in the Context of Pragmatist Philosophy and Rational Choice Theory

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1

Artificial Intelligence Prof. P. Dasgupta Department of Computer Science & Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Kharagpur

The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Ethics.

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Here s a very dumbed down way to understand why Gödel is no threat at all to A.I..

Possibility and Necessity

How Subjective Fact Ties Language to Reality

Stout s teleological theory of action

Macmillan/McGraw-Hill SCIENCE: A CLOSER LOOK 2011, Grade 3 Correlated with Common Core State Standards, Grade 3

Free Acts and Chance: Why the Rollback Argument Fails Lara Buchak, UC Berkeley

Russell: On Denoting

Final Paper. May 13, 2015

The SAT Essay: An Argument-Centered Strategy

6.041SC Probabilistic Systems Analysis and Applied Probability, Fall 2013 Transcript Lecture 21

Debates and Decisions: On a Rationale of Argumentation Rules

Grade 6 correlated to Illinois Learning Standards for Mathematics

Conditionals II: no truth conditions?

Is it rational to have faith? Looking for new evidence, Good s Theorem, and Risk Aversion. Lara Buchak UC Berkeley

This report is organized in four sections. The first section discusses the sample design. The next

Is the Identity of Indiscernibles refuted by Max Black's thought experiment? What is the Principle of Identity of Indiscernibles (PII)?

Asking the Right Questions: A Guide to Critical Thinking M. Neil Browne and Stuart Keeley

Symbolic Logic Prof. Chhanda Chakraborti Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Kharagpur

A QUANTITATIVE STUDY OF THE BACKGROUND OF RELIGIOUS BELIEFS, ATTITUDES AND PRACTICES OF YOUNG RUSSIAN EVANGELICAL CONVERTS

SUMMARY COMPARISON of 6 th grade Math texts approved for 2007 local Texas adoption

Bradley on Chance, Admissibility & the Mind of God

The Kripkenstein Paradox and the Private World. In his paper, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Languages, Kripke expands upon a conclusion

In his paper Studies of Logical Confirmation, Carl Hempel discusses

Most philosophy books, it s fair to say, contain more footnotes than graphs. By this

Judith Jarvis Thomson s Normativity

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information

The Prospective View of Obligation

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

Truth and Evidence in Validity Theory

Belief, Rationality and Psychophysical Laws. blurring the distinction between two of these ways. Indeed, it will be argued here that no

2.1 Review. 2.2 Inference and justifications

Primitive Thisness and Primitive Identity by Robert Merrihew Adams (1979)

Georgia Quality Core Curriculum

Learning is a Risky Business. Wayne C. Myrvold Department of Philosophy The University of Western Ontario

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Basic Concepts and Skills!

THE ROLE OF COHERENCE OF EVIDENCE IN THE NON- DYNAMIC MODEL OF CONFIRMATION TOMOJI SHOGENJI

Artificial Intelligence: Valid Arguments and Proof Systems. Prof. Deepak Khemani. Department of Computer Science and Engineering

Gilbert. Margaret. Scientists Are People Too: Comment on Andersen. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 6, no. 5 (2017):

What God Could Have Made

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 110, No. 3. (Jul., 2001), pp

Six Sigma Prof. Dr. T. P. Bagchi Department of Management Indian Institute of Technology, Kharagpur

A Course In Miracle Workbook For Dummies

Christ-Centered Critical Thinking. Lesson 6: Evaluating Thinking

Types of Uncertainty

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth).

A Discussion on Kaplan s and Frege s Theories of Demonstratives

175 Chapter CHAPTER 23: Probability

Informalizing Formal Logic

SEPARATION OF CHURCH AND STATE: HISTORICAL FACT AND CURRENT FICTION. By Robert L. Cord. New York: Lambeth Press Pp. xv, 302. $16.95.

Subjective Probability Does Not Exist Dr. Asad Zaman

Russell on Denoting. G. J. Mattey. Fall, 2005 / Philosophy 156. The concept any finite number is not odd, nor is it even.

A DILEMMA FOR JAMES S JUSTIFICATION OF FAITH SCOTT F. AIKIN

Region of Inexactness and Related Concepts

Writing & Technology Amy Koppen NCSU

Don t Even Think About It Why Our Brains Are Wired to Ignore Climate Change

What is the difference between Expository Essays and Persuasive Essays?

Question the fundamental assumptions of game theoretic analysis. 1. Rational decision-making 2. Common knowledge of rationality 3.

Gandalf s Solution to the Newcomb Problem. Ralph Wedgwood

Compromise and Toleration: Some Reflections I. Introduction

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

Contradictory Information Can Be Better than Nothing The Example of the Two Firemen

Rational choice as a toolbox for the economist: an interview with Itzhak Gilboa

Transcription:

Risk, Ambiguity, and the Savage Axioms: Comment Author(s): Howard Raiffa Source: The Quarterly Journal of Economics, Vol. 75, No. 4 (Nov., 1961), pp. 690-694 Published by: Oxford University Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1884326 Accessed: 06-09-2017 21:32 UTC JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://about.jstor.org/terms Oxford University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Quarterly Journal of Economics

RISK, AMBIGUITY, AND THE SAVAGE AXIOMS: COMMENT By HOWARD RAIFFA Ellsberg writes: I propose to indicate a class of choice-situations in which many otherwise reasonable people neither wish nor tend to conform to the Savage postulates, nor to the other axiom sets that have been devised. But the implications of such a finding, if true, are not wholly destructive. First, both the predictive and normative use of the Savage or equivalent postulates might be improved by avoiding attempts to apply them in certain, specifiable circumstances where they do not seem acceptable. Second, we might hope that it is precisely in such circumstances that certain proposals for alternative decision rules and nonprobabilistic descriptions of uncertainty (e.g., by Knight, Shackle, Hurwicz, and Hodges and L mann) might prove fruitful. I believe, in fact, that this is the case.' Let me introduce myself as one who accepts Savage's postulates or equivalent rules for a much wider domain of problems than does either Ellsberg or Fellner. In particular, I find that I would want to behave in a manner consistent with Savage's normative prescriptions of behavior in the examples cited by the above authors. At the outset I will agree with them that it is not hard to elicit from most people (and I include myself in this category) a set of mutually inconsistent responses to questions or to observe in their actions inconsistent behavior. But I wish to reaffirm, what these authors also emphasize, that Savage's theory is not a descriptive or predictive theory of behavior. It is a theory which purports to advise any one of its believers how he should behave in complicated situations, provided he can make choices in a coherent manner in relatively simple, uncomplicated situations. The fact that most people can be shown to be inconsistent in their manifest choice behavior cuts two ways: First, it emphasizes the difficulties encountered in putting into practice a model which demands in each application that the decision-maker assign a set of preferences to a host of simple problems which are internally consistent. Second, it clearly demonstrates how important it is to have a theory which can be used to aid in the making of decisions under uncertainty. If most people behaved in a manner roughly consistent with Savage's theory then the theory would gain stature as a descrip- 1. Op. cit., p. 646. 690

RISK, AMBIGUITY, AND THE SAVAGE AXIOMS 691 tive theory but would lose a good deal of its normative importance. We do not have to teach people what comes naturally. But as it is, we need to do a lot of teaching; and to help point out this need, I particularly like the examples cited in Ellsberg's and Fellner's papers. Several years ago, Ellsberg tested some of his observations on me. As an experimental subject I was hopelessly contaminated because I had already thought hard about the discussion in Jimmy Savage's book on the Allais Paradox. My immediate impulse was to break apart some of the options he asked me to consider into simpler components and then to force internal consistency on myself by means of the Savage model. But as Ellsberg pointed out, this was not playing his game and he asked me for a reply to his questions without any pencil pushing. I complied and I was found wanting. I was inconsistent. But I was uncomfortably inconsistent, because some of the options he posed seemed too complicated to me and I wanted to reduce them by means of the Sure-thing Principle. Of course, if I had done this, I would have forced consistency on myself. Naturally, when he pointed out that I was inconsistent I insisted that if I were playing the game for real I would pay a premium to be allowed to change my choices so that I would not violate the Surething Principle. Each of us went away from that meeting with different messages: he with the notion of the limitations of the Savage theory; I with renewed respect for the importance of the Savage theory. I started to experiment on my own with adaptations of Ellsberg's counter-intuitive examples. My subjects were students at the Harvard Business School and a few seasoned business executives - "men of experience." Immediately I observed what I shall call the "two-shift-effect." I found that when relative frequencies or so-called objective probabilities were given in numerical form as data of a decision problem, then these were often used in computing various indices (e.g., expected or actuarial values) which served as a guide to action. But if certain uncertainties in the problem were in cloudy or fuzzy form, then very often there was a shifting of gears and no effort at all was made to think deliberately and reflectively about the problem. Systematic decomposition of the problem was shunned and an over-all "seat of the pants" judgment was made which usually graphically reflected the temperament of the decision-maker. (I refer here to the pessimism-optimism polarity.) In reporting this, I am just confirming the experience of Ellsberg and Fellner (and also

692 QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF ECONOMICS of Shackle, Knight, etc.). However, I draw a different message from this experience. There is a need to teach people how to cope with uncertainty in a purposive and reflective manner, and to break down the taboo that probabilities should only be assigned if one has clearcut relative frequency data at hand. As one step toward making this view more palatable I have regularly used in my classes the following adaptation of one of Ellsberg's thought-provoking problems. I believe the following questionnaire (two questions plus the brief preamble) should be clear enough. You might enjoy trying this yourself now. In the classroom I usually emphasize the fact that "You," the subject, have complete freedom of calling "red" or "black" in both of the questions below. EXHIBIT AN EXPERIMENT INVOLVING OBJECTIVE AND SUBJECTIVE PROBABILITIES Please answer the following questions as fairly as you can, indicating how you personally would act if faced with the choices described. This is not a quiz; there is no single "right" answer to either question. Question 1 Suppose you have been offered the following proposition: You will be given an urn containing exactly 50 red balls and 50 black balls; there are no balls of other colors in the urn. You will name a color (red or black), and then without looking, draw a single ball from the urn. Suppose, further, that the pay-offs are as follows: (a) If the color you name differs from your drawing you get nothing. (b) If the color you name agrees with your drawing your gain is $100. Keeping in mind yourfinancial position as of today, and remembering that the game is to be played just once, up to how much would you be willing to pay in order to participate in this game? $ Question 2 Suppose now, that youf have been offered the same proposition as above, except that in this case the urn contains an unknown number of red balls and an unknown number of black balls; that is, the urn may contain all black balls, all red balls, or a mixture of the two, but there are no balls of other colors in the urn. The procedure and the pay-offs are exactly the same as in Question 1.

RISK, AMBIGUITY, AND THE SAVAGE AXIOMS 693 Keeping in mind yourfinancial position as of today, and remembering that the game is to be played just once. up to how much would you be willing to pay in order to participate in this game? $ The answers for the first question clustered somewhere around $30. Several subjects go down as low as $10 and a few go as high as $45. Of course, although the actuarial or expected value of the game is $50 there is nothing "incorrect" about any of these answers. A majority of the subjects offered considerably more for question 1 than for question 2. For example, an answer of $35 for question 1 and $5 for question 2 would be a typical pair. On the other hand, a minority gave like amounts: $40 and $40 or $10 and $10, etc. According to the Savage Axioms the second option should be worth at least as much as the first. It's fun to listen to a group of subjects argue in class whether or not the second option is worse than the first. There is not only division of opinion but opinions do not change easily. But then someone - all too often that someone is I - comes up with the following argument: Suppose you withdraw a ball from the urn with unknown composition but do not look at its color. Now toss a fair (unbiased) coin and call "red" if heads, "black" if tails. The "objective" probability of getting a match is now.5 and therefore it is just as desirable to participate in the second game as in the first. I have found out that after the student convinces himself it does not matter whether the ball is drawn first or whether the coin is tossed first, that he is most willing to increase his price for the second game up to the price he was willing to pay in the first game. Incidentally, I tried this same experiment on a graduate class in statistics in which all the students had prior courses in mathematical statistics and the pattern of answers, as well as the ensuing free-for-all discussion, was very much like the experiences I had with business school students who had had no previous courses in statistics. As a second example let us use the very ingenious example given by Ellsberg, where a subject chooses a ball from an urn containing 30 red balls and 60 (black and yellow) balls, the latter in unknown proportion. Recall that the four acts he considers lead to the array: State Red Black Yellow I 100 0 0 A ctii 0 100 0 III 100 0 100 IV 0 100 100

694 QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF ECONOMICS I concur with Ellsberg that most subjects choose act I over II and IV over III, thus violating the Savage Axioms. Also I admit that many of these subjects are reluctant to change their choices when it is pointed out to them that their behavior is inconsistent with the Sure-thing Principle. Many are also not very impressed with the argument that no partition of the sixty (black, yellow) balls would lead to the pattern I over II and IV over III. Well, I would like to undermine further their confidence in their initial choices! I find the following argument is quite persuasive. Suppose you register I > II and IV > III. I now offer you the paired comparison between the following two options: In option A a fair (unbiased) coin is tossed and act I is taken if heads appears, whereas act IV is taken if tails appears; with option B, heads leads to act II and tails to act III. In table form we get: Heads Tails Option A: Act I Act IV Option B: Act II Act III Now by strict dominance option A is better than B for you since you prefer I to II and IV to III. So far there is no trouble but let's take a closer look at options A and B. The final outcomes of either option depend on the toss of the coin and the selection of a ball. Now let's do the accounting by analyzing the implications of the options conditional on the color of the withdrawn ball. Our analysis takes the form: Red Black Yellow Option A (An "objective" 50-50_ chance of $100 and $0J -> same same Option B same -- same - same But this reasoning should lead everyone to assert that options A and B are objectively identical! Something must give! I cannot see how anyone could refute the logic leading to the conclusion that given your initial choices, you should prefer option A to option B. This bit of logic is certainly not the weak link in the argument. But then again these options look awfully alike to me! Therefore, on thinking it over, wouldn't you like to change your mind about your initial preferences? HARVARD UNIVERSITY