The Additive Fallacy

Similar documents
Oxford Scholarship Online

18 Die Philippa Foot 1

Phil 108, July 15, 2010

THE ROAD TO HELL by Alastair Norcross 1. Introduction: The Doctrine of the Double Effect.

Scanlon on Double Effect

Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan

How should I live? I should do whatever brings about the most pleasure (or, at least, the most good)

Intending Versus Foreseeing Harm

Living High and Letting Die

Quinn s Doctrine of Doing and Allowing (DDA)

Judge s Two Options: he can (i) let the rioters kill the five hostages, or (ii) frame an innocent person for the crime, and have him executed.

The Trolley Problem. 1. The Trolley Problem: Consider the following pair of cases:

Thomson s turnabout on the trolley

NOTE ON THE DOCTRINE OF DOUBLE EFFECT AND THE DOCTRINE OF ACTS AND OMISSIONS For Philosophy 13 Fall, 2004

Suicide. 1. Rationality vs. Morality: Kagan begins by distinguishing between two questions:

The Realm of Rights, Chapter 6, Tradeoffs Judith Jarvis Thomson

Is it Reasonable to Rely on Intuitions in Ethics? as relying on intuitions, though I will argue that this description is deeply misleading.

Must Consequentialists Kill?

The Moral Relevance of the Past (Hanna)

Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives

Thresholds for Rights

The Non-Identity Problem from Reasons and Persons by Derek Parfit (1984)

Quinn s DDE. 1. Quinn s DDE: Warren Quinn begins by running through the familiar pairs of cases:

Philosophy 1100: Ethics

NOTE ON THE DOCTRINE OF DOUBLE EFFECT AND THE DOCTRINE OF ACTS AND OMISSIONS For Philosophy 13 Fall, 2008

Ethics is subjective.

Killing and Letting Die

inertia Moral Philos Stud (2008) 140: DOI /s x Sartorio Carolina

Truth and Molinism * Trenton Merricks. Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, 2011.

Jeff McMahan, The Ethics of Killing: Problems at the Margins of Life. Oxford: Oxford University Press, xiii pp.

A Contractualist Reply

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

Adapted from The Academic Essay: A Brief Anatomy, for the Writing Center at Harvard University by Gordon Harvey. Counter-Argument

Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience

The Harm of Coming into Existence

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

The Prospective View of Obligation

WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY

Equality, Fairness, and Responsibility in an Unequal World

Well-Being, Disability, and the Mere-Difference Thesis. Jennifer Hawkins Duke University

HOW TO BE RESPONSIBLE FOR SOMETHING WITHOUT CAUSING IT* Carolina Sartorio University of Wisconsin-Madison

SATISFICING CONSEQUENTIALISM AND SCALAR CONSEQUENTIALISM

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

THE CASE OF THE MINERS

WHEN is a moral theory self-defeating? I suggest the following.

The Nature of Death. chapter 8. What Is Death?

Torture Does Timing Matter?

The Critical Mind is A Questioning Mind

Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is

A CONSEQUENTIALIST RESPONSE TO THE DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Nicholas R. Baker, Lee University THE DEMANDS OF ACT CONSEQUENTIALISM

Zimmerman, Michael J. Subsidiary Obligation, Philosophical Studies, 50 (1986):

Universities of Leeds, Sheffield and York

Chapter 2: Reasoning about ethics

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

Utilitarianism. But what is meant by intrinsically good and instrumentally good?

FAILURES TO ACT AND FAILURES OF ADDITIVITY. Carolina Sartorio University of Wisconsin-Madison

Blame and Forfeiture. The central issue that a theory of punishment must address is why we are we permitted to

Answers to Five Questions

On Some Alleged Consequences Of The Hartle-Hawking Cosmology. In [3], Quentin Smith claims that the Hartle-Hawking cosmology is inconsistent with

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY

DOES CONSEQUENTIALISM DEMAND TOO MUCH?

Virtue Ethics without Character Traits

Ethical Relativism 1. Ethical Relativism: Ethical Relativism: subjective objective ethical nihilism Ice cream is good subjective

Killing Innocent People

PHIL 202: IV:

BEGINNINGLESS PAST AND ENDLESS FUTURE: REPLY TO CRAIG. Wes Morriston. In a recent paper, I claimed that if a familiar line of argument against

Ethical non-naturalism

Deontology, Rationality, and Agent-Centered Restrictions

what makes reasons sufficient?

In Defense of Culpable Ignorance

The Comparative Badness for Animals of Suffering and Death Jeff McMahan November 2014

Compatibilist Objections to Prepunishment

Why We Shouldn t Reject Conflicts: A Critique of Tadros. The original publication is available at

Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1

DEFENDING DOUBLE EFFECT Ralph Wedgwood

ON PROMOTING THE DEAD CERTAIN: A REPLY TO BEHRENDS, DIPAOLO AND SHARADIN

What is real? Heaps, bald things, and tall things

The Non-Identity Non-Problem ( )

On the Relevance of Ignorance to the Demands of Morality 1

5 A Modal Version of the

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows:

Stem Cell Research on Embryonic Persons is Just

Ethical Theory for Catholic Professionals

CHECKING THE NEIGHBORHOOD: A REPLY TO DIPAOLO AND BEHRENDS ON PROMOTION

HOW TO BE (AND HOW NOT TO BE) A NORMATIVE REALIST:

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

The Doctrine of Doing and Allowing II: The Moral Relevance of the Doing Allowing Distinction

Lost in Transmission: Testimonial Justification and Practical Reason

in Social Science Encyclopedia (Routledge, forthcoming, 2006). Consequentialism (Blackwell Publishers, forthcoming, 2006)

PLEASESURE, DESIRE AND OPPOSITENESS

7AAN2011 Ethics. Basic Information: Module Description: Teaching Arrangement. Assessment Methods and Deadlines. Academic Year 2016/17 Semester 1

WORLD UTILITARIANISM AND ACTUALISM VS. POSSIBILISM

A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel

The Problem of Justified Harm: a Reply to Gardner

The Trolley Problem. 11 Judith Jarvith Thomson Killing, Letting Die and the Trolley Problem (1976) 59 Oxford University Press 204-

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Transcription:

The Additive Fallacy by Shelly Kagan (1988) Much moral philosophy is concerned with defending or attacking the moral relevance of various distinctions. Thus consequentialists disagree with deontologists, and deontologists disagree among themselves, over whether any moral weight should be given to such distinctions as that between what one does and what one merely allows, or to the distinction between what one intends as a means, and what one merely foresees as a side-effect, and so on. Similarly, there is disagreement over the moral relevance of such factors as the motive of the agent, the consequences of a given act, or the guilt of those who may be harmed. (On some matters, perhaps, there is widespread agreement: there seems to be a contemporary consensus, e.g., that skin color is of no intrinsic moral importance.) Such discussions, of course, are of intrinsic theoretical interest, for as moral philosophers we would like to have adequate beliefs about which factors (and which distinctions) are morally relevant. They are also, furthermore, of some practical importance, for we appeal to such factors in assessing the moral status of actions in difficult and controversial cases, and in order to explain and defend our judgments. Obviously, however, such practical applications are of limited value until we have determined whether or not a given distinction actually merits being given moral weight. But how are we to settle this? How can we defend, or attack, claims involving the moral relevance of different distinctions? A very common form of argument proceeds by offering a pair of cases that differ only in terms of the factor in question. If we judge the two cases to be morally different, it is argued, this difference must arise from the different values of the given factor (everything else being held constant), and so the factor is shown to be morally relevant. If we judge the cases to be similar, on the other hand, despite the variation in the given factor, this shows that the factor is not actually morally relevant after all. Let us call the pair of cases offered for comparison contrast cases (since the argument turns on the presence or absence of a contrast in our judgments about the cases), and let us call arguments of this sort contrast arguments. By way of example, consider the distinction between what I do and what I (merely) allow. If I take out my gun and shoot you, I have brought about your death, killed you: I have done harm. In contrast, if I merely come upon you drowning, and fail to throw you the life preserver, I have not done any harm to you, even if you drown: I have only allowed harm. Most of us not only draw this distinction, we give it moral weight, holding that doing harm is worse than merely allowing harm. Now it is not easy to make the do/allow distinction precise, but this need not concern us here. Assuming that we can make the distinction, we still need to ask: is it morally relevant?

A critic of the do/allow distinction might argue as follows: "The issue of whether I brought about a given harm or merely allowed it is not itself of intrinsic moral importance. No doubt the distinction is typically correlated with other factors which do make a difference morally, and this has perhaps blinded us to the irrelevance of the do/allow distinction itself. For example, cases of doing harm are typically also cases of harming as a means, or cases where the agent has a repugnant motive, or cases where the consequences would be better if the act in question were avoided, and so on; cases of allowing harm, on the other hand, typically do not display these features. [Different critics will, of course, offer different lists of factors.] For this reason, cases of doing harm typically are worse than cases of allowing harm. But this does not show that the distinction between doing and allowing itself affects the moral status of an act. For if the distinction were morally relevant, it should make a difference even when all of these other factors are held constant. We can see that this isn't so, however, by considering this pair of contrast cases: a) Gertrude pushes Bertrand into a deep pit, hoping that the fall will kill him so that she will inherit the family fortune; b) Seeing that Bertrand is about to fall into a deep pit, Gertrude deliberately refrains from warning him, hoping that the fall will kill him so that she will inherit the family fortune. These cases display the same morally relevant features (e.g., motive, outcome, etc.); they differ only with regard to the doing or allowing of harm. If the do/allow distinction were itself of genuine moral importance, there should be some difference in the moral status of the two acts. But surely Gertrude's behavior in the second case is quite as bad as in the first, despite the fact that in the first case she kills Bertrand, while in the second she merely allows him to die. Since the difference between doing and allowing harm does not make a difference in this case, we can see that the do/allow distinction is not itself of any intrinsic moral importance." Armed with this conclusion, the critic may go on to derive moral implications concerning other cases. He might, for example, argue that our failure to make significant contributions to famine relief is roughly the moral equivalent of murder. For although we are only allowing the starving to die, given the moral irrelevance of the do/allow distinction, our failure to aid is morally as bad as if we were killing them. (Other differences, of course, e.g., our lack of ill will toward the starving, may ameliorate the badness of our act somewhat in comparison with typical cases of murder.) There are a number of ways in which a defender of the do/allow distinction might attempt to defuse the critic's argument, and I will discuss some in the next section. But first it is important to see that contrast arguments can be used to advocate as well as to criticize a distinction. Thus the advocate of the do/allow distinction might argue as

follows: "Admittedly, cases of doing harm typically differ from cases of allowing harm in terms of several morally relevant factors. But of course this does not show that the do/allow distinction lacks moral importance in its own right. If it were morally irrelevant, then in contrast cases where the only difference was whether harm was done or merely allowed, all other features being held constant, no moral difference between the cases should remain. But we can see that this is not so, by considering the following pair of cases: c) Ludwig sees Sylvia drowning, but since the rocks beneath the water would do extensive damage to his boat, he decides not to rescue her; d) Ludwig sees that his boat is about to hit Sylvia, but since avoiding her would mean steering into the rocks, which would do extensive damage to his boat, he decides not to change course. Certainly there is something morally unacceptable about Ludwig's behavior in the first case; but surely his action is even worse in the second. Yet how could there be this moral difference in the status of the two cases if the do/allow distinction were morally irrelevant? After all, all of the other relevant features of the two cases are the same. So it must be that the do/allow distinction is of intrinsic moral importance, and what we have just established is that doing harm is morally more significant than merely allowing harm." Armed with this conclusion, the advocate may go on to suggest that negative duties (not to do harm) are more strict than positive duties (to provide aid). Or she might use her conclusion in defense of the claim that an innocent person may not be harmed, even if this is the only way to save several other people from equivalent harms. And so on. This time it is the critic of the distinction who must try to disarm the contrast argument. But it should be clear that although the two sides may disagree about the use of particular instances of contrast arguments, they share a common belief in the general strategy behind such arguments. Both sides believe that with a properly constructed pair of contrast cases, the moral status of the cases will differ if and only if the do/allow distinction is morally relevant. The contrast strategy clearly assumes that if a factor has genuine moral relevance, then for any pair of cases, where the given factor varies while others are held constant, the cases in that pair will differ in moral status. (The difference, of course, need not be so extreme as to make, e.g., one act permissible and the other act impermissible; the point is simply that some difference in moral status should exist.) That is, putting aside difficulties with proper construction and assessment, in principle any one pair of cases should be sufficient to settle the question of whether the given factor is of intrinsic moral relevance. In effect, the contrast strategy must be assuming that if variation in a given factor makes a difference anywhere, it makes a difference everywhere. Let us call this the ubiquity thesis.

Despite the seductiveness of this line of thought, I believe it is mistaken. An analogy may be helpful here. The presence or absence of oxygen has a role in determining chemical reactions. This role is presumably universal-that is, the fundamental laws of chemistry do not vary from case to case. Yet, obviously enough, the particular effects of oxygen's presence or absence do vary: in some cases, for example, the presence of oxygen makes a difference to whether or not a compound burns; but it would be a mistake to think that it must make this difference in every case. This is because making a difference to whether compounds burn is not, strictly speaking, part of the role of oxygen in the laws of chemistry. Rather, it is a consequence of that role in particular cases. The mere fact that the role of oxygen in the laws of chemistry is universal does not imply that some particular kind of effect must be universal. Similarly, the mere fact that the role of some factor in the fundamental principles of morality must be universal does not automatically imply that some particular effect must be universal. Whether the ubiquity thesis is true depends on taking a substantive position on the role of genuine moral factors. The view which underlies the use of contrast arguments seems to be this: the function that determines the overall status of the act given the values of the particular factors is an additive one. That is, the status of the act is the net balance or sum which is the result of adding up the separate positive and negative effects of the individual factors. On this view, each factor makes a contribution, whether positive or negative, to the moral status of the act. (The strength of the contribution will depend on the particular value of the factor in the given situation, e.g., how much good will be done by the act.) The overall status is the sum of these positive and negative contributions. Once again, however, on such a view there would be no particular reason to assume that the ubiquity thesis was true. The mathematical analogy should make this clear. If S = x y + z, then although differences in y would normally make a difference to S when x and z are held constant, in those cases where x is equal to zero, differences in y would not affect S. Similarly, if the contributions of some of the moral factors are multiplied, then it might well be in certain cases that even variation in a genuine factor would make no difference to the overall moral status of the act. (No doubt it would be somewhat strained to speak of the factor's contribution in such a case.) It is only by assuming that the governing function is additive that there is any plausible reason to assume that this possibility is avoided. One or two examples should be sufficient to show that most theorists will need to reject the additive assumption. Consider, first, the issue of self-defense. Most of us believe that in some situations killing someone in self-defense can be morally permissible. Imagine such a situation, and compare these two cases:

e) In order to defend myself against the aggressor, I push him into a pit, expecting the fall to kill him; f) In order to defend myself against the aggressor, I refrain from warning him about the pit into which he is about to fall, and I expect the fall to kill him. Most of us will certainly want to claim that the moral status of these two cases is the same, even though, obviously enough, in the first case I do harm, while in the second case I merely allow it. Not everyone will accept this judgment: some may insist that there is a slight difference, but it is lost on our insufficiently sensitive intuitions; others (e.g., pacifists) may claim the difference is rather significant. Nonetheless, most of us will want to maintain that the distinction between doing harm and allowing harm makes no difference in such legitimate cases of self-defense. The crucial point to see is that even the advocate of the do/allow distinction may well want to make this claim, and surely it is coherent for her to do so. In fact, this view-that although the difference between doing harm and allowing it typically has a great effect on the moral status of an act, in cases of self-defense it makes no difference whatsoever-is not only coherent: most of us want to claim that it is true. Yet if the additive assumption is correct, then the view I have just described must be false, since it violates the ubiquity thesis to claim that although the do/allow distinction normally makes a difference, in cases of self-defense it does not. The example of self-defense suggests that most of us (unwittingly, perhaps) are committed to the rejection of the additive assumption. Recall the earlier mathematical example where S = x y + z, and suppose for simplicity that x can equal only zero or one. When x is equal to one, differences in y will make a difference to S; but when x is equal to zero, differences in y will not matter at all. The self-defense/non-self-defense factor seems to act somewhat like x in this example: normally, with a value of one, it allows the do/allow distinction to make a difference; but in cases of self-defense, it takes on the value of zero, and so differences between doing and allowing harm do not affect the moral status of the act at all.

Reply to Rachels from Killing, Letting Die, and the Trolley Problem by Judith Jarvis Thomson (1976) Morally speaking it may matter a great deal how a death comes about, whether from natural causes, or at the hands of another, for example. Does it matter whether a man was killed or only let die? A great many people think it does: they think that killing is worse than letting die. And they draw conclusions from this for abortion, euthanasia, and the distribution of scarce medical resources. Others think it doesn't, and they think this shown by what we see when we construct a pair of cases which are so far as possible in all other respects alike, except that in the one case the agent kills, in the other he only lets die. So, for example, imagine that (1) Alfred hates his wife and wants her dead. He puts cleaning fluid in her coffee, thereby killing her, and that (2) Bert hates his wife and wants her dead. She puts cleaning fluid in her coffee (being muddled, thinking it's cream). Bert happens to have the antidote to cleaning fluid, but he does not give it to her; he lets her die. 1 Alfred kills his wife out of a desire for her death; Bert lets his wife die out of a desire for her death. But what Bert does is surely every bit as bad as what Alfred does. So killing isn't worse than letting die. But I am now inclined to think that this argument is a bad one. Compare the following argument for the thesis that cutting off a man's head is no worse than punching a man in the nose. Alfrieda knows that if she cuts off Alfred's head he will die, and, wanting him to die, cuts it off; Bertha knows that if she punches Bert in the nose he will die Bert is in peculiar physical condition and, wanting him to die, punches him in the nose. But what Bertha does is surely every bit as bad as what Alfrieda does. So cutting off a man's head isn't worse than punching a man in the nose. It s not easy to say just exactly what goes wrong in this argument, because it s not clear what we mean when we say, as we do, such things as that cutting off a man s head is worse than punching a man in the nose. The argument brings out that we don t mean by it anything which entails that for every pair of acts, actual or possible, one of which is a nose-punching, the other of which is a head cutting-off, but which are so far as possible in all other respects alike, the second is worse than the first. Or at least the argument brings out that we can t mean anything which entails this by Cutting off a man's head is worse than punching a man in the nose if we want to go on taking it for true. Choice is presumably in question, and the language which 1 Cf. Judith Jarvis Thomson, "Rights and Deaths," Philosophy and Public Affairs (Winter 1973), sec. 3. Cf. also Michael Tooley, "Abortion and Infanticide," Philosophy and Public Affairs (Fall 1972), sec. 5, and James Rachels, "Active and Passive Euthanasia," New England Journal of Medicine, January 9, 1975.

comes most readily is perhaps this: if you can cut off a man s head or punch him in the nose, then if he is in normal condition and if other things are equal you had better not choose cutting off his head. But there is no need to go into any of this for present purposes. Whatever precisely we do mean by Cutting off a man s head is worse than punching a man in the nose, it surely (a) is not disconfirmed by the cases of Alfrieda and Bertha, and (b) is confirmed by the fact that if you can now either cut off my head, or punch me in the nose, you had better not choose cutting off my head. This latter is a fact. I don t say that you had better choose punching me in the nose: best would be to do neither. Nor do I say it couldn't have been the case that it would be permissible to choose cutting off my head. But things being as they are, you had better not choose it. I m not going to hazard a guess as to what precisely people mean by saying Killing is worse than letting die. I think the argument of the first paragraph brings out that they can t mean by it anything which entails that for every pair of acts, actual or possible, one of which is a letting die, the other of which is a killing, but which are so far as possible in all other respects alike, the second is worse than the first i.e., they can t if they want to go on taking it for true. I think here too that choice is in question, and that what they mean by it is something which is not disconfirmed by the cases of Alfred and Bert. And isn t what they mean by it confirmed by the fact isn t it a fact? that in the following case, Charles must not kill, that he must instead let die: (3) Charles is a great transplant surgeon. One of his patients needs a new heart, but is of a relatively rare blood-type. By chance, Charles learns of a healthy specimen with that very blood-type. Charles can take the healthy specimen s heart, killing him, and install it in his patient, saving him. Or he can refrain from taking the healthy specimen s heart, letting his patient die. I should imagine that most people would agree that Charles must not choose to take out the one man s heart to save the other: he must let his patient die. And isn t what they mean by it further confirmed by the fact isn t it a fact? that in the following case, David must not kill, that he must instead let die: (4) David is a great transplant surgeon. Five of his patients need new parts one needs a heart, the others need, respectively, liver, stomach, spleen, and spinal cord but all are of the same, relatively rare, blood-type. By chance, David learns of a healthy specimen with that very blood-type. David can take the healthy specimen s parts, killing him, and install them in his patients, saving them. Or he can refrain from taking the healthy specimen s parts, letting his patients die. If David may not even choose to cut up one where five will thereby be saved, surely what people who say Killing is worse than letting die mean by it must be right!

Killing and Letting Die by Philippa Foot (1984) Is there a morally relevant distinction between killing and allowing to die? Many philosophers say that there is not, and further insist that there is no other closely related difference, as for instance that which divides act from omission, whichever plays a part in determining the moral character of an action. James Rachels has argued this case in his well known article on active and passive euthanasia, Michael Tooley has argued it in in his writings on abortion, and Jonathan Bennett argued it in the Tanner Lectures given in Oxford in 1980. 1 I believe that these people are mistaken, and this is what I shall try to show in this essay. I shall first consider the question in abstraction from any particular practical moral problem, and then I shall examine the implications my thesis may have concerning the issue of abortion. The question with which we are concerned has been dramatically posed by asking whether we are as equally to blame for allowing people in Third World countries to starve to death as we would be for killing them by sending poisoned food? In each case it is true that if we acted differently by sending good food or by not sending poisoned food those who are going to die because we do not send the good food or do send the poisoned food would not die after all. Our agency plays a part in what happens whichever way they die. Philosophers such as Rachels, Tooley, and Bennett consider this to be all that matters in determining our guilt or innocence. Or rather they say that although related things are morally relevant, such as our reasons for acting as we do and the cost of acting otherwise, these are only contingently related to the distinction between doing and allowing. If we hold them steady and vary only the way in which our agency enters into the matter, no moral differences will be found. It is of no significance, they say, whether we kill others or let them die, or whether they die by our act or our omission. Whereas these latter differences may at first seem to affect the morality of action, we shall always find on further enquiry that some other difference such as a difference of motive or cost has crept in. Now this, on the face of it, is extremely implausible. We are not inclined to think that it would be no worse to murder to get money for some comfort such as a nice winter coat than it is to keep the money back before sending a donation to Oxfam or Care. We do not think that we might just as well be called murderers for one as for the other. And there are a host of other examples which seem to make the same point. We may have to allow one person to die if saving him would mean that we could not save five others, as for instance when a drug is in short supply and he needs five times as much as each of them, but that does not mean that we could carve up one patient to get "spare parts" for five.

These moral intuitions stand clearly before us, but I do not think it would be right to conclude from the fact that these examples all seem to hang on the contrast between killing and allowing to die that this is precisely the distinction that is important from the moral point of view. For example, having someone killed is not strictly killing him, but seems just the same morally speaking; and on the other hand, turning off a respirator might be called killing, although it seems morally indistinguishable from allowing to die. Nor does it seem that the difference between 'act' and 'omission' is quite what we want, in that a respirator that had to be turned on each morning would not change the moral problems that arise with the ones we have now. Perhaps there is no locution in the language which exactly serves our purposes and we should therefore invent our own vocabulary. Let us mark the distinction we are after by saying that one person may or may not be 'the agent' of harm that befalls someone else. When is one person 'the agent' in this special sense of someone else's death, or of some harm other than death that befalls him? This idea can easily be described in a general way. If there are difficulties when it comes to detail, some of these ideas may be best left unsolved, for there may be an area of indefiniteness reflecting the uncertainty that belongs to our moral judgments in some complex and perhaps infrequently encountered situations. The idea of agency, in the sense that we want, seems to be composed of two subsidiary ideas. First, we think of particular effects as the result of particular sequences, as when a certain fatal sequence leads to someone's death. This idea is implied in coroners' verdicts telling us what someone died of, and this concept is not made suspect by the fact that it is sometimes impossible to pick out a single fatal sequence as in the lawyers' example of the man journeying into the desert who had two enemies, one of whom bored a hole in his water barrel while another filled it with brine. Suppose such complications absent. Then we can pick out the fatal sequence and go on to ask who initiated it. If the subject died by poisoning and it was I who put the poison into his drink, then I am the agent of his death; likewise if I shot him and he died of a bullet wound. Of course there are problems about fatal sequences which would have been harmless but for special circumstances, and those which although threatening would have run out harmlessly but for something that somebody did. But we can easily understand the idea that a death comes about through our agency if we send someone poisoned food or cut him up for spare parts, but not (ordinarily) if we fail to save him when he is threatened by accident or disease. Our examples are not problem cases from this point of view. Nor is it difficult to find more examples to drive our original point home, and show that it is sometimes permissible to allow a certain harm to befall someone, although it would have been wrong to bring this harm on him by one's own agency, i.e., by originating or sustaining the sequence which brings the harm. Let us consider, for instance, a pair of cases which I shall call Rescue I and Rescue II. In the first Rescue story we are hurrying in our jeep to save some people let there be five of them

who are imminently threatened by the ocean tide. We have not a moment to spare, so when we hear of a single person who also needs rescuing from some other disaster we say regretfully that we cannot rescue him, but must leave him to die. To most of us this seems clear, and I shall take it as clear, ignoring John Taurek's interesting if surprising argument against the obligation to save the greater number when we can. 2 This is Rescue I and with it I contrast Rescue II. In this second story we are again hurrying to the place where the tide is coming in in order to rescue the party of people, but this time it is relevant that the road is narrow and rocky. In this version the lone individual is trapped (do not ask me how) on the path. If we are to rescue the five we would have to drive over him. But can we do so? If we stop he will be all right eventually: he is in no danger unless from us. But of course all five of the others will be drowned. As in the first story our choice is between a course of action which will leave one man dead and five alive at the end of the day and a course of action which will have the opposite result. And yet we surely feel that in one case we can rescue the five men and in the other we cannot. We can allow someone to die of whatever disaster threatens him if the cost of saving him is failing to save five; we cannot, however, drive over him in order to get to them. We cannot originate a fatal sequence, although we can allow one to run its course. Similarly, in the pair of examples mentioned earlier, we find a contrast between on the one hand refusing to give to one man the whole supply of a scarce drug, because we can use portions of it to save five, and on the other, cutting him up for spare parts. And we notice that we may not originate a fatal sequence even if the resulting death is in no sense our object. We could not knowingly subject one person to deadly fumes in the process of manufacturing some substance that would save many, even if the poisoning were a mere side effect of the process that saved lives. Considering these examples, it is hard to resist the conclusion that it makes all the difference whether those who are going to die if we act in a certain way will die as a result of a sequence that we originate or one that we allow to continue, it being of course something that did not start by our agency. So let us ask how this could be? If the distinction which is roughly that between killing and allowing to die is morally relevant, because it sometimes makes the difference between what is right and what is wrong, how does this work? After all, it cannot be a magical difference, and it does not satisfy anyone to hear that what we have is just an ultimate moral fact. Moreover, those who deny the relevance can point to cases in which it seems to make no difference to the goodness or badness of an action having a certain result, as, for example, that some innocent person dies, whether due to a sequence we originate or because of one we merely allow. And if the way the result comes about sometimes makes no difference, how can it ever do so? If it sometimes makes an action bad that harm came to someone else as a result of a sequence we originated, must this not always contribute some element of badness? How can a consideration be a reason for saying that an action is bad in one place without being at least a reason for saying the same elsewhere?

Let us address these questions. As to the route by which considerations of agency enter the process of moral judgment, it seems to be through its connection with different types of rights. For there are rights to noninterference, which form one class of rights; and there are also rights to goods or services, which are different. And corresponding to these two types of rights are, on the one hand, the duty not to interfere, called a 'negative duty', and on the other the duty to provide the goods or services, called a 'positive duty'. These rights may be in certain circumstances be overridden, and this can in principle happen to rights of either kind. So, for instance, in the matter of property rights, others have in ordinary circumstances a duty not to interfere with our property, though in exceptional circumstances the right is overridden, as in Elizabeth Anscombe's example of destroying someone's house to stop the spread of fire. 3 And a right to goods or services depending, for example, on a promise will quite often be overridden in the same kind of case. There is, however, no guarantee that the special circumstances that allow one kind of right to be overridden will always allow the overriding of the other. Typically, it takes more to justify an interference than to justify the withholding of goods or services; and it is, of course, possible to think that nothing whatsoever will justify, for example, the infliction of torture or the deliberate killing of the innocent. It is not hard to find how all this connects with the morality of killing and allowing to die and in general with harm which an agent allows to happen and harm coming about through his agency, in my special sense having to do with originating or sustaining harmful sequences. For the violation of a right to noninterference consists in interference, which implies breaking into an existing sequence and initiating a new one. It is not usually possible, for instance, to violate that right to noninterference, which is at least part of what is meant by 'the right to life' by failing to save someone from death. So if, in any circumstances, the right to noninterference is the only right that exists, or if it is the only right special circumstances have not overridden, then it may not be permissible to initiate a fatal sequence, but it may be permissible to withhold aid. The question now is whether we ever find cases in which the right to noninterference exists and is not overridden, but where the right to goods or services either does not exist or is here overridden. The answer is, of course, that this is quite a common case. It often happens that whereas someone's rights stand in the way of our interference, we owe him no service in relation to that which he would lose if we interfered. We may not deprive him of his property, though we do not have to help him secure his hold on it, in spite of the fact that the balance of good and evil in the outcome (counting his loss or gain and the cost to us) will be the same regardless of how they come about. Similarly, where the issue is one of life and death, it is often impermissible to kill someone although special circumstances having to do with the good of others make it permissible, or even required, that we do not spend the time or resources needed to save his life, as for instance, in the story of Rescue I, or in that of the scarce drug.

It seems clear, therefore, that there are circumstances in which it makes all the difference, morally speaking, whether a given balance of good and evil came about through our agency (in our sense), or whether it was rather something we had the ability to prevent but, for good reasons, did not prevent. Of course, we often have a strict duty to prevent harm to others, or to ameliorate their condition. And even where they do not, strictly speaking, have a right to our goods or services, we should often be failing (and sometimes grossly failing) in charity if we did not help them. But, to reiterate, it may be right to allow one person to die in order to save five, although it would not be right to kill him to bring the same good to them. How is it, then, that anyone has ever denied this conclusion, so sympathetic to our everyday moral intuitions and apparently so well grounded in a very generally recognized distinction between different types of rights? We must now turn to an argument first given, by James Rachels, and more or less followed by others who think as he does. Rachels told a gruesome story of a child drowned in a bathtub in two different ways: in one case someone pushed the child's head under water, and in the other he found the child drowning and did not pull him out. Rachels says that we should judge one way of acting as bad as the other, so we have an example in which killing is as bad as allowing to die. But how, he asks, can the distinction ever be relevant if it is not relevant here? 4 Based on what has been said earlier, the answer to Rachels should be obvious. The reason why it is, in ordinary circumstances, "no worse" to leave a child drowning in a bathtub than to push it under, is that both charity and the special duty of care that we owe to children give us a positive obligation to save them, and we have no particular reason to say that it is "less bad" to fail in this than it is to be in dereliction of the negative duty by being the agent of harm. The level of badness is, we may suppose, the same, but because a different kind of bad action has been done, there is no reason to suppose that the two ways of acting will always give the same result. In other circumstances one might be worse than the other, or only one might be bad. And this last result is exactly what we find in circumstances that allow a positive but not a negative duty to be overridden. Thus, it could be right to leave someone to die by the roadside in the story of Rescue I, though wrong to run over him in the story of Rescue II; and it could be right to act correspondingly in the cases of the scarce drug and the ''spare parts." Let me now consider an objection to the thesis I have been defending. It may be said that I shall have difficulty explaining a certain range of examples in which it seems permissible, and even obligatory, to make an intervention which jeopardizes people not already in danger in order to save others who are. They following case has been discussed. Suppose a runaway trolley is heading toward a track on which five people are standing, and that there is someone who can possibly switch the points, thereby diverting the trolley onto a track on which there is only one person. It seems that he

should so this, just as a pilot whose plane is going to crash has a duty to steer, if he can, toward a less crowded street than the one he sees below. But the railway man then puts the one man newly in danger, instead of allowing the five to be killed. Why does not the one man's right to noninterference stand in his way, as one person's right to noninterference impeded the manufacture of poisonous fumes when this was necessary to save five? The answer seems to be that this is a special case, in that we have here the diverting of a fatal sequence and not the starting of a new one. So we could not start a flood to stop a fire, even when the fire would kill more than the flood, but we could divert a flood to an area in which fewer people would be drowned. A second and much more important difficulty involves cases in which it seems that the distinction between agency and allowing is inexplicably irrelevant. Why, I shall be asked, is it not morally permissible to allow someone to die deliberately in order to use his body for a medical procedure that would save many lives? It might be suggested that the distinction between agency and allowing is relevant when what is allowed to happen is itself aimed at. Yet this is not quite right, because there are cases in which it does make a difference whether one originates a sequence or only allows it to continue, although the allowing is with deliberate intent. Thus, for instance, it may not be permissible to deprive someone of a possession which only harms him, but it may be reasonable to refuse to get it back for him if it is already slipping from his grasp. 5 And it is arguable that nonvoluntary passive euthanasia is sometimes justifiable although nonvoluntary active euthanasia is not. What these examples have in common is that harm is not in question, which suggests that the 'direct', i.e., deliberate, intention of evil is what makes it morally objectionable to allow the beggar to die. When this element is present it is impossible to justify an action by indicating that no origination of evil is involved. But this special case leaves no doubt about the relevance of distinguishing between originating an evil and allowing it to occur. It was never suggested that there will always and everywhere be a difference of permissibility between the two. Having defended the moral relevance of the distinction which roughly corresponds to the contrast between killing and allowing to die, I shall now ask how it affects the argument between those who oppose and those who support abortion. The answer seems to be that this entirely depends on how the argument is supposed to go. The most usual defense of abortion lies in the distinction between the destruction of a fetus and the destruction of a human person, and neither side in this debate will have reason to refer to the distinction between being the agent of an evil and allowing it to come about. But this is not the only defense of abortion which is current at the present time. In an influential and widely read article, Judith Jarvis Thomson has suggested an argument for allowing abortion which depends off denying what I have been at pains to maintain. 6

Thomson suggests that abortion can be justified, at least in certain cases, without the need to deny that the fetus has the moral rights of a human person. For, she says, no person has an absolute right to the use of another's body, even to save his life, and so the fetus, whatever its status, has no right to the use of the mother's body. Her rights override its rights, and justify her in removing it if it seriously encumbers her life. To persuade us to agree with her she invents an example, which is supposed to give a parallel, in which someone dangerously ill is kept alive by being hooked up to the body of another person, without that person's consent. It is obvious, she says, that the person whose body was thus being used would have no obligation to continue in that situation, suffering immobility or other serious inconvenience, for any length of time. We should not think of him as a murderer if he detached himself, and we ought to think of a pregnant woman as having the same right to rid herself of an unwanted pregnancy. Thomson's whole case depends on this analogy. It is, however, faulty if what I have said earlier is correct. According to my thesis, the two cases must be treated quite differently because one involves the initiation of a fatal sequence and the other the refusal to save a life. It is true that someone who extricated himself from a situation in which his body was being used in the way a respirator or a kidney machine is used could, indeed, be said to kill the other person in detaching himself. But this only shows, once more, that the use of "kill" is not important: what matters is that the fatal sequence resulting in death is not initiated but is rather allowed to take its course. And although charity or duties of care could have dictated that the help be given, it seems perfectly reasonable to treat this as a case in which such presumptions are overridden by other rights those belonging to the person whose body would be used. The case of abortion is of course completely different. The fetus is not in jeopardy because it is in its mother's womb; it is merely dependent on her in the way children are dependent on their parents for food. An abortion, therefore, originates the sequence which ends in the death of the fetus, and the destruction comes about "through the agency" of the mother who seeks the abortion. If the fetus has the moral status of a human person then her action is, at best, likened to that of killing for spare parts or in Rescue II; conversely, the act of someone who refused to let his body be used to save the life of the sick man in Thomson's story belongs with the scarce drug decision, or that of Rescue I. It appears, therefore, that Thomson's argument is not valid, and that we are thrown back to the old debate about the moral status of the fetus, which stands as the crucial issue in determining whether abortion is justified.

Notes 1. James Rachels, "Active and Passive Euthanasia," New England Journal of Medicine, 292 (January 9, 1975), 78 80; this volume, chapter 5: Michael Tooley, "Abortion and Infanticide," Philosophy and Public Affairs, 2, no. 1 (Fall 1972), 37 65; Jonathan Bennett, ''Morality and Consequences," in The Tanner Lectures on Human Values, II, ed. Sterling McMurrin (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), pp. 47 16. 2. John Taurek, "Should the Numbers Count?" Phitosophy and Public Affairs, no. 4 (Summer 1977): 293 316. 3. G. E. M. Anscombe, "Modern Moral Philosophy," Philosophy, 33 (1958): 1 19. 4. Rachels, "Active and Passive Euthanasia." 5. Cf. Philippa Foot, "Killing, Letting Die, and Euthanasia: A Reply to Holly Smith Goldman," Analysis, 41, no. 4 (June 1981). 6. Judith Jarvis Thomson, "A Defense of Abortion," Philosophy and Public Affairs, 1 (1971), 44.