Lecture #14: St. Thomas Aquinas on Goodness & Badness in Human Actions

Similar documents
Bernard Hoose - Proportionalism

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule

Saint Thomas Aquinas Summa Theologiae Selections III Good and Evil Actions. ST I-II, Question 18, Article 1

TOPIC 27: MORALITY OF HUMAN ACTS

Short Answers: Answer the following questions in one paragraph (each is worth 4 points).

Introduction. In light of these facts, we will ask, is killing animals for human benefit morally permissible?

Moral Philosophy : Utilitarianism

Utilitarianism. But what is meant by intrinsically good and instrumentally good?

Philosophical Ethics. Consequentialism Deontology (Virtue Ethics)

CONTEMPORARY MORAL PROBLEMS LECTURE 14 CAPITAL PUNISHMENT PART 2

Deontology, Rationality, and Agent-Centered Restrictions

Kant, Deontology, & Respect for Persons

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

Scanlon on Double Effect

Utilitarianism pp

Thomistic Natural Law. C. Given by the one who has care for the community (legitimate authority).

Ethical Theory. Ethical Theory. Consequentialism in practice. How do we get the numbers? Must Choose Best Possible Act

Lecture #12: Morality & War: Non-Combatant Immunity (Supreme Emergency)

Take Home Exam #2. PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert

CHAPTER 2 Test Bank MULTIPLE CHOICE

Faith-N-Focus : E-quip Your Faith

The Utilitarian Approach. Chapter 7, Elements of Moral Philosophy James Rachels Professor Douglas Olena

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

UNALTERABLE LIFESTYLES

Hello again. Today we re gonna continue our discussions of Kant s ethics.

Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 110W Spring 2011 Russell Marcus

Law and Authority. An unjust law is not a law

EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES My Answers

ADVANCED SUBSIDIARY (AS) General Certificate of Education Religious Studies Assessment Unit AS 6. assessing

Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 110W Fall 2013 Russell Marcus

AS Religious Studies. RSS02 Religion and Ethics 2 Mark scheme June Version: 1.0 Final

LAW04. Law and Morals. The Concepts of Law

From Veritatis Splendor (The Splendor of the Truth), Pope John Paul II, IV. THE MORAL ACT Teleology and teleologism...

Stem Cell Research on Embryonic Persons is Just

THE ROAD TO HELL by Alastair Norcross 1. Introduction: The Doctrine of the Double Effect.

Same-Sex Marriage, Just War, and the Social Principles

Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1

(i) Morality is a system; and (ii) It is a system comprised of moral rules and principles.

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

Ethical Theory for Catholic Professionals

Topic III: Sexual Morality

24.03: Good Food 3 April Animal Liberation and the Moral Community

Suicide. 1. Rationality vs. Morality: Kagan begins by distinguishing between two questions:


Deontology: Duty-Based Ethics IMMANUEL KANT

Traditional Morality and Utilitarianism. Chapter 16, Kai Nielsen Introduction to Ethics Professor Douglas Olena

The Philosophy of Ethics as It Relates to Capital Punishment. Nicole Warkoski, Lynchburg College

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

How should I live? I should do whatever brings about the most pleasure (or, at least, the most good)

24.02 Moral Problems and the Good Life

Consider... Ethical Egoism. Rachels. Consider... Theories about Human Motivations

The Fifth and Sixth Commandments

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 1. Background Material for the Exercise on Validity

Let us begin by first locating our fields in relation to other fields that study ethics. Consider the following taxonomy: Kinds of ethical inquiries

THE ETHICS OF STRATEGIC COMMUNICATION: WINTER 2009

CS305 Topic Introduction to Ethics

Option C. Living as a Disciple of Jesus Christ

Direct Sterilization: An Intrinsically Evil Act - A Rejoinder to Fr. Keenan

Philosophical Ethics. The nature of ethical analysis. Discussion based on Johnson, Computer Ethics, Chapter 2.

What Part of the Soul Does Justice Perfect? Shane Drefcinski Department of Humanities/Philosophy University of Wisconsin Platteville

Unit objectives. Unit 3.6 Capital Punishment. To know. What Capital Punishment is and its history. Reasons given for and against Capital Punishment

Application Form Non Teaching Position

First of all, the question implies the word loving to mean only giving pleasant things to those who are loved.

Phil 108, August 10, 2010 Punishment

Social Laws Deuteronomy 21:1-26:19 Study Guide. Day 1

THEMES: PROMPT: RESPONSE:

Nichomachean Ethics. Philosophy 21 Fall, 2004 G. J. Mattey

A Coherent and Comprehensible Interpretation of Saul Smilansky s Dualism

Aristotle s Virtue Ethics

The Non-Identity Problem from Reasons and Persons by Derek Parfit (1984)

Pojman: What is Moral Philosophy?

EUTHANASIA EUTHANASIA NEWS IN CANADA

Virtue Ethics. What kind of person do you want to grow up to be? Virtue Ethics (VE): The Basic Idea

Morality in the Modern World (Higher) Religious, Moral and Philosophical Studies (Higher)

Philosophy 1100: Ethics

Final Paper. May 13, 2015

PHIL 202: IV:

MEDICAL ETHICS A Roman Catholic Perspective Monsignor Peter R. Beaulieu, M.A., S.T.L. PRUDENTIAL PERSONALISM. Ethics In General

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

If Everyone Does It, Then You Can Too Charlie Melman

Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press, Pp $90.00 (cloth); $28.99

Suppose a school were to set out deliberately to improve the mental

Selections of the Nicomachean Ethics for GGL Unit: Learning to Live Well Taken from classic.mit.edu archive. Translated by W.D. Ross I.

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

HOLY SCRIPTURE...John 8:1-11, KJV esus went unto the mount of Olives. 2 And early in the morning he came again

Euthanasia; Acts & Omissions

Quiz 1. Criticisms of consequentialism and Kant. Consequentialism and Nonconsequentialism. Consequentialism in practice. Must Choose Best Possible Act

Suppose... Kant. The Good Will. Kant Three Propositions

Honors Ethics Oral Presentations: Instructions

WHEN is a moral theory self-defeating? I suggest the following.

National Quali cations

W.D. Ross ( )

RCIA Christian Morality Part II Session 20

Marriage. Embryonic Stem-Cell Research

THE FAIR OAKS PRESBYTERIAN CHURCH (FOPC) APPLICATION FOR EMPLOYMENT

Chapter 2 Ethical Concepts and Ethical Theories: Establishing and Justifying a Moral System

Yr11 Philosophy and Ethics Religious Studies B (OCR) GCSE. Medical Ethics B603

Louisiana Law Review. Cheney C. Joseph Jr. Louisiana State University Law Center. Volume 35 Number 5 Special Issue Repository Citation

Class 23 - April 20 Plato, What is Right Conduct?

Transcription:

Lecture #14: St. Thomas Aquinas on Goodness & Badness in Human Actions St. Thomas Moral Principles: Summary 1. The Dionysian Principle An act (or thing) is good only if it is good in all respects; it is bad if it is bad in any respect. 2. The Three Determinants of Morality The goodness or badness of a human action is determined by three things: the object the end the circumstances. 3. The Reason Principle Good human actions are those which are in accordance with reason & Bad actions are those contrary to reason 3 4 The Dionysian Principle A Translation Note We must speak of goodness and badness in actions as of goodness and badness in things IaIIæ, 18.1 On badness, see translation note (next slide) What makes things good or bad? The Dionysian Principle: Bonum ex integra causa; malum ex quocumque defectu Badness results from any single defect, but goodness from the complete cause Equivalently, goodness is fulness of being if a thing be lacking in its due fulness of being, it is not said to be good simply = having all the features appropriate to a thing of that kind Considerandum est de bonitate et malitia humanorum actuum Question: malum & malitia bad & badness or evil & malice? The distinction can something be bad, but not evil? the tires on one s car can be bad; they can t be evil evil seems to be limited to moral badness telling a white lie may be bad, but would we describe it as evil? evil suggests that something is not only bad, but profoundly so can it be evil & not bad? and what can be malum? the weather: tempestas mala malum = bad, not necessarily evil So, not a blind man is possessed of evil, inasmuch as he lacks sight but of something bad Goodness in Aristotelian Philosophy 5 The Three Determinants of Morality: Two Key Passages 6 All things are things of a certain kind Goodness is judged by reference to features characteristic of a given kind of thing Consider the criteria by which we would judge something we make to be a good watch, the watch would have to keep time well to be a good dog, the dog would have to be able to see, &c. Full goodness requires all those features (goodness as fulness in being ) Every action has goodness, in so far as it has being; whereas it is lacking in goodness, in so far as it is lacking in something that is due to its fulness of being; and thus it is said to be bad A good bloodhound must be good in all respects not just capable of smelling but of staying on task A good farmer must be good in all respects not only capable of reliably producing a crop but a good steward of his land Accordingly a fourfold goodness may be considered in a human action. First, that which, as an action, it derives from its genus; because as much as it has of action and being so much has it of goodness, as stated above (a. 1). Secondly, it has goodness according to its species; which is derived from its suitable object. Thirdly, it has goodness from its circumstances, in respect, as it were, of its accidents. Fourthly, it has goodness from its end, to which it is compared as to the cause of its goodness. 1a2æ, 18.4 c Nothing hinders an action that is good in one of the way mentioned above, from lacking goodness in another way. And thus it may happen that an action which is good in its species or in its circumstances is ordained to a bad end, or vice versa. However, an action is not good simply, unless it is good in all those ways: since badness results from any single defect, but goodness from the complete cause, as Dionysius says. 1a2æ, 18.4 ad 3

8 St. Thomas Moral Principles: 2. The Three Determinants of Morality What are the respects that constitute the integra causa of a human action? The (foundational) Fourfold Goodness Principle: There are four aspects of goodness in an action: genus species (object) end circumstances There are three things that determine the goodness or badness of a human action: the object the end the circumstances. The Genus The genus of every human action is just human action. That is generally the kind of thing we are talking about. Every human act is good with respect to its genus. No action is bad as a human action. All bad actions are bad because of their object, their end or their circumstances. These three remain as the determinants of whether an action is morally good or bad. The Object The object of a human action This can also be characterized as the species (or kind) of action or what the agent did In sentences that say I am doing, performing, or committing X : X is the direct object of the verb. X names the kind (species) of action, or the object of the action. E.g., killing an innocent person, visiting the sick, picking up a leaf The object of a human action corresponds to the immediate intention of the agent more than a basic bodily action (e.g., moving one s trigger finger) less than the reason for the action (e.g., getting revenge) so, in a killing the object is killing another human being the act as intended & affected by those other features that are so logically close as to be practically indistinguishable from it ( specifying circumstances ) Beheading is a kind of killing (even if the decapitator says, I didn t intend to kill him. All I intended to do was to cut off his head. ). Bombing military targets is not a kind of killing innocent neighbors of the target. the reason the act is performed The the aim, not the outcome (or actual consequences) why the agent did what he did kinds of end ultimate end always the same formally to attain happiness but various materially to attain something that is seen as a constituent of happiness proximate end e.g., friendship, getting revenge Various e.g., money, health Object & Distinguished Object & Distinguished: A Complication Object Act (= what the agent did) Motive (= why the agent did it) Means (= how the end was achieved) (= why the act was done) The of the Act (= finis operis) The of the Agent (= finis operantis) St. Thomas Analysis in terms of object & end seems oversimplified: Analysis reveals more complexity. Basic Action Flexing One s Trigger Finger Means to Performing the Act The Act Itself (the Object) Firing a Rifle Killing Someone The Intermediate ing their Suffering The Ultimate Greatest Happiness for the Greatest Number Flexing One s Trigger Finger Firing a Rifle Killing Someone Making the Victim s Relatives Unhappy Attaining the Sweet Feeling of Revenge Solution: Object & together name the whole spectrum. Often, distinguishing two points is sufficient for moral analysis. Sometimes it is not.

Circumstances Definition Features that are not part of the act itself (i.e., the act as intended or chosen by the agent), but surround it. What is part of the act itself? Clearly everything intended by the agent (object & end). These are the things on the basis of which the thing was chosen. Those circumstances that change the moral nature of the action, whether the agent intended them or not (because the agent should have considered them), i.e., specifying circumstances [see next slide]. St. Thomas Moral Principles: Kinds of Circumstances There are two kinds of circumstances: Specifying Circumstances which change the moral nature of the action from one kind to another (& possibly from good to bad) & thereby become part of the object (associated with the will by its neglect of them) rather than remaining part of the circumstances Stealing from a church is sacrilege, even if the location of the action had nothing to do with why the thief stole there. Adulterers may only intend to satisfy their lust, but if one of them is married, the act is ipso facto adultery. Aggravating or Mitigating Circumstances These make the action more or less bad than it otherwise would be, but do not change its nature (or change it from good to bad). Stealing from the poor may be worse than stealing from the rich, but both are just cases of stealing. 16 The List of Circumstances Who execution by public hangman or private vigilante correction of children by a parent, a sibling, or a stranger What (the effect) with certain side effects as consequences When killing a deer in hunting season or out of season Where target practice on Main Street or in the country How correcting children harshly or gently [Why but this is equivalent to the ] The Reason Principle What do we look for in object, end, & circumstance? Human actions, as opposed to mere actions of man are the product of deliberative will, i.e., of reason So we ask whether the object, end, & circumstance are in accordance with reason (& therefore good) or contrary to reason (& therefore bad) Evaluating the Object: The Heart of Thomistic Absolutism Some acts are wrong by their intrinsic nature The object specifies the act (i.e., makes it the kind of act it is) 17 Evaluating the Object The object specifies the act (i.e., makes it the kind of act it is) Some acts are wrong because of the kind of act they are There are three relations which an object can have to reason. It can be in accord with reason (& therefore good) E.g., just, temperate, courageous actions contrary to reason (& therefore bad) E.g., unjust, intemperate, cowardly, rash actions injustice treating someone in a way that is not due to him intemperance» gluttony eating in a way that cuts the act off from nutrition» lust engaging in sex in a way that cuts it off from procreation & love neither ( indifferent ) Some actions are too generally described to be relatable to reason. (See next slide) 18

Evaluating the Object (cont d.): Indifference Some kinds of actions are too generally described to be relatable to reason. Easy examples are trivial actions E.g., picking up a leaf (as such) is neither in accord with reason nor contrary to reason. But non-trivial actions can also be indifferent (i.e., by their nature neither good nor bad) E.g., killing someone Killing whom? Do they deserve it? (= Are they nocent or innocent?) Contrast executing a dangerous murderer (just; good object) killing innocent Japanese citizens at Hiroshima (unjust; bad object) shooting down a kamikaze (just; good object) So, the characterization killing someone did not give us enough information to determine wether the object of the action was in accord with reason or not. However, no individual action is indifferent. An individual action may be indifferent as a kind of action. But the circumstances could make an indifferent action bad E.g. Singing is indifferent. Singing during philosophy class is bad (time & place unreasonable). The end will always be in accordance with or contrary to reason. indifferent object + good end good act (unless circumstances are bad) indifferent object + bad end bad act (regardless of circumstances) Evaluating the s in accord with reason (good) s that are a part of real happiness (ultimate ends) e.g., friendship, contemplation s that are a means to it (proximate ends) e.g., money, health s contrary to reason (bad) Things desired for their own sake though not part of real happiness e.g., getting even with everyone who harms one Instrumental goods desired for their own sake e.g., wanting money for its own sake Things desired as a means, though not compatible with happiness e.g., sneakiness? N.B. All ends are either in accordance with reason or contrary to it. None are ever indifferent. Evaluating Circumstances Evaluating Circumstances (cont d.) Circumstances in accord with reason Who (done by the right person) E.g., criminal punishment by the proper authorities What (having acceptable consequences) When E.g., bad side effects not outweighing the intended good effects E.g., packing up one s papers after the professor has finished the lecture How (done in the right way) E.g. breaking bad news gently using only the force necessary to restrain a criminal during an arrest Circumstances contrary to reason Who (done by the wrong person) E.g., criminal punishment by vigilantes What (having unacceptable consequences) E.g., bad side effects outweighing the intended good effects When E.g., packing up one s papers while the professor is trying to summarize the lecture How (done in the wrong way) E.g. breaking bad news crudely or inconsiderately police brutality Summary Thomistic ethics as intrinsicalist (like presumptivism; unlike utilitarianism) It is not enough to look at the consequences of the action. One must determine what kind of an action one is doing. The Three Determinants of Morality require this Thomistic ethics as absolutist (unlike presumptivism & utilitarianism) Evaluation of the object as bad is sufficient to make the action bad To be good, it must be good in all respects Evaluation of the object as good is necessary to make the action good but it is not sufficient An action good with respect to its object could still be bad with respect to end or circumstances Acts that are bad should never be done. But, to avoid improperly stringent application of this principle, see next lecture. Moral Absolutes

25 The Grounds of Absolute Prohibitions I 26 Keys to understanding St. Thomas on absolute moral prohibitions The doctrine of absolute moral prohibitions is that some kinds of act are bad because of the kind of act and should never be done Fiat justitia, ruat coelum, Let justice be done though the heavens may fall. i.e., Injustice is wrong regardless of the good consequences that might come from doing an injustice & even if it is the lesser of two evils (which generally comes to the same thing) The argument is always that certain acts are bad by their very nature & therefore absolutely prohibited It is never that certain acts are good by their very nature & absolutely required For each kind of act that is always prohibited, the absolutist must show why that kind of act is instrinsically bad. One must understand the exact scope of the prohibition Sometimes, principles of justice E.g., killing might be contrary to reason, because it is not due to the person this would include» someone who wants to be killed (assisted suicide & voluntary euthanasia)» someone who is willing to risk being killed (duelling)» someone who is terminally ill in general, anyone who is innocent in accordance with reason, if the person is» guilty» nocent Here killing might be what is necessary to prevent or punish harm» therefore, due & thus good with respect to its object Even in these cases the end & circumstances would also have to be good (see below) 27 28 The Grounds of Absolute Prohibitions II Sometimes, principles about the proper use of one s faculties the sexual powers are for reproduction (& the good of marital friendship that is associated with reproduction) so violated in one way by homosexual & contraceptive acts violated in another way by fornication & adultery the power of speech is for expressing one s thoughts violated by lying The Limits of Absolute Prohibitions This means intentional killing of the innocent This would not include these, which may or may not be wrong (depending on end & circumstances) doing something that one foresees may (or will) cause a death (cf. aerial bombardment) letting someone die (cf. failure to give medical treatment) This means making assertions that are contrary to what one thinks This would not include these, which may or may not be wrong (depending on end & circumstances) refusing to say anything at all saying something ambiguous This means taking deliberate steps to prevent conception This would not include these, which may or may not be wrong (depending on end & circumstances) refraining from marital relations during fertile periods, but not refraining at other times ( natural family planning ) On the phrase The end justifies the means 30 This is not typically a phrase anyone uses to characterize his own position It is a charge used to accuse others of bad moral reasoning especially a charge made by Thomists against consequentialists The end doesn t justify the means.

Cases in which the phrase might be used 31 The end does not justify the means & Moral Theories 32 Consider two recent statements as though they were complete justifications for a controversial policy Pres. Obama in defense of allowing federal funding of embryonic stem-cell research, said: scientists believe these tiny cells may have the potential to help us understand, and possibly cure, some of our most devastating diseases and conditions. To regenerate a severed spinal cord and lift someone from a wheelchair. Michael Hayden (former DCI) & Michael Mukasey (former AG) in defense of using aggressive interrogation techniques wrote: even with the growing success of other intelligence tools, fully half of the government s knowledge about the structure and activities of al Qaeda came from those interrogations [in which harsh interrogation techniques were used]. Critics of each statement might say, The end does not justify the means, meaning the prospect of finding new cures does not itself justify any means of finding them the prospect of getting intelligence about the enemy does not justify any means of extracting it The means used (destruction of embryonic human beings, the techniques in question) need to be assessed independently Is the destruction of human embryos murder? Do these interrogation techniques constitute cruel, inhuman or degrading treatment? Note that the passages quoted are not a complete justification Pres. Obama does not think that killing human embryos is itself wrong. Messrs. Hayden & Mukasey do not think the techniques in question are cruel, inhuman or degrading treatment. Utilitarians & the slogan A few utilitarians say that the end justifies the means They need not do so They might better characterize their position as saying that the consequences justify the action» the end = what one is aiming at» the consequences = what actually results (both one s end & any side effects) They might say that the slogan the end does not justify warns against neglecting sideeffects but, though they look at more than the end, they deny that the act itself requires any evaluation independent of the consequences Thomists & the slogan Thomism most explicitly rejects the idea that the end justifies According to Thomists, the end and the object (i.e., the means to the end) are explicity objects of independent evaluation Presumptivists will look to Thomists like utilitarians (i.e., justifying the means by the ends) whenever they let beneficence override non-maleficence & look like Thomists (i.e., denying that the ends justify the means) whenever they let other duties override beneficence