Theoretical Virtues in Science

Similar documents
Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

Realism and the success of science argument. Leplin:

Psillos s Defense of Scientific Realism

FINAL EXAM REVIEW SHEET. objectivity intersubjectivity ways the peer review system is supposed to improve objectivity

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

HPS 1653 / PHIL 1610 Revision Guide (all topics)

HPS 1653 / PHIL 1610 Introduction to the Philosophy of Science

PHIL 155: Introduction. January 9, 2013

Scientific realism and anti-realism

145 Philosophy of Science

How Successful Is Naturalism?

We aim to cover in some detail a number of issues currently debated in the philosophy of natural and social science.

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

Scientific Realism and Empiricism

Class 6 - Scientific Method

What the History of Science Cannot Teach Us Ioannis Votsis University of Bristol

Philosophers and Scientists Are Social Epistemic Agents. Seungbae Park, Ulsan National Institute of Science and Technology

The Positive Argument for Constructive Empiricism and Inference to the Best

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

145 Philosophy of Science

What Should We Believe?

Van Fraassen: Arguments concerning scientific realism

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Philosophy of Science PHIL 241, MW 12:00-1:15

Historical Inductions, Unconceived Alternatives, and Unconceived Objections

Temperate Rationalism: An Option for the Methodology and Understanding of Scientific Enterprise

Science, Metaphysics, and Scientific Realism

Popper s Falsificationism. Philosophy of Economics University of Virginia Matthias Brinkmann

Quests of a Realist. Stathis Psillos, Scientific Realism: How Science Tracks Truth. London: Routledge, Pp. xxv PB.

DO WE NEED A THEORY OF METAPHYSICAL COMPOSITION?

K.V. LAURIKAINEN EXTENDING THE LIMITS OF SCIENCE

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

REALISM/ANTI-REALISM

Analogy and Pursuitworthiness

Critical Scientific Realism

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Sydenham College of Commerce & Economics. * Dr. Sunil S. Shete. * Associate Professor

THE HYPOTHETICAL-DEDUCTIVE METHOD OR THE INFERENCE TO THE BEST EXPLANATION: THE CASE OF THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION BY NATURAL SELECTION

CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

Kazuhisa Todayama (Graduate School of Information Science, Nagoya University, Japan)

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

The Nature of Science: Methods for Seeking Natural Patterns in the Universe Using Rationalism and Empiricism Mike Viney

Truth and Realism. EDITED BY PATRICK GREENOUGH AND MICHAEL P. LYNCH. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. ix Price h/b, p/b.

Tuukka Kaidesoja Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

The Illusion of Scientific Realism: An Argument for Scientific Soft Antirealism

Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke,

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

THE PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE. jennifer ROSATO

Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University,

Holtzman Spring Philosophy and the Integration of Knowledge

CHRISTIANITY AND THE NATURE OF SCIENCE J.P. MORELAND

Are Scientific Theories True?

Ch V: The Vienna Circle (Moritz Schlick, Rudolf Carnap, and Otto Neurath)[title crossed out?]

The Best Explanation: A Defense of Scientific Realism

The linguistic-cultural nature of scientific truth 1

Statement of Research

Adam Smith and the Limits of Empiricism

Intro to Science Studies I

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27)

HAS SCIENCE ESTABLISHED THAT THE UNIVERSE IS COMPREHENSIBLE?

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE

Are Miracles Identifiable?

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Unit. Science and Hypothesis. Downloaded from Downloaded from Why Hypothesis? What is a Hypothesis?

PHIL 480: Seminar in the History of Philosophy Building Moral Character: Neo-Confucianism and Moral Psychology

INTRODUCTION: EPISTEMIC COHERENTISM

Buck-Passers Negative Thesis

Falsification of Popper and Lakatos (Falsifikace podle Poppera a Lakatose)

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

Human Nature & Human Diversity: Sex, Love & Parenting; Morality, Religion & Race. Course Description

Science and Pseudoscience (transcript)

BOOK REVIEWS. The arguments of the Parmenides, though they do not refute the Theory of Forms, do expose certain problems, ambiguities and

NOTES ON WILLIAMSON: CHAPTER 11 ASSERTION Constitutive Rules

SCIENTIFIC REALISM AND EPISTEMOLOGY

All philosophical debates not due to ignorance of base truths or our imperfect rationality are indeterminate.

Philosophy 427 Intuitions and Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2011

Epistemic Utility and Theory-Choice in Science: Comments on Hempel

Introduction to Political Science

Explanation and Experiment in Social Psychological Science

David Copp, ed., The Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory, Oxford: Oxford University

Relativism. We re both right.

MARK KAPLAN AND LAWRENCE SKLAR. Received 2 February, 1976) Surely an aim of science is the discovery of the truth. Truth may not be the

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

Class 4 - The Myth of the Given

Approximate Truth vs. Empirical Adequacy

Chapter One. Constructive Empiricism and the Case. Against Scientific Realism

Falsification or Confirmation: From Logic to Psychology

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology

The Unbearable Lightness of Theory of Knowledge:

NORMATIVITY WITHOUT NORMATIVISM 1

Scientific realism is dead, or so many philosophers believe. Its death was announced when philosophers became

Of Skepticism with Regard to the Senses. David Hume

Social mechanisms and explaining how: A reply to Kimberly Chuang Johannes Persson, Lund University

Module 1: Science as Culture Demarcation, Autonomy and Cognitive Authority of Science

Introduction and Background

Transcription:

manuscript, September 11, 2017 Samuel K. Schindler Theoretical Virtues in Science Uncovering Reality Through Theory

Table of contents Table of Figures... iii Introduction... 1 1 Theoretical virtues, truth, and the argument from simplicity... 4 1.1 Theoretical virtues... 4 1.2 The explanatory defense of realism and its criticisms... 16 1.3 Theoretical virtues: epistemic or pragmatic?... 25 1.4 The first virtuous argument for realism: the argument from simplicity... 29 2 Pessimism, base rates, and the no-virtue-coincidence argument... 33 2.1 The Pessimistic Meta Induction and the divide et impera move... 33 2.2 False posits and novel success: what if?... 38 2.3 PMI vs. PUA... 40 2.4 Broader concerns: the base rate fallacy... 41 2.5 The central virtuous argument for realism: virtue convergence... 44 2.6 Conclusion... 56 3 Novel success and predictivism... 58 3.1 Worrall s account of use-novelty: weak and strong... 59 3.2 Parameter freedom and local-symptomatic predictivism... 62 3.3 Non-starters... 64 3.4 Deflationary approaches and comparative novel success... 67 3.5 Mendeleev s periodic table and the prediction of chemical elements... 71 3.6 Conclusion: novel success and nagging Popperian intuitions... 76 4 Theoretical fertility without novel success... 78 4.1 McMullinian fertility and Nolan s challenge... 78 4.2 The Bohr-Sommerfeld model of the atom... 84 4.3 An objectionable change... 94 4.4 Conclusion... 96 5 Ad hoc hypotheses and the argument from coherence... 98 5.1 Ad hocness: the state of the art... 99 5.2 A coherentist conception of ad hocness... 109 5.3 In-depth illustrations of the coherentist conception... 116 5.4 The third virtuous argument for realism: the argument from coherence... 125 6 Virtues as confidence boosters and the argument from choice... 128 i P age

6.1 The Negative View, the dictatorship condition, and its violation... 128 6.2 Historical case studies... 131 6.3 The fourth virtuous argument for realism: the argument from choice... 148 6.4 Objections... 149 7 Philosophy of science by historical means... 153 7.1 Laudan s naïve and sophisticated naturalism... 153 7.2 Rational reconstruction... 157 7.3 Concept clarification... 166 8 Conclusion... 171 Epilogue: the demarcation problem... 175 Bibliography... 184 ii P age

Introduction Philosophy of science is coming to resemble science: ever more specialized. Philosophers of physics deliberate the correct interpretation of quantum mechanics, whether spacetime is sustantival or relational, and whether the time-asymmetry of our world can be reconciled with the time-symmetry of the laws of physics. Philosophers of biology grapple with determining the meaning of concepts such as gene, evolution, and fitness. Philosophers of chemistry ponder whether chemistry is really reducible to physics, and philosophers of climate modeling debate whether or not computer simulations can be trusted as much as experiments. While all these questions and debates are highly interesting and important, this particularist trend, as one might call it, has unfortunately gone to the expense of larger picture questions about science: what is science? Is there a scientific method? How can we distinguish between science and pseudo-science? What constitutes a good scientific theory? Can science discover truths about the world? In sum, it bears some irony that today s philosopher of science has much to say about physics, biology, or chemistry, but little about science. This book returns to one of those more ambitious philosophical questions about science, namely the question of what features characterize good scientific theories, that is, what are theoretical virtues in science. While this question clearly has a normative aspect, which I explore in this book, a successful answer will also have to take into account which properties of a theory scientists actually value when they decide to adopt a theory. I seek to establish this link to scientific practice primarily through various historical case studies in the venerable tradition of Duhem, Kuhn, Feyerabend, Lakatos, and others. Although any empirical or descriptive effort such as this naturally comes with certain inductive risk, it is an all too common fallacy to believe that, due to the complexity and diversity we find in the sciences, any attempt to say something more general about science must be futile. Clearly, physics, chemistry, and biology are sciences. True statements about theoretical virtues in physics, for example, will therefore automatically be true statements about theoretical virtues in science. Such statements of course need not be true about all sciences, or even more implausibly, exhaust all there is to be said about theoretical virtues in science, but that need not be one s ambition. It s not mine in any case. Apart from attempting to answer the question, what is a good scientific theory? this book also seeks to address the question, can our best scientific theories help us discover what is real? In fact, these two questions are intertwined: a good answer to the latter presupposes a good answer to the former, since we can judge whether a theory is likely to be true, if at all, only via the (internal and relational) properties of the theory. On the basis of my answer to the first question, I will argue that the mainstream defense of realism, which is built on the idea that a theory s successful prediction of novel phenomena, or novel success for short, is not justified. Instead, I think that realism can and should be defended 1 P age

along lines that are more in tune with the way in which theoretical properties are actually valued by scientists. I will advance one central and three auxiliary arguments for realism. My central argument for realism is that a very virtuous theory, i.e., a theory possessing all of the standard virtues, is likely to be true. My three auxiliary arguments are as follows: (i) contrary to the standard view, there is an epistemic, i.e. knowledge-related, rationale for a controversial theoretical virtue, which is usually thought to be merely pragmatic; (ii) non-ad hocness is a sign for truth, and (iii) actual theory-choice decisions by scientists force us to accept that some theoretical virtues are indeed at least weakly epistemic. I will refer to the central and the three auxiliary arguments as my four virtuous arguments for realism and to the resulting position as VIRTUOUS REALISM. Although all of these arguments are fairly independent, the three auxiliary arguments, as we shall see, support my central argument for realism. I proceed in the following manner. In Chapter 1 of this book, I first introduce what many consider to be the standard theoretical virtues and the so-called explanatory defense of scientific realism. The success of the latter, we will see, depends on whether theoretical virtues are truth-conducive. I will discuss this question with a particular focus on simplicity, perhaps the most controversial theoretical virtue. Many philosophers hold that simplicity cannot be truth-conducive because we would have to presuppose that the world is simple. I reject this idea. Simplicity can be a reasonable epistemic concern without this presupposition. On the basis of what I call the evidential-explanatory rationale for simplicity I will advance my first virtuous argument for realism. I call it the ARGUMENT FROM SIMPLICITY. In Chapter 2, I discuss an antirealist challenge that has been at the forefront of the realism debate in recent years, namely the so-called pessimistic meta-induction, and its cousin, the problem of unconceived alternatives, both of which appeal to the historical record of empirically successful but false theories. My main focus in this chapter, though, is on a challenge that has shed doubt on the very possibility of resolving the realism debate by any historical examples. The charge is that the base rate of true theories, which is needed to compute the probability of a theory being true given its success, has been neglected and that we have no way of accessing it anyway. I take on this challenge and argue on the basis of the Kuhnian framework of theory-choice and an important epistemological insight that a very virtuous theory is likely to be true when it is embraced by numerous scientists even when the base rate is diminishingly small. I call this the NO-VIRTUE-COINCIDENCE-ARGUMENT. It is my second, and central, virtuous argument for realism. In order to fend off the pessimistic meta-induction, realists have sought refuge in what has come to be known as the divide-et-impera move. That is, realists have restricted their commitments to those parts of theories which are responsible for empirical success, and more specifically, for novel empirical success, i.e., the successful prediction of novel phenomena. But is such a restriction warranted? Here I am doubtful. Such a restriction is only justifiable if a case can be made for the view, also known as predictivism, that novel success is better empirical evidence than non-novel success. However, the rationales that 2 Page

have been proposed to justify this view do not hold water, or so I shall argue in detail in Chapter 3. Novel success can be viewed as a form of a theory s fertility. There is another form of theoretical fertility, which has received much less attention from philosophers. I shall explore this other kind of fertility and arguments for realism based on it in Chapter 4. The allegedly special epistemic status of both kinds of theoretical fertility has been motivated via an avoidance of ad hoc hypotheses. But what does ad hocness mean in the first place? This question will be the main focus of Chapter 5. The answer to this question seems intuitively clear: ad hoc hypotheses are those that are devised to save a theory from refutation. And yet, such an answer tells us only about what motivates the introduction of such hypotheses; it does not tell us what is epistemically amiss with them. But that we need to know in order to understand why ad hocness is viewed as affecting a theory s empirical support in a negative way. My proposal is that ad hoc hypotheses are hypotheses that do not cohere either with the theories they amend or with the available background theories. Coherence, in turn, I believe can be understand as the provision of theoretical reasons for belief. This will form the basis for my third virtuous argument for realism. I call it the ARGUMENT FROM COHERENCE. My fourth virtuous argument for realism, to be presented in Chapter 6, is based on the observation that, as a matter of historical fact, theoretical virtues have functioned as confidence boosters : scientists adopted (and did not just pursue) virtuous theories despite the fact that they were contradicted by some of the available evidence. My argument for realism takes the form of a dilemma for the antirealist: either the scientists in question made utterly irrational and methodologically wrong choices, or theoretical virtues are epistemic. I argue that we should try to avoid the first horn of the dilemma. This is my ARGUMENT FROM CHOICE. In Chapter 7, I reflect on my chosen method of a historically informed philosophy of science. I argue that there are two fruitful roles for history and philosophy of science: rational reconstruction of scientific practice and clarification of concepts used by scientists. Both, I argue, respect the notorious norm-fact divide. Chapter 8 contains my conclusion. I end the book with an epilogue on the demarcation problem, viz. the problem of distinguishing science from non-science. 3 P age