Intro Viewed from a certain angle, philosophy is about what, if anything, we ought to believe.

Similar documents
MCQ IN TRADITIONAL LOGIC. 1. Logic is the science of A) Thought. B) Beauty. C) Mind. D) Goodness

2016 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions

ELEMENTS OF LOGIC. 1.1 What is Logic? Arguments and Propositions

Pastor-teacher Don Hargrove Faith Bible Church September 8, 2011

Logic Appendix: More detailed instruction in deductive logic

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Argumentation Module: Philosophy Lesson 7 What do we mean by argument? (Two meanings for the word.) A quarrel or a dispute, expressing a difference

C. Exam #1 comments on difficult spots; if you have questions about this, please let me know. D. Discussion of extra credit opportunities

Helpful Hints for doing Philosophy Papers (Spring 2000)

Full file at

Moore on External Relations

Deduction. Of all the modes of reasoning, deductive arguments have the strongest relationship between the premises

CRITICAL THINKING (CT) MODEL PART 1 GENERAL CONCEPTS

2. Refutations can be stronger or weaker.

Lecture 1: Validity & Soundness

Lecture 3 Arguments Jim Pryor What is an Argument? Jim Pryor Vocabulary Describing Arguments

Academic argument does not mean conflict or competition; an argument is a set of reasons which support, or lead to, a conclusion.

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 1. Background Material for the Exercise on Validity

PHILOSOPHY 102 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC PRACTICE EXAM 1. W# Section (10 or 11) 4. T F The statements that compose a disjunction are called conjuncts.

Instructor s Manual 1

Lecture 2.1 INTRO TO LOGIC/ ARGUMENTS. Recognize an argument when you see one (in media, articles, people s claims).

PHILOSOPHY ESSAY ADVICE

Portfolio Project. Phil 251A Logic Fall Due: Friday, December 7

A R G U M E N T S I N A C T I O N

Logic Book Part 1! by Skylar Ruloff!

Basic Concepts and Skills!

A Primer on Logic Part 1: Preliminaries and Vocabulary. Jason Zarri. 1. An Easy $10.00? a 3 c 2. (i) (ii) (iii) (iv)

Overview of Today s Lecture

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

Criticizing Arguments

National Quali cations

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 5

2017 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions

I think, therefore I am. - Rene Descartes

BASIC CONCEPTS OF LOGIC

On Priest on nonmonotonic and inductive logic

Skim the Article to Find its Conclusion and Get a Sense of its Structure

Informalizing Formal Logic

What is an argument? PHIL 110. Is this an argument? Is this an argument? What about this? And what about this?

Chapter 1 - Basic Training

PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy

6: DEDUCTIVE LOGIC. Chapter 17: Deductive validity and invalidity Ben Bayer Drafted April 25, 2010 Revised August 23, 2010

Study Guides. Chapter 1 - Basic Training

PHI Introduction Lecture 4. An Overview of the Two Branches of Logic

Do we have knowledge of the external world?

What is a logical argument? What is deductive reasoning? Fundamentals of Academic Writing

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Genre Guide for Argumentative Essays in Social Science

BASIC CONCEPTS OF LOGIC

Chapter 1 Why Study Logic? Answers and Comments

1.5 Deductive and Inductive Arguments

ISSA Proceedings 1998 Wilson On Circular Arguments

Asking the Right Questions: A Guide to Critical Thinking M. Neil Browne and Stuart Keeley

Department of Philosophy

Critical Thinking 5.7 Validity in inductive, conductive, and abductive arguments

Teachur Philosophy Degree 2018

Course Learning Outcomes for Unit V

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

Chadwick Prize Winner: Christian Michel THE LIAR PARADOX OUTSIDE-IN

The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions. Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction Defining induction...

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

HOW TO ANALYZE AN ARGUMENT

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

Kripke on the distinctness of the mind from the body

Argument Basics. When an argument shows that its conclusion is worth accepting we say that the argument is good.

Complications for Categorical Syllogisms. PHIL 121: Methods of Reasoning February 27, 2013 Instructor:Karin Howe Binghamton University

Introduction to Philosophy Crito. Instructor: Jason Sheley

OTTAWA ONLINE PHL Basic Issues in Philosophy

Philosophical Arguments

A Brief History of Thinking about Thinking Thomas Lombardo

The Critical Mind is A Questioning Mind

2013 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved. 1

Introduction Symbolic Logic

Critical Thinking - Wk 3. Instructor: Jason Sheley

The Problem of Major Premise in Buddhist Logic

1.6 Validity and Truth

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece

1. To arrive at the truth we have to reason correctly. 2. Logic is the study of correct reasoning. B. DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE ARGUMENTS

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

Creation & necessity

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

Reading and Evaluating Arguments

CHAPTER THREE Philosophical Argument

! Introduction to the Class! Some Introductory Concepts. Today s Lecture 1/19/10

Please visit our website for other great titles:

Logic: The Science that Evaluates Arguments

Circularity in ethotic structures

Introduction to Logic. Instructor: Jason Sheley

Chapter 1. Introduction. 1.1 Deductive and Plausible Reasoning Strong Syllogism

Critical Thinking is:

Logic, Deductive And Inductive By Carveth Read READ ONLINE

A. Problem set #3 it has been posted and is due Tuesday, 15 November

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

A s a contracts professional, from

Introducing Our New Faculty

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Artificial Intelligence: Valid Arguments and Proof Systems. Prof. Deepak Khemani. Department of Computer Science and Engineering

Handout for: Ibn Sīnā: analysis with modal syllogisms

Transcription:

Overview Philosophy & logic 1.2 What is philosophy? 1.3 nature of philosophy Why philosophy Rules of engagement Punctuality and regularity is of the essence You should be active in class It is good to put your mobile phone on vibration but silence mood is preferred Why Should I Study philosophy & Logic? Because it is a required (or an optional) subject. (I need the credits to graduate!!!) Because logic has application in any subject which employs inference and argument. This includes every domain of intellectual endeavor as well as the practical affairs of everyday life Because the standards of logic apply to every person in the universe - even to Mr. or Ms. E Cont. It help students to think critically; Logic is the field of study concerned with analysing and appraising the goodness or badness of arguments. Critical thinking is the name given to the thought processes used in evaluating arguments. It gives students the tools to evaluate arguments; through philosophy students minimize committing common fallacies that appear in everyday life Logic & critical thinking disciplined intellectual criticism that combines research, knowledge of historical context, and balanced judgment Outlines What is Logic? Why Study Logic? Arguments, Forms, and Truth Values Deductive Criteria Inductive Criteria Fallacies Intro Viewed from a certain angle, philosophy is about what, if anything, we ought to believe.

There are many sources for our beliefs the influence of our parents and friends, newspapers, television, internet, government, churches, schools, textbooks, our own observations, and our own thought processes but not all these sources are equally good, nor is any of them good all the time. Intro Many of the beliefs attained through casual observation and most of the teaching and socialization of childhood is simply absorbed without our realizing it. Despite our best efforts, this uncritical acceptance of claims and formation of beliefs continues through adulthood. But such uncritical thinking can be a dangerous thing, for it enslaves us to the influence and manipulations of other individuals and institutions Thus, since our beliefs (the claims we accept) constitute our view of the world and of ourselves, and affect how we act, it is important to examine more carefully the beliefs we hold. This applies both to large scale philosophical issues (Does God exist? Do I have a soul? Am I free? Does it matter?), and to small scale mundane issues (Should I buy this car? Should I believe what she said? Howshould I dress?). This is what we will spend the rest of the semester doing-examining various of our fundamental philosophical beliefs about the world, ourselves, and our values. What is Logic? Logic is the study of argument. In particular, logic is the study of criteria for distinguishing successful from unsuccessful arguments and the study of methods for applying those criteria. Argument By 'argument' I do not mean a shouting match or angry disagreement). Rather, an argument is a set of statements, some of which the premises are supposed to support, or give reasons for, the remaining statement the conclusion. Usually the intent behind an argument is to produce understanding or conviction in oneself or another. However, by successful argument', I do not mean one which merely succeeds in persuading the reader or listener or thinker. Due to the foibles of human psychology and/ or the use of manipulative rhetorical devices, people can be persuaded by arguments even though the premises do not genuinely support the conclusion Here we shall focus on the core principles which any such critical strategies presuppose: the criteria for successful argument.the basic idea behind these criteria is that the premises should genuinely support the conclusion. Why study logic skill in logical analysis and evaluation is the core of critical thinking. So, increasing your logical abilities will lead to a corresponding increase in your overall critical ability. You will be better able to guard against psychological fallibility and manipulative rhetoric your own as well as others. While a basic understanding of some logic will not determine for you what you ought to believe it is an essential tool for being a strong critical thinker. And whether you are writing a paper in philosophy, having a discussion with a friend, watching the news, or buying a computer, it is always to the good to be a strong critical thinker.

First, there is the discovery and learning of new things. Then there is aesthetic and intellectual delight in abstract structures and systems. Less grandiose, perhaps, is the enjoyment of puzzle solving and rising to meet an intellectual challenge. This is not to say that appreciating logic as good in itself is required to do well in philosophy. Far from it. But it will help you to understand some logic. Terms Logic: Logic is the study of (i) criteria for distinguishing successful from unsuccessful argument, (ii) (ii) methods for applying those criteria, Statement: A statement is a declarative sentence; a sentence which attempts to state a fact as opposed to a question, a command, an exclamation. Truth Value: The truth value of a statement is just its truth or falsehood. Cont Logic is the science of the correctness or incorrectness of reasoning, or the study of the evaluation of arguments. A statement is a declarative sentence, or part of a sentence, that can be true or false. How many statements are there in this example? The Winter Olympics are in Italy this year, but four years from now they will be in Vancouver, Canada. 3.A proposition is what is meant by a statement (the idea or notion it expresses) (this might be the same for different sentences) An argument is a collection of statements or propositions,some of which are intended to provide support or evidence in favor of one of the others. 5. Premises are those statements or propositions in an argument that are intended to provide the support or evidence. 6. The conclusion is that statement or proposition for which the premises are intended to provide support. (In short, it is the point the argument is trying to make.) (Important note: premises are always intended to provide support or evidence for the conclusion, but they don't always succeed. It's still an argument either way.) P1. If Bush lied to Congress, then Bush should be impeached. P2. Bush lied to Congress.

C. Therefore, Bush should be impeached. Every wizard uses a magic. P2. Mr. A uses a magic. C. Therefore, A is a wizard. Statement is either true or false but not both. The truth value of a given statement is fixed whether or not we know what that truth value is. Issues of vagueness, ambiguity, subjectivity, and various sorts of indeterminacy may lead us to think that some statements are neither true nor false, or both true and false, or "somewhere in between". Argument: An argument is a (finite) set of, some of which the premises are supposed to support, or give reasons for, the remaining statement the conclusion. When we encounter an argument in the course of reading or during discussion the premises and conclusion may come in any order. Consider Pat is mortal, for all humans are mortal, and Pat is human Given that Socrates is human, Socrates is mortal; since all humans are mortal All humans are mortal; Socrates is human; therefore, Socrates is mortal Three statements are involved in each of the above examples (two premises and a conclusion), and despite the fact that they appear in different order in each one, all three examples express the same argument. For the sake of clarity we will often transcribe arguments into what is called standard form we list the premises, draw line, and then write the conclusion Standard form All humans are mortal Socrates is human Socrates is mortal This is usually done through contextual clues, including the indicator words/phrases I used above. Below are two brief lists of conclusion and premise indicators: Premise Indicators: as, since, for, because, given that, for the reason that, inasmuch as Conclusion Indicators: therefore, hence, thus, so, we may infer, consequently, it follows that Argument form & instance An argument form (sometimes called a schema) is the framework of an argument which results when certain portions of the component sentences are replaced by blanks or schematic letters. An argument instance is what results when the blanks in a form are appropriately filled in. For example, the argument presented above is an instance of the following form:

All Fare G x is F x is G All pop-stars are attention-starved Ernest is a pop star Ernest is attention-starved Criteria 4 evaluating argument Now I will divide criteria for evaluating arguments into two basic types. We will have similar but different things to say about what counts as "success" for each type. The two types are Deductive and Inductive. Deductive reasoning Deduction is a form of reasoning in which a conclusion follows necessarily from the stated premises. Deduction is generally an inference by reasoning from the general to the specific. A deduction is also the conclusion reached by a deductive reasoning process. One classic example of deductive reasoning is that found in syllogisms like the following: Premise 1: All humans are mortal. Premise 2: Ernest is a human. Conclusion: Ernest is mortal. The reasoning in this argument is valid, because there is no way in which the premises, 1 and 2, could be true and the conclusion, 3, be false. Syllogisms Logical argument involving three propositions: A formal deductive argument made up of a major premise, a minor premise, and a conclusion. An example is, "All birds have feathers, vultures are birds, and therefore vultures have feathers." Deductive Criteria Deductive criteria, roughly speaking, require that the premises guarantee the truth of the conclusion. There are two questions we want to ask when applying deductive criteria. One, the question of validity, has to do with the connection between the premises and conclusion. The other, the question of soundness, has to do with the truth values of the premises. Deductive Validity, Invalidity:

An argument (form) is deductively valid if and only if it is NOT possible for ALL the premises to be true AND the conclusion false. An argument (form) is deductively invalid if and only if it is not valid. I.e., an argument is valid if and only if the assumed truth of the premises would guarantee the truth of the conclusion if you mull it over you'll see that these say basically the same thing; though the statement above is our official definition of validity. Soundness: An argument is sound if and only if it is deductively valid AND all its premises are true soundness refers to arguments, which means that the premises of a valid argument are true in the actual world. eg All whales are mammals All mammals are air-breathers All whales are air-breathers Valid and Sound All whales are fish All fish are air-breathers All whales are air-breathers Valid but Unsound Conclusion False Not Possible! FORM 1 All whales are reptiles all F are G All reptiles are birds All whales are birds All F are FI Valid but Unsound Valid FORM All G are FI See that all three arguments of Form 1 are valid, and that this has nothing to do with the actual truth values of the component claims. That is, despite the actual truth value of the component statements in each instance, there is no way (it is NOT possible) that the premises could ALL be true AND the conclusion false Some animals are frogs Some animals are tree-climbers Some frogs are tree-climbers Invalid 2B

Some fish are frogs * Some fish are tree-climbers Some frogs are tree-climbers Invalid Conclusion False 2C Some animals are frogs Some animals are birds Some frogs are birds Invalid 2D Now look at the four arguments of Form 2 in Table 2. First, note that they are all invalid. That is, despite the actual truth values of the component sentences, in each instance it is possible for all the premises to be true and the conclusion false.2a, 2B, and 2D, will require some imagination, but you will see that you can consistently imagine all the premises true and the conclusion false in each case. 2C takes no imagination at all Counterexample: A counterexample to an argument (form) is an argument instance of exactly the same form having all true premises and a false conclusion Production of a counterexample shows that the argument form and all instances thereof are invalid. (Failure to produce counterexample shows nothing, however).inference Logic reasoning process: the process of reasoning from a premise to a conclusion implication: something that is implied An inference is deductively valid if and only if there is no possible situation in which all the premises are true but the conclusion false. An inductive argument can be neither valid nor Invalid; its premises give only some degree of probability, but not certainty, to its conclusion. Here are some points to remember about deductive validity. Validity is a question of truth preservation, and this is a question of form, so the actual truth values of the premises and conclusion are irrelevant. All true premises and true conclusion do not make a valid argument! See 1B, 1D, and (especially) 2A. If an argument is valid and all its premises are true, then it is sound. Soundness does have to do with the actual truth value of the premises. Thus, it is not a matter of form. We can see that a particular argument, and all arguments of the same form, are invalid either by consistently imagining that all the premises are true and the conclusion false, or by finding a counter example (an instance which actually does have all true premises and a false conclusion).

148 Inductive Criteria Traditionally, deductive reasoning was said to be that which proceeds from the general to the particular, while inductive reasoning was said to move from the particular to the general. But this is incorrect. Some deductively successful arguments have particular premises and particular conclusions. Moreover, some inductively successful arguments invoke general premises and/or arrive at particular conclusions. I, therefore, dispense with this traditional way of making the distinction. I will distinguish inductive from deductive criteria in terms of the sort of support the premises are required to give the conclusion. Again, there are two questions we want to ask when applying inductive criteria. One, the question of strength, has to do with the connection between the premises and conclusion. The other, the question of cogency, has to do with the truth values of the premises. First, strength: Inductive Strength: An argument is inductively strong to the degree to which the premises provide evidence to make the truth of the conclusion plausible or probable. If an argument is not strong, it is weak. Note the contrast with deductive validity, which requires that premises guarantee the truth of the conclusion. Here, inductive strength is a matter of the degree of plausibility or probability. Also in contrast to the definition of validity, the definition of strength does not apply to argument forms, but only to individual instances. Cogency: An argument is cogent if and only if it is inductively strong AND all the premises are true. With respect to strength, cogency plays a role analogous to that which soundness plays with respect to validity. In both cases we have a question about the connection between premises and conclusion (validity or strength), and then a question about the truth value of the premises. Consider the following examples: This bag has 100 marbles in it 80 of them are black 20 of them are white The next marble I pick will be black It is 5pm on Monday But the mail has not come yet The mail carrier is almost never late It must be a holiday

What Makes an Argument a Good One? 1. By definition, an argument is deductively valid if and *only if the form of the argument makes it impossible for the conclusion to be false if the premises are true. 2. By definition, an argument is factually correct if and only if all its premises are true. 3. To be a good argument, an argument needs to both Valid and factually correct. By definition, an argument is sound if and only if it is both Deductively valid and factually correct.