RETHINKING RELIGIOUS LANGUAGE IN THE AGE OF SCIENCE

Similar documents
Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable

Positive Philosophy, Freedom and Democracy. Roger Bishop Jones

Positive Philosophy, Freedom and Democracy. Roger Bishop Jones

A Defence of Kantian Synthetic-Analytic Distinction

Divisibility, Logic, Radical Empiricism, and Metaphysics

A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

Rationalist-Irrationalist Dialectic in Buddhism:

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University,

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Wittgenstein on forms of life: a short introduction

THE CRISIS OF THE SCmNCES AS EXPRESSION OF THE RADICAL LIFE-CRISIS OF EUROPEAN HUMANITY

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT David Hume: The Origin of Our Ideas and Skepticism about Causal Reasoning

PHILOSOPHY IAS MAINS: QUESTIONS TREND ANALYSIS

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

Conventionalism and the linguistic doctrine of logical truth

A Brief History of Thinking about Thinking Thomas Lombardo

Religion and Science: The Emerging Relationship Part II

Evidence and Transcendence

1/8. Introduction to Kant: The Project of Critique

P. Weingartner, God s existence. Can it be proven? A logical commentary on the five ways of Thomas Aquinas, Ontos, Frankfurt Pp. 116.

"Can We Have a Word in Private?": Wittgenstein on the Impossibility of Private Languages

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

PHILOSOPHICAL RAMIFICATIONS: THEORY, EXPERIMENT, & EMPIRICAL TRUTH

145 Philosophy of Science

Death and Immortality (by D Z Phillips) Introductory Remarks

The Cosmological Argument, Sufficient Reason, and Why-Questions

Is the Skeptical Attitude the Attitude of a Skeptic?

VERIFICATION AND METAPHYSICS

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations

Possibility and Necessity

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Alternative Conceptual Schemes and a Non-Kantian Scheme-Content Dualism

Title: Wittgenstein on forms of life: a short introduction.

PHI2391: Logical Empiricism I 8.0

STANISŁAW BRZOZOWSKI S CRITICAL HERMENEUTICS

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

A Logical Approach to Metametaphysics

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

Phil/Ling 375: Meaning and Mind [Handout #10]

Holtzman Spring Philosophy and the Integration of Knowledge

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins

When meaning goes by the board, what about philosophy? Jaroslav Peregrin

POLI 343 Introduction to Political Research

EXAM PREP (Semester 2: 2018) Jules Khomo. Linguistic analysis is concerned with the following question:

The Coherence of Kant s Synthetic A Priori

A Priori Knowledge: Analytic? Synthetic A Priori (again) Is All A Priori Knowledge Analytic?

Quine on the analytic/synthetic distinction

Copyright 2015 by KAD International All rights reserved. Published in the Ghana

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Can Christianity be Reduced to Morality? Ted Di Maria, Philosophy, Gonzaga University Gonzaga Socratic Club, April 18, 2008

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

The purpose of this paper is to introduce the problem of skepticism as the

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

A Rational Solution to the Problem of Moral Error Theory? Benjamin Scott Harrison

ABSTRACT of the Habilitation Thesis

Towards Richard Rorty s Critique on Transcendental Grounding of Human Rights by Dr. P.S. Sreevidya

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

Pure Pragmatics and the Transcendence of Belief

Introduction. 1 Bertrand Russell, The Problems of Philosophy (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, n.d.), 7.

John D. Caputo s book is one in a new series from Penguin called Philosophy in

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

Overview. Is there a priori knowledge? No: Mill, Quine. Is there synthetic a priori knowledge? Yes: faculty of a priori intuition (Rationalism, Kant)

CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH

LOCKE STUDIES Vol ISSN: X

METHODENSTREIT WHY CARL MENGER WAS, AND IS, RIGHT

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

1/7. The Postulates of Empirical Thought

Defending A Dogma: Between Grice, Strawson and Quine

RECENT WORK THE MINIMAL DEFINITION AND METHODOLOGY OF COMPARATIVE PHILOSOPHY: A REPORT FROM A CONFERENCE STEPHEN C. ANGLE

Perspectival Methods in Metaphysics

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Metaphysical Problems and Methods

The Copernican Shift and Theory of Knowledge in Immanuel Kant and Edmund Husserl.

5: Preliminaries to the Argument

Gary Ebbs, Carnap, Quine, and Putnam on Methods of Inquiry, Cambridge. University Press, 2017, 278pp., $99.99 (hbk), ISBN

Heidegger's What is Metaphysics?

PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT FALL SEMESTER 2009 COURSE OFFERINGS

Instructor's Manual for Gregg Barak s Integrating Criminologies. Prepared by Paul Leighton (Boston: Allyn & Bacon, 1997) * CHAPTER 4

Fabrizio Luciano, Università degli Studi di Padova

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

Practical Wisdom and Politics

THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN SCIENCE, RELIGION AND ARISTOTELIAN THEOLOGY TODAY

Transcription:

Jo u rn a l o f D harm a 33, 4 (October-Decembcr 2008), 405-4 i I RETHINKING RELIGIOUS LANGUAGE IN THE AGE OF SCIENCE Koshy Tharakan* 1. Introduction Relation o f science and religion has been at the centre o f many discourses in the past as well as in the recent times. Some o f these were meant to refute religious claims in the light o f scientific truths about the world, while others took the pain o f explaining the essential compatibility between the two. The former subjects religion to the scrutiny o f science while the latter reads science in religion or religion in science.1 Both these attempts are ill-conceived as they conflate the logic o f one with the other. Ian G. Barbour, who has pioneered the philosophical debate between science and religion, provides four typologies to relate the two domains o f science and religion, namely, conflict, independence, dialogue, and integration.2 Nevertheless, his position is one that treats the two as distinct disciplines and yet sharing a common ground rather than two separate and conflicting discourses. In what follows, we attempt to understand the nature o f the interaction o f these two, science and religion, from a phenomenological perspective. In order to do that, we have to look into the life-world (Lebenswelt) that engenders science and houses religious experiences. 2. Positivism an d Phenom enology Positivism is the dominant image o f science that came along with the enlightenment rationality^. Central to the positivist philosophy is the conception that there is a firm line that separates facts from values. The fact-value dichotomy that informed positivism culminated in the verifiability theory o f m eaning and the consequent rejection o f *Dr. Koshy T harakan teaches philosophy of social science and phenomenology at the Department of Philosophy, Goa University, since 1996. He was awarded a doctorate in philosophy for his work Phenomenological Approach to Social Reality by the University o f Hyderabad. The argument for Intelligent Design voiced in Dover, USA, is an offshoot of reading religion into science, whereas the talk of scientific truths in the Vedas is an instance o f reading science into religion. 2Ian G. Barbour, Issues in Science and Religion, New York: Harper and Row, 1966. O ZOM ofdkmrmm: Dkmrmmrtm Jonrmmi JUSgurtu mmdpkuosophits ( P ttrm in a VMyi K jhetnn, Bsngsforc), ISSN: 4253-7222

Koshy Tharakan metaphysics in the last century. According to logical positivists, statements are cognitively meaningful only if they are verifiable in principle. Thus, for them the meaning o f a proposition lies in its method of verification. Connected to the principle o f verification is the positivist thesis that the world is a collection o f individual facts. The positivist belief that observations are pure seems to make the principle o f verification credible. However, the post-positivist philosophy o f science has convincingly shown that our observations are theory-laden and many have questioned the availability o f an independent world as our beliefs about the world itself are fashioned by our theories. In contemporary philosophical writings, many have called the verifiability thesis into question as they regard the same as a dogma of positivism'. Phenomenology rejects positivism as the latter fails to grasp adequately how facts themselves are constituted. The positivist failure to problematise facts resulted in the reification o f facts and ignoring the role o f human subjects in making facts meaningful. Phenomenology, on the other hand, tries to look at the ways in which facts are constituted in human consciousness. Husserl, the founding father o f phenomenology, views science not just as a fact, but also as a problem that is in need of philosophical understanding. Phenomenology understands science as a cultural fact that has been shaped by human practice. It originates from the interaction o f the members o f the professional community o f scientists. The scientific community is an open community insofar as the works achieved by the predecessors are taken up and continued by the successors. Criticisms, confirmations, and corrections find place in the activities of this community. Husserl identifies the spirit o f modem science with Galilean Science that mathematizes nature.3 Through mathematization o f nature, nature itself becomes idealized. Mathematical model makes the study o f nature a routine affair. Husserl compares the Galilean Science to a machine. The method o f science, once formalized, renders science to a mathematical process. The successful operation o f the machine guarantees the success of practical achievement, especially in the form o f technology. Husserl criticizes the Galilean style o f mathematizing the nature. It misunderstands the objective nature as something hidden from the lifeworld, a reality that is to be explored beneath the appearances o f the lifeworld. 3See Edmund Husserl, The Crisis o f European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology, trans. David Carr, Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1970.

Journal o f Dkarma 33, 4 (October-December 2008) I Rethinking Religious Language in the Age o f Science J 3. Life-W orld: H om e of Science and Religion According to Husserl, the crisis o f European sciences is borne out o f the fact that it severed its relation to the life-world. The European sciences, thus, are uprooted. It erroneously substituted th world o f everyday experiences, the life-world, with the idealized world o f science. Thus, Nature is identified with its constituted mathematical or quantifiable object. The technological success o f science prompted to ignore the foundational acts that constitute scientific experiences from the prescientific experiences. To understand the real significance o f the alienation o f science from its soil, the life-world, we have to first analyze the lifeworld. Gurwitsch notes three prominent features o f the life-world.4 First of all, the life-world is extended in space and time. This spatio-temporal framework makes our experience o f objects in the everyday world related to one another. Secondly, life-world exhibits regularities amidst variations. Things have their habits o f behaviour, as Husserl puts it. It is not from science that we learn that if a stone is lifted and consequently released, it would fall down. Thus, we gain the idea o f universal causality from our everyday world o f experiences. Knowledge o f such regularities is significant in conducting our lives. Finally, things in the life-world exhibit a sort o f relativity and subjectivity. Our observations in the life-world are perspectival. Each o f us sees things in the life-world according to our standpoints. Thus, the same thing appears to each o f us in a different manner. However, through our inter-subjective experiences we learn that all o f us share the same world o f objects, live in the common life-world, at least, with respect to a community o f fellow inhabitants. Husserl writes about the origin o f geometry to elaborate his points. According to Husserl, geometry originated in the practical needs of measurement in our everyday life. Every historical community, however ancient it may be, possesses some idea o f measurement. The accuracy o f our measurement depends upon the purpose for which we measure. The whole o f science, like other cultural enterprises, exists through tradition. They have not merely arisen casually. Being a tradition, it has formed through human activity. Tradition is not something that had been handed down passively. It is dynamic in the sense that we renew our traditions by way o f sustained inquiry. It thereby makes up a totality in which each present stage functions as the premise 4Aron Gurwitsch, Galilean Physics in the Light of Husserl s Phenomenology in Phenomenology and Sociology: Selected Readings, ed. Thomas Luckmann, Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1978, 72.

Koshy Tharakan for the future project. Thus, all our scientific activities have a further project, which awaits its execution.5 Phenomenological philosophy o f science maintains that the life-world is prior to the world o f science. The world o f science is a theoretical construction that comes up later. However, this is not to rule out the reality o f the scientific world, rather it maintains that it is only through die life-world that we have access to the world o f science. If science, thus, enables us to gather knowledge about the physical world, religion refers to a system o f values by which man places himself in relation to nature and a reality that transcends nature. The factual knowledge provided by the sciences often count as the epitome o f rationality while the religious values we cherish are explained away as mere articles o f faith. Many a time we tend to be sceptical about religious claims and beliefs. Quite often, the doubts regarding the truth, or even the plausibility o f such beliefs, germinate from our seemingly rational appraisal o f religious notions. Thus, the religiously inclined ones tell us not to subject religion to the test o f reason; rather we must surrender to the dictates o f faith. Understanding the nature o f religious beliefs in the above manner institutes a sharp boundary between the realms o f faith and reason. We tend to banish reason while invoking faith to ground religious beliefs. In doing so, we seem to think that rationality is the sole privilege of our scientific beliefs where faith has no role to play. However, many a scientific theory develops from the faith the scientist has in holding certain beliefs. In addition, what we reason out to a great extent depends on what we believe as a matter of faith. An example from science itself illustrates this point. Though both Huygens and Hooke held that light travelled m waves, just like sound, Newton propounded the corpuscular theory of light that conceives the phenomenon o f light as a stream o f particles. O f course; Newton had certain rationale to believe so. For instance, sound that travels in a waveform can be heard around comers, light cannot normally be sera around a comer unless it is reflected from a surface. Nevertheless, Newtdn did not have all the evidence for his theory. More than a century later another scientist, Thomas Young, once again, came up with the wsiye theory of light. In fact, Young suggested that light travelled in transverse waves, like waves o f water, and not in longitudinal waves as sound does! O f course, the current theory on light holds that light sometimes act like sedmund Husserl, The Origin of Geometry in Phenomenology and Sociology, 67-68.

Journal o f Dharma 33, 4 (October-December 2008) I Rethinking Religious Language in the Age o f Science particles and sometimes like waves, which amply explains why scientists could not succeed conclusively in defining the nature o f light for so long.6 However, the point that needs our attention is why did Newton who performed much earlier the same experiment, as young did, hold on to particle theory even when his contemporaries argued in favour o f wave theory? Philosophers o f science point out that it is because o f Newton s metaphysical faith in atomism that prompted him to adhere to the particle theory rather than the wave theory. 4. Language-G am e: Being of Science and Religion Those who conceive faith and reason as antithetical to each other seem to think that unless these two are kept at a distance from each other it is impossible to defend religious beliefs in the era o f science and technology. Apparently, it becomes imperative for them to argue for faith alone as constituting the domain o f religion. However, faith devoid o f reason degenerates into dogmatism and fundamentalism. Thus, we need to give reason its due respect and domain even in religion. This does not mean that we have to subject religious beliefs to the scrutiny o f science. What I try to articulate may be illustrated by invoking Ludwig W ittgenstein s metaphor o f Language-Game that clarifies the nature o f language and meaning.7 Just as rules at once constitute and regulate games, our language is constituted and governed by a set o f rules. We play each game according to the specific rules o f that game. In following the set o f rules o f a game, the game itself is played out. Similarly, every language-game has its own set o f rules and by following the rules o f a language-game we bring to fore a particular fact. Though both volleyball and basketball are games we play with a ball, we differentiate between the two games on the basis o f the rules applicable to each game. Similarly, we have to differentiate between science and religion. Here, I wish to submit that religion and science are two different language-games and, as such, it is meaningless either to do science by following the rules o f a religious language-game or to practice religion by following the rules o f a scientific language-game.8 B y the same 6See Ray Spangenburg and Diane K. Moser, The History o f Science: From the Ancient Greeks to the Scientific Revolution, Hyderabad: Universities Press, 1999,68-75. 7See Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, trans. G. E. M. Anscombe, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1953. Though Wittgenstein gives many examples of different language-games such as telling a story, making a joke, reporting an event, etc., in Philosophical

410 1Koshy Tharakan token, what counts as an evidence o f scientific rationality need not be the evidence for rationally holding a religious belief, nor can we contradict a religious belief by the rationality o f science, as science and religion are two different language-games. It is a wasteful exercise to look for scientific compatibility as far as religious beliefs are concerned. Following rules, whether we play soccer or practise religion is a matter o f rationality. Only rational beings can consistently follow rules. A soccer player who suddenly changes rules in the middle o f a game and start playing according to different rules is seen as an irrational player. The necessity o f rationality along with faith in religious beliefs is all the more felt in our contemporary cultural matrix.9 One who exercises reason in his religious faith can see that different religions are not different language-games but belong to the same language-game o f worship, devotion, humility, righteousness, and other attenuated values. 5. C onclusion The language-game interpretation o f the practice o f science and religion has its critics amongst scientists and theologians as well as philosophers. The advocates o f science oppose it because it dethrones science from the privileged position it has enjoyed since its birth, as it becomes one language-game, albeit quite useful, amongst many other language-games. Accordingly, science as the sole rational way o f understanding the world is no more defensible in the metaphor o f language-game. However, postpositivist philosophy o f science has rejected many such exalted image o f science. Tlie idea o f objective truth, which science used to claim for its findings is shown to be highly problematical. A pragmatist like Quine says that in point o f epistemological footing the physical objects that are posited by science and the gods o f Homer differ only in degree and not in kind.10 The superiority o f the scientific over the cultural, then, may be seen Investigations, he does not cite science and religion as language-games. Later; Phillips and many others gave currency to the metaphor of a religious languagegame. 9The recent controversy surrounding Sethusamudram in India is a best example of this confusion of the logic of two distinct language-games. In this regard, see Koshy Tharakan, Science amidst Religion: The Politics of Knowledge, Current Science 94, 6 (March 2008), 714. 10W. V. O. Quine, Two Dogmas of Empiricism in Classics o f Analytic Philosophy, ed. Robert R. Ammerman, Bombay/New Delhi: Tata McGraw-Hill Publishing Co., 1965,196-213.

Journal o f Dharma 33,4 (October-Dccem bcr 2008) I 4X 1 Rethinking Religious Language in the Age o f Science as to do with the efficacy o f the former in structuring the experience that we have o f the world. Advantage o f the metaphor of language-game is that it successfully resists any attempt to read science in religion or vice versa, which is an obscurantist enterprise that confuses the logic o f two distinct languagegames. However, it may be opposed by the religiously inclined on the ground that it does not justify the importance o f religion. Religion, thus, may at best be conceived as a game but could not explain why it is important.11 Here we m ay want to emphasize that the importance o f religion apart from the spiritual values it fosters lies in its role o f providing a language o f contrast vis-a-vis other language-games. In other words, religion assumes a logical necessity for the appreciation o f other spheres o f life-world and vice-versa. As Phillips points out, the force o f religious beliefs depends, in part, on what is outside religion... So, far from it being true that religious beliefs can be thought o f as isolated language-games, cut off from all other forms o f life, the fact is that religious beliefs cannot be understood at all unless their relation to other modes o f life is taken into account. 12 Thus, it can be argued that understanding religion as a distinct language-game does not diminish the significance o f religion or reduce it to an isolated and contingent activity o f language-game. It is important to understand that it is the spiritual experience and not the doctrine o f any religious tradition per se that is o f significance to phenomenological analysis o f religion. Religion tells us how to live in the world purposively and meaningfully. It informs us how to obtain nonmaterial satisfaction from the world. Unlike scientific knowledge, in this sense, religious experience is very much a part o f the lived experience o f human beings. Nevertheless, human existence in terms o f the lived experience is an integral whole. We do integrate different spheres into our lived experience, thus engendering meaning and purpose. In other words, life-world expands the horizon o f both science and religion. 1 D. Z. Phillips, Religious Beliefs and Language Games in The Philosophy o f Religion, ed. Basil Mitchell, Oxford; Oxford University Press, 1971, 132. l2phillips, Religious Beliefs and Language Games, 134.