MILL ON JUSTICE: CHAPTER 5 of UTILITARIANISM Lecture Notes Dick Arneson Philosophy 13 Fall, 2005

Similar documents
MILL. The principle of utility determines the rightness of acts (or rules of action?) by their effect on the total happiness.

CONTEMPORARY MORAL PROBLEMS LECTURE 14 CAPITAL PUNISHMENT PART 2

24.01: Classics of Western Philosophy

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

HUME AND HIS CRITICS: Reid and Kames

DOES CONSEQUENTIALISM DEMAND TOO MUCH?

Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social

Utilitarianism. John Stuart Mill

The Pleasure Imperative

Making Decisions on Behalf of Others: Who or What Do I Select as a Guide? A Dilemma: - My boss. - The shareholders. - Other stakeholders

Rawls, rationality, and responsibility: Why we should not treat our endowments as morally arbitrary

The Conflict Between Authority and Autonomy from Robert Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (1970)

Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan

24.02 Moral Problems and the Good Life

A lonelier contractualism A. J. Julius, UCLA, January

Phil 108, August 10, 2010 Punishment

Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1

Q2) The test of an ethical argument lies in the fact that others need to be able to follow it and come to the same result.

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Phil 114, April 24, 2007 until the end of semester Mill: Individual Liberty Against the Tyranny of the Majority

24.03: Good Food 2/15/17

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

BOOK REVIEW: CONTEMPORARY MORAL PROBLEMS

On the Relevance of Ignorance to the Demands of Morality 1

Philosophical Ethics. The nature of ethical analysis. Discussion based on Johnson, Computer Ethics, Chapter 2.

Let us begin by first locating our fields in relation to other fields that study ethics. Consider the following taxonomy: Kinds of ethical inquiries

Compromise and Toleration: Some Reflections I. Introduction

A Contractualist Reply

Comment on Martha Nussbaum s Purified Patriotism

UTILITARIANISM AND CONSEQUENTIALISM: THE BASICS

Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule

Creative Genius and the Rights of the Individual: From Romanticism to Utilitarianism

Critical Reasoning and Moral theory day 3

Introduction. Natural Law Jurisprudence and Natural Law Political Philosophy

How should I live? I should do whatever brings about the most pleasure (or, at least, the most good)

(i) Morality is a system; and (ii) It is a system comprised of moral rules and principles.

THE SEPARATION OF LAW AND MORALS

Hugh LaFollette: The Practice of Ethics

IS ACT-UTILITARIANISM SELF-DEFEATING?

Take Home Exam #2. PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert

Utilitarianism. But what is meant by intrinsically good and instrumentally good?

factors in Bentham's hedonic calculus.

Chapter 2 Determining Moral Behavior

CHAPTER 2 Test Bank MULTIPLE CHOICE

Moral Theory. What makes things right or wrong?

The Prospective View of Obligation

PROFESSIONAL ETHICS IN SCIENCE AND ENGINEERING

Weighing The Consequences. Lying, Chapter 4 Sissela Bok Contemporary Moral Problems Professor Douglas Olena

Chapter 2 Ethical Concepts and Ethical Theories: Establishing and Justifying a Moral System

Utilitarianism pp

Act Consequentialism s Compelling Idea and Deontology s Paradoxical Idea

Deontological Ethics

Preliminary Remarks on Locke's The Second Treatise of Government (T2)

CONSEQUENTIALISM AND THE SELF OTHER ASYMMETRY

Sidgwick on Practical Reason

Rethinking Development: the Centrality of Human Rights

Philosophical Ethics. Consequentialism Deontology (Virtue Ethics)

38 Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals. [Ak 4:422] [Ak4:421]

Blame and Forfeiture. The central issue that a theory of punishment must address is why we are we permitted to

BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth).

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

Legal Positivism: the Separation and Identification theses are true.

Review of Nathan M. Nobis s Truth in Ethics and Epistemology

Mill and Bentham both endorse the harm principle. Utilitarians, they both rest

On the Alleged Incoherence of Consequentialism. by Robert Mckim and Peter Simpson

Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes

Hello again. Today we re gonna continue our discussions of Kant s ethics.

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

Legal positivism represents a view about the nature of law. It states that

Interest-Relativity and Testimony Jeremy Fantl, University of Calgary

90 South Cascade Avenue, Suite 1500, Colorado Springs, Colorado Telephone: Fax:

In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of

Notes on Moore and Parker, Chapter 12: Moral, Legal and Aesthetic Reasoning

A CONSEQUENTIALIST RESPONSE TO THE DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Nicholas R. Baker, Lee University THE DEMANDS OF ACT CONSEQUENTIALISM

Are Humans Always Selfish? OR Is Altruism Possible?

What is the "Social" in "Social Coherence?" Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious Freedom in an Egalitarian Age

Reply to Gauthier and Gibbard

John Stuart Mill ( ) is widely regarded as the leading English-speaking philosopher of

Testing Fairmindedness

The hallmark of a good moral theory is that it agrees with and improves

Introduction: the original position and The Original Position an overview

The Discounting Defense of Animal Research

A NOTE ON UTILITARIANISM & CONSEQUENTIALISM FOR PHILOSOPHY 13 Richard Arneson Fall, 2004

The view that all of our actions are done in self-interest is called psychological egoism.

CLIMBING THE MOUNTAIN SUMMARY CHAPTER 1 REASONS. 1 Practical Reasons

How to Live a More Authentic Life in Both Markets and Morals

Do we have reasons to obey the law?

UTILITARIANISM AND INFINITE UTILITY. Peter Vallentyne. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 71 (1993): I. Introduction

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

BOOK REVIEWS. Justice in Love, by Nicholas Wolterstorff. William B. Eerdmann s Publishing Company, ix pages. $35.00 (hardcover).

Reflections on Xunzi. Han-Han Yang, Emory University

The Important Questions: a Dialogue between Cary Smith and Ph.D Candidate

THE PURE THEORY OF LAW

Mill s Utilitarian Theory

Louisiana Law Review. Cheney C. Joseph Jr. Louisiana State University Law Center. Volume 35 Number 5 Special Issue Repository Citation

SATISFICING CONSEQUENTIALISM AND SCALAR CONSEQUENTIALISM

On Law. (1) Eternal Law: God s providence over and plan for all of Creation. He writes,

Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 110W Fall 2014 Russell Marcus

Adam Smith and the Limits of Empiricism

Transcription:

1 MILL ON JUSTICE: CHAPTER 5 of UTILITARIANISM Lecture Notes Dick Arneson Philosophy 13 Fall, 2005 Some people hold that utilitarianism is incompatible with justice and objectionable for that reason. Utilitarianism according to its critics can imply that we should in certain situations treat people unfairly, violate their moral rights. Utilitarianism "does not take seriously the distinction between persons," some say. The quoted slogan alludes to the thought that utilitarianism extends what is acceptable in choices that one person makes for her own life to situations of conflict of interest among distinct persons. It is prudent, and permissible, for me to accept the modest pain of going to the dentist now to avoid the bigger pain of a toothache later, but utilitarianism holds that if I can gain for Smith relief of a pain equivalent to toothache by imposing on Jones a smaller pain equivalent to going to the dentist and no other option I can choose produces more utility than I should impose on Jones. In chapter 5 of Utilitarianism J. S. Mill takes up the supposed conflict between utilitarianism and justice. His argument is difficult, complex, and subtle. In the end the question arises whether he meets the objection or evades it. Mill takes the problem to be that the sentiment of justice feels to most of us more compelling and morally more authoritative than the sentiment of benevolence associated with utilitarianism. Mill thinks that people are in general willing enough to allow that objectively the dictates of justice coincide with a part of the field of general expediency." Still, the "subjective mental feeling of justice is usually more imperative in its demands that the feeling "which commonly attaches to simple expediency" (p. 42). We begin by asking what is the common quality that unites all modes of conduct and policy we deem just. It is thought normally to be unjust to (a) violate someone's legal rights, at least those that ought to be his rights, (b) not to treat people as they deserve, (c) to break faith with anyone, (d) to be partial in those situations where impartiality is required, and (e) to treat people unequally, though people disagree wildly as to what sort of equality might be morally required. Mill cannot find a common thread here, so breaks off this discussion and starts another. Mill looks at the history of usage of the word and finds the idea of justice tied to the idea of conformity to law, at least law as it ought to be. We call conduct unjust that we do not think should be enforced by law, but what is thought unjust is always thought to be fit for punishment, either by law, or public opinion, or by pangs of conscience. But this is not the specific idea of injustice but the more general idea of a moral wrong. An act that is morally wrong is one that ought to be punished somehow (and an act is morally right, rather than

2 merely nice, if not doing that act would be morally wrong). To get the specific idea of injustice we add to the idea of a wrong act a particular person or persons wronged by that wrong act. Mill states, "Justice implies something which it is not only right to do, and wrong not to do, but which some individual person can claim from us as his moral right" (p. 49). Example that illustrates Mill's point: Consider Minimally Decent Samaritanism: acting in an emergency situation to save someone's life when one can do so at small cost and risk to oneself. Some people think that Minimally Decent Samaritanism is conduct one ought to do, but if one does not do it, one has maybe been uncharitable, but violates no right of the person who is not saved from death. Others think that not only is failure to conform to the norm of Minimally Decent Samaritanism wrong, but it also violates a right that the person who could be saved has to the easy rescue. The people who hold the latter view will say that failing to be a Minimally Decent Samaritan is unjust; those who hold the former view will deny such conduct is unjust. Next, Mill asks what is the relation of justice so construed to utility. He gives several arguments against affirming that justice is a norm that should have independent moral force against the idea of the general welfare. 1. The origin of justice is a primitive instinct. Of the sense of justice he asserts that "the sentiment itself does not arise from anything which would commonly or correctly be termed an idea of expediency, but that, though the sentiment does not, whatever is moral in it does" (p. 50). He goes on to say that the desire to punish someone who harms a person grows out of two primitive sentiments--the instinct of self-defense and the feeling of sympathy. We want to harm those we see as threatening to harm us and those with whom we sympathize. There isn't anything moral in these instincts, they need to be tamed and shaped by morality, which Mill identifies with the principle of utility. When that is done, I only want to retaliate against those who threaten me and those near and dear to me with harm if I see that retaliating promotes the general welfare (happiness) and does not merely satisfy my desire for retaliation. 2. Justice is an ambiguous oracle. Injustice occurs when there is a violation of some person's right. When someone has a right to something, he has "a valid claim on society to defend him in the possession of it" (p. 52). But rights claims multiply. On almost any side of any controversial issue, people on all sides of the dispute claim they have a right to win. Mill gives examples. Some say punishment is just only when done to benefit the person punished; others say this would be wrong and that punishment is acceptable only when needed to protect the legitimate interests of other people, others say punishment is always unjust. Some say the punishment should be exactly proportioned or matched to

3 the severity of the crime; others say that the only good justification for punishment is that it is necessary to deter that criminal or others from committing further crimes. Mill also gives the example of seemingly intractable disputes about just wages. A third example is taxation: again opposed views that cannot all be correct present themselves as right and just. If we wish to respect and protect people's rights, how can we decide what people's rights are? Mill says only utility can reasonably resolve these conflicting claims. The rights claim that is valid is the one protection of which best promotes the general happiness. 3. Part of the explanation of the strength of the moral feeling that we ought to do what is just is that the subset of the moral rules promoting utility that concerns justice is the subset that regulates matters that are very important to people's lives and on which a lot of utility turns. The utilitarian does not admit that justice is a moral standard independent and distinct from utility but acknowledges that the part of (supposed) justice that coincides with what utilitarianism recommends is "the chief part, and incomparably the most sacred and binding part, of all morality" (p. 58). These rules that are in the overlap of justice and utility include rules forbidding people to hurt one another or interfere with their freedom without good reason. Punishing those who violate useful social rules and being disposed to reciprocate good for good are also norms of justice backed by utilitarianism. Of course no such justice rules are absolute; they admit of exceptions when circumstances are unusual and the general happiness is best served by making an exception. 4. The core of justice is implied by the principle of utility. Doing to each "according to his deserts, returning good for good, as well as repressing evil by evil, " requires us to "treat all equally well...who have deserved equally well of us" an requires society to "treat all equally well who have deserved equally well of it." This is "the highest abstract standard of social and distributive justice." But this rule itself is derived from the utilitarian first principle of morals, which requires that each person's happiness counts equally in calculations to determine social policy as every other person's. An equal claim of everyone to happiness along with "an equal claim to all the means of happiness" except insofar as considerations of incentives qualify the claim is thus the norm of justice and implied by the utilitarian morality. Evaluation of Mill's arguments. I take Mill's points in the order that he presents them. 1. By itself it is not clear that this has any argumentative force. The principle of utility might have its historical origin in a primitive sentiment of sympathy. If so, this does not tend to show that the principle of utility is a bad principle that should not be accepted. The same goes for the sentiment of justice.

4 2. Mill is pointing out that you can't beat a theory except with a theory. We should not then rest content with particular judgments that disagree with utilitarianism but should try to refine and order these judgments into an acceptable theory of justice. Mill challenges the opponent to produce such a theory but does not show it cannot be done. Also, we might deny that justice never gives firm guidance. Even if there are kinds of case where justice tends to speak with a forked tongue, supporting all sides in a dispute, there may be other cases where justice is unambiguous. And even if justice considerations in no case determine the morally right answer, they might still rule out some wrong answers, and the utilitarian recommendation might be among these wrong answers. 3. Suppose justice partially overlaps with utility. This still leaves open the question what to say about the area where there is no overlap and utilitarian reasoning and claims about moral rights conflict. 4. The utilitarian norm of equality is a norm of equal consideration: In determining the right policy, do not ignore or discount anyone's interests. But this is compatible with extreme inequality in the policy that is chosen, if our aim is to maximize the sum of utility. For some, equal consideration might not seem equality enough. Also, neutrally and equally counting everyone's interests may itself be unjust. The justice theorist will say we should count as positive reason for a policy only that it satisfies legitimate interests. That slaveholders benefit from slavery is not a consideration, one might say, that should count in favor of slavery. It is wrong for the utilitarian to count this slaveholders interest as a positive consideration at all in the calculation that determines correct social policy, as the utilitarian principle requires her to do. This problem remains even if the slaveholders' interest is ultimately outweighed in the utilitarian calculation by the greater interests of those who suffer under slavery. I don't raise these criticisms as decisive, just thoughts to start discussion. Question: does Mill ever address a case where justice considerations seem to weigh heavily against the policy recommendation that it would seem utilitarianism should give? ***** Aside from the justice versus utility issue, chapter 5 is of interest for another reason. See chapter 5, paragraph 14. There Mill suggests a new proposal, apparently different from what he has asserted earlier in the book, about what the utilitarian criterion of right conduct is. The chapter 5 suggestion is that a wrong act is one that is fit to be punished or ought to be punished, and a utilitarian account of wrong acts then stipulates

that these acts that ought to be punished are the ones punishing which would maximize utility. A right act is then one such that failure to do it is wrong. An act is neither right nor wrong if it is not wrong to do it and not wrong not to do it either. This seems to be a different idea from the scalar criterion suggested in chapter 1. That holds: Order all the possible acts a person could now do from best to worst by the standard of producing most utility (or least disutility). The closer an act is to the best choice, the more it is right, and the further it is from the worst choice, the more it is wrong. (Act utilitarianism is the yet different idea that one should always do the best act in this order and anything else one does is wrong.) Consider an example: I can order fish or chicken or carne asada tacos at a restaurant one night, and more utility would be gained if I choose the fish tacos, least if I choose chicken. The act utilitarian test gives the result that I do what is wrong if I do not order fish tacos. The chapter 5 test gives the result that my act of ordering nonfish tacos would not be wrong because it would not maximize utility to set in place any social practice that punishes acts like this one in any way. The scalar test yields the result that it would be more right to order fish than carne asada and more wrong to order chicken than carne asada. In this example the chapter 5 test has some plausibility: since only small amounts of utility are at stake, why bring right and wrong into the evaluation of the choice? At some points in chapter 2 Mill hints at a rule utilitarian test, so he proposes at least three and maybe four different utilitarian standards in all without choosing among them or noticing that they are different. 5