Article selection and anaphora in the German relative clause Julian Grove and Emily Hanink University of Chicago

Similar documents
Some observations on identity, sameness and comparison

Discourse Constraints on Anaphora Ling 614 / Phil 615 Sponsored by the Marshall M. Weinberg Fund for Graduate Seminars in Cognitive Science

The Interpretation of Complement Anaphora: The Case of The Others

ANAPHORIC REFERENCE IN JUSTIN BIEBER S ALBUM BELIEVE ACOUSTIC

Semantics of DP islands

Factivity and Presuppositions David Schueler University of Minnesota, Twin Cities LSA Annual Meeting 2013

HS01: The Grammar of Anaphora: The Study of Anaphora and Ellipsis An Introduction. Winkler /Konietzko WS06/07

Pronominal, temporal and descriptive anaphora

The projection problem of presuppositions

Anaphora Resolution in Biomedical Literature: A

Be Bound or Be Disjoint! Andrew Kehler and Daniel Büring. UCSD and UCLA

A presupposition is a precondition of a sentence such that the sentences cannot be

Coreference Resolution Lecture 15: October 30, Reference Resolution

ACD in AP? Richard K. Larson. Stony Brook University

Reference Resolution. Regina Barzilay. February 23, 2004

Reference Resolution. Announcements. Last Time. 3/3 first part of the projects Example topics

Solutions for Assignment 1

Semantics and Pragmatics of NLP DRT: Constructing LFs and Presuppositions

Presupposition Projection and Anaphora in Quantified Sentences

Lecture 9: Presuppositions

That -clauses as existential quantifiers

Conditions on Propositional Anaphora

Competition and Disjoint Reference. Norvin Richards, MIT. appear; Richards 1995). The typical inability of pronouns to be locally bound, on this

Kai von Fintel (MIT)

Entailment as Plural Modal Anaphora

Satisfied or Exhaustified An Ambiguity Account of the Proviso Problem

Models of Anaphora Processing and the Binding Constraints

Anaphoric Deflationism: Truth and Reference

CAS LX 522 Syntax I Fall 2000 November 6, 2000 Paul Hagstrom Week 9: Binding Theory. (8) John likes him.

Presupposition Projection and At-issueness

Presupposition and Rules for Anaphora

4) When are complex discourse entities constructed in the process of text comprehension?

Identifying Anaphoric and Non- Anaphoric Noun Phrases to Improve Coreference Resolution

ROBERT STALNAKER PRESUPPOSITIONS

Presupposition projection: Global accommodation, local accommodation, and scope ambiguities

The Semantics and Pragmatics of Presupposition

10. Presuppositions Introduction The Phenomenon Tests for presuppositions

Long-distance anaphora: comparing Mandarin Chinese with Iron Range English 1

Dialogue structure as a preference in anaphora resolution systems

ANAPHORA RESOLUTION IN MACHINE TRANSLATION

Extraposition and Covert Movement

Presupposition: An (un)common attitude?

2.1 Review. 2.2 Inference and justifications

Lexical Alternatives as a Source of Pragmatic Presuppositions

Could have done otherwise, action sentences and anaphora

TWO KINDS OF PERSPECTIVE TAKING IN NARRATIVE TEXTS

TURCOLOGICA. Herausgegeben von Lars Johanson. Band 98. Harrassowitz Verlag Wiesbaden

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1

08 Anaphora resolution

Presupposition and Accommodation: Understanding the Stalnakerian picture *

Coordination Problems

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic

What would count as Ibn Sīnā (11th century Persia) having first order logic?

ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR

Reductio ad Absurdum, Modulation, and Logical Forms. Miguel López-Astorga 1

Module 5. Knowledge Representation and Logic (Propositional Logic) Version 2 CSE IIT, Kharagpur

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

QUESTIONING GÖDEL S ONTOLOGICAL PROOF: IS TRUTH POSITIVE?

Category Mistakes in M&E

All They Know: A Study in Multi-Agent Autoepistemic Reasoning

An Analysis of Reference in J.K. Rowling s Novel: Harry Potter and the Half-Blood Prince

Definite Descriptions and the Argument from Inference

Automatic Evaluation for Anaphora Resolution in SUPAR system 1

Sloppy Identity in Surface and Deep Anaphora Hajime Hoji University of Southern California

Anaphora Resolution. Nuno Nobre

Brazilian Portuguese Bare Singulars and Discourse Referents

Phil 413: Problem set #1

A New Parameter for Maintaining Consistency in an Agent's Knowledge Base Using Truth Maintenance System

Some Anaphoric/Elliptical Constructions of English

Structured Discourse Reference to Propositions

(Refer Slide Time 03:00)

SEVENTH GRADE RELIGION

UC Berkeley, Philosophy 142, Spring 2016

Williams on Supervaluationism and Logical Revisionism

17. Tying it up: thoughts and intentionality

Exhaustification over Questions in Japanese

Exercises Introduction to morphosyntax

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information

Anaphora Resolution in Hindi Language

Two restrictions on possible connectives

Lecture 4. Before beginning the present lecture, I should give the solution to the homework problem

Logical Omniscience in the Many Agent Case

Topics in Linguistic Theory: Propositional Attitudes

The Representation of Logical Form: A Dilemma

Some questions about Adams conditionals

Intersubstitutivity Principles and the Generalization Function of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh. Shawn Standefer University of Melbourne

Maximize Presupposition and Two Types of Definite Competitors *

ZHANG Yan-qiu, CHEN Qiang. Changchun University, Changchun, China

Mandy Simons Carnegie Mellon University June 2010

Logophors, variable binding and the interpretation of have. *

A unified theory of ((in)definite) descriptions

finagling frege Mark Schroeder University of Southern California September 25, 2007

Judge dependence, epistemic modals, and predicates of personal taste

Class 33 - November 13 Philosophy Friday #6: Quine and Ontological Commitment Fisher 59-69; Quine, On What There Is

Reconsidering Raising and Experiencers in English

ROB VAN DER SANDT R V D S A N D H I L.K U N.N L

Wittgenstein s The First Person and Two-Dimensional Semantics

Artificial Intelligence: Valid Arguments and Proof Systems. Prof. Deepak Khemani. Department of Computer Science and Engineering

Haberdashers Aske s Boys School

Semantic Entailment and Natural Deduction

Transcription:

Article selection and anaphora in the German relative clause Julian Grove and Emily Hanink University of Chicago German definite articles are able to contract with prepositions under certain conditions. When a noun phrase is discourse anaphoric, contraction is blocked. In the current paper we present a puzzle: restrictive relative clauses require the use of the non-contracted (strong) article form, despite their apparent lack of anaphoricity; both the determiner of the head noun and the relative pronoun (which is, in most cases, syncretic with the definite article) surface with the strong form. We provide a uniform analysis of discourse anaphoric and relative clause uses that makes use of contexts, as defined in the dynamic framework of de Groote (2006). We argue that a lexical item, which we call anaph, whose purpose is to make reference to an individual provided by the context, intervenes between the noun and the article in the strong form. anaph makes reference to an individual provided by the global context in cases of anaphora, and to an individual provided by an updated local context in the case of relative clauses. 1

Introduction. Work in the semantics of anaphora that makes use of variables has assumed either that anaphoric expressions themselves are variables (Kamp, 1981; Heim, 1982, and work in this tradition), or that variables are properly contained in their syntactic description (Schwarz, 2009; Elbourne, 2005, 2008). Here we present a semantics for anaphoric definite descriptions in German that strongly supports a version of the latter view. The semantics we present is a variable-free account of the phenomenon presented, in that we give a lexical denotation to what traditionally serves the role of a variable on this view. We provide support for the view, and our proposal specifically, by showing that it solves a puzzle in the morphology and semantics of German relative clauses, as well as a novel puzzle involving the appearance of the modifier same. Data. The German definite article contracts with a preposition under certain conditions. Schwarz (2009) argues that the contracted weak form surfaces in situationally unique uses of a definite (see (1a)), while the non-contracted strong form surfaces in anaphora (see (1b)). (1) a. Hans ging zum Haus Hans went to+the house Hans went to the house. b. Hans ging zu dem Haus Hans went to the house Hans went to the house. While Schwarz (2009) shows that the strong article form in (1b) is required in anaphoric contexts, it is also obligatory in restrictive relatives clauses, and surprisingly so restrictive relatives do not at first glance appear to involve anaphora. We explain this puzzling use by showing that relative clauses do in fact constitute a case of anaphora, using the the variable-free theory of anaphora laid out by de Groote (2006), who treats pronouns as denoting anaphora-resolution functions. Puzzle. (2) gives a canonical use of the strong form in cross-sentential anaphora (Schwarz 2009). (2) Fritz wohnt seit Jahren in einem groben Haus. Er schwärmt von Fritz lives since years in a big house. He raves from Fritz has lived in a big house for years. He raves about the house. dem/#vom the Haus. house However, as Schwarz points out, the strong form is also required whenever the noun is modified by a relative clause, regardless of whether or not it is anaphoric to something in previous discourse. (The use of the strong form in the relative pronoun which is just the definite article, see Wiltschko (1998) is the result of an independent ban on the weak form when it lacks a nominal restriction.) (3) Fritz wohnt jetzt in dem/#im Haus, von dem/*vom er seit Jahren schwärmt. Fritz lives now in the/in+the house, from the/from+the he since years raves He now lives in the house that he has been raving about for years. The strength of the matrix form in (3) is unexpected given Schwarz s anaphoric generalization about the strong form: relative clauses do not obviously constitute instances of anaphora. We give a variable-free solution to the puzzle, whose composition we illustrate with the associative Lambek Calculus (Lambek, 1958). The analysis relies on the approach to anaphora provided by de Groote (2006), and moreover gives a straightforward account of anaphoric uses like (2), thus uniting both. Proposal. As indicated, we argue that the strong form is structurally more complex than the weak. A head, which we call anaph, intervenes between the determiner and the noun, triggering allomorphy of the determiner (c.f. Elbourne, 2005, 2008; Schwarz, 2009; Wiltschko, 2013; Simonenko, 2015). anaph introduces the property of being anaphoric, which is accomplished by the use of contexts, i.e., sets of individuals, whose type is γ (de Groote, 2006). Because not every meaning is 2

lexically sensitive to contexts, we make use of the intensionalization-transformation of de Groote and Kanazawa (2013), but, following Kobele (2015), set to contexts. (4) gives the relevant derivation, where pairs of expressions and denotations sit on the other side of the turnstile from their syntactic types. (4) Strong form: anaph, (λf (γe)γt.(λx γe.(λc γ.x c = sel c &f x c))) n[a]/n haus, (λx γe(λc γ.house (x c)).) n dem, (λp (γe)γt.(λc γ.(ιx e.p (λc γ.x) c))) d/n[a] anaph haus, (λx γe.(λc γ.x c = selc&house (x c))) n[a] dem anaph haus, (λc γ.(ιx e.x = selc&housex)) d In (4), sel, used in de Groote s analysis of pronouns, is a function from contexts to individuals, i.e., the anaphora-resolution function. anaph composes with the NP with the effect that the DP denotes the unique individual with the property denoted by the NP and which is the individual picked by by the function sel. anaph therefore has the same meaning involved in pronominal anaphora. Relative clauses. Relative clauses are formed via a head C with the denotation in (5), which selects for a property on its right (the gapped clause) and a function from properties to individuals on its left (the relative pronoun): (5) C = (λp (γe)γt.(λx ((γe)γt)γe.(λq (γe)γt.(λy γe.(λc γ.p (λc γ.x Q {y c})c))))) The attachment site of the restrictive relative clause is not at the matrix NP, but rather at the phrase headed by anaph. We additionally give a raising analysis of RCs (along the lines of Bhatt (2002)), wherein all material that would have been selected by the relative pronoun appears adjacent to the matrix determiner. The proof in (6) (which proceeds in subparts (6a)-(6e)) illustrates composition of the relative clause from (3), given the interpretation of C in (5). The last inference in (6e) yields the resulting meaning. (6) a. dem, (λp (γe)γt.(λc γ.(ιx e.p (λc γ.x) c))) d/n[a] P, P n[a] von, (λf γe.f) p[von]/d dem P, (λc γ.(ιx e.p (λc γ.x) c)) d von dem P, (λc γ(ιx e.p (λc γ.x)c).) p[von] /I von dem, (λp (γe)γt.(λc γ.(ιx e.p (λc γ.x) c))) p[von]/n[a] b. anaph, (λf (γe)γt.(λx γe.(λc γ.x c = selc&f x c))) n[a]/n haus, (λx γe.(λc γ.house (x c))) n anaph haus, (λx γe.(λc γ.x c = selc&house (x c))) n[a] c. schwaermt, (λx γe.(λy γe.(λc γ.rave abt (x c) (y c)))) (d\t)/p[von] x,x p[von] schwaermt x, (λy γe.(λc γ.rave abt (x c) (y c))) d\t fritz, (λc γ.f) d \E fritz schwaermt x, (λc γ.rave abt (x c) f) t /I fritz schwaermt, (λx γe.(λc γ.rave abt (x c) f)) t/p[von] d. (6c) c, (5) ((p[von]/n[a])\(n[a]\n[a]))/(t/p[von]) c fritz schwaermt, (λx ((γe)γt)γe.(λq (γe)γt.(λy γe.(λc γ.rave abt (x Q {y c}) f)))) (p[von]/n[a])\(n[a]\n[a]) e. (6a) (6d) \E von dem c fritz schwaermt, (λq (γe)γt.(λy γe.(λc γ.rave abt (ιx e.q (λc γ.x) {y c}) f))) n[a]\n[a] (6b) \E anaph haus von dem c fritz schwaermt, (λy γe.(λc γ.rave abt (ιx e.x = sel{y c} & housex) f)) n[a] Because there is only one member of the context used in the evaluation of the relative pronoun in (6), sel has no option but to select it. (6) may therefore be reduced to (7), the intuitively correct meaning for the relative clause. (7) (λy γe.(λc γ.rave abt (ιx e.x = y c & housex) f)) 3

Binding is therefore accomplished through the semantics of C, whose role is to pass a context with a single bound individual to the evaluation of its specifier. The use of the strong form as the determiner that selects nouns modified by relative clauses can now be seen as simply a special case of anaphora, which, following de Groote (2006), binding constitutes an instance of. The present account thus provides the first unified analysis of the strong form, accounting for its use in anaphora as well as in restrictive relative clauses in precisely the same way. In both cases, anaph composes with the NP, resulting in the unique individual both with the property denoted by the NP and which is identical to the individual picked by by the function sel. In the case of anaphora, the value of this individual is resolved by a salient antecedent; in the relative clause, it is resolved by the only possible value given by the context carried by C. Morphological evidence for anaph. The proposal that anaph intervenes between the article and the noun in the strong form is motivated by the behavior of the anaphoric modifier same, which surfaces in anaphora like (8). 1 The appearance same in (8) is explained if same (on its external reading) is an overt realization of anaph. In such examples, the definite article is either pronounced with same, or it contracts: (8) Es hängt an einem Haus. An demselben/am selben Haus findet ihr eine Jahreszahl... It hangs on a house. On the+same/on+the same house find you a date It s hanging on a house. On the same house you ll find a date... If same is the overt realization of anaph, we expect it to be available in the strong form of the matrix determiner in relative clauses as well. This is borne out, supporting our claim: (9) Sie wohnte in demselben/im selben Haus, das sie drei Jahre zuvor gekauft hatte. she lived in the+same/in+the same house, REL she three years before bought had She lived in the same house that she had bought three years beforehand. The mysterious availability of same in a seemingly non-anaphoric context like (9) is explained if it is realizing anaph in the strong matrix determiner, required in the formation of restrictive relatives. Outside of German, the Hebrew pronoun oto provides further evidence that the modifier same can realize anaph. While oto is a third-person accusative pronoun, (10) shows that the very same lexical item can also take on the meaning of same in anaphoric contexts, providing evidence that the item realizing a pronoun (i.e., that realizing anaph in Hebrew) can be realized as same. (10) Karati sefer. Itamar kara et oto ha-sefer. read.1sg book Itamar read.3sg.m ACC same the-book I read a book. Itamar read the same book. Conclusion. Our proposal offers the first variable free analysis of the strong article form in German, crucially explaining its role as the matrix determiner in relative clauses, while uniting this use with other instances of anaphora. We posit anaph to the be the locus of pronoun resolution inside the strong form, whose value is determined either by the discourse context (anaphora), or by the context provided by C (restrictive relatives). Independent evidence for anaph is shown through the ability of same to realize anaph in German as well as across languages, as shown by Hebrew. 1 The examples in (8)-(9) are modified from a Google search. 4

References Bhatt, Rajesh. 2002. The raising analysis of relative clauses: Evidence from adjectival modification. Natural Language Semantics 10:43 90. Elbourne, Paul. 2005. Situations and individuals. Cambridge: MIT Press. Elbourne, Paul. 2008. Demonstratives as individual concepts. Linguistics and Philosophy 31.4:409 466. de Groote, Philippe. 2006. Towards a Montagovian account of dynamics. In Proceedings of the 16th Conference on Semantics and Linguistic Theory, ed. M. Gibson and J. Howell, 1 16. Ithaca, NY: Cornell. de Groote, Philippe, and Makoto Kanazawa. 2013. A note on intensionalization. Journal of Logic, Language and Information 22:173 194. Heim, Irene. 1982. The semantics of definite and indefinite noun phrases. Doctoral Dissertation, University of Massachussetts, Amherst. Kamp, Hans. 1981. A theory of truth and semantic representation. In Formal methods in the study of language, ed. Jeroen A. Groenendijk, Theo M. V. Janssen, and Martin B. J. Stokhof, number 135 in Mathematical Centre Tracts, 277 322. Amsterdam: Mathematisch Centrum. Kobele, Gregory M. 2015. Montagovian dynamics in three easy steps. University of Chicago. Lambek, Joachim. 1958. The mathematics of sentence structure. American Mathematical Montly 65:154 170. Schwarz, Florian. 2009. Two types of definites in natural language. Doctoral Dissertation, University of Massachussetts, Amherst. Simonenko, Alexandra. 2015. Structural triggers of the loss of direct referentiality. Proceedings of the 32nd West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics (WCCFL 32). Wiltschko, Martina. 1998. On the syntax and semantics of (relative) pronouns and determiners. Journal of Comparative Germanic Linguistics 2.2:143 181. Wiltschko, Martina. 2013. Descriptive relative clauses in Austro-Bavarian German. The Canadian Journal of Linguistics/La revue canadienne de linguistique 58.2:157 189. 5