Introducing Our New Faculty

Similar documents
Chapter 3: More Deductive Reasoning (Symbolic Logic)

1/19/2011. Concept. Analysis

Example Arguments ID1050 Quantitative & Qualitative Reasoning

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

MISSOURI S FRAMEWORK FOR CURRICULAR DEVELOPMENT IN MATH TOPIC I: PROBLEM SOLVING

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

Philosophy 1100: Ethics

HOW TO ANALYZE AN ARGUMENT

Chapter 8 - Sentential Truth Tables and Argument Forms

Logic Appendix: More detailed instruction in deductive logic

Appendix: The Logic Behind the Inferential Test

PROSPECTIVE TEACHERS UNDERSTANDING OF PROOF: WHAT IF THE TRUTH SET OF AN OPEN SENTENCE IS BROADER THAN THAT COVERED BY THE PROOF?

Basic Concepts and Skills!

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Revisiting the Socrates Example

Tutorial A03: Patterns of Valid Arguments By: Jonathan Chan

Chapter 1. What is Philosophy? Thinking Philosophically About Life

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

HANDBOOK. IV. Argument Construction Determine the Ultimate Conclusion Construct the Chain of Reasoning Communicate the Argument 13

PHILOSOPHY 102 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC PRACTICE EXAM 1. W# Section (10 or 11) 4. T F The statements that compose a disjunction are called conjuncts.

Logic Book Part 1! by Skylar Ruloff!

Conditionals II: no truth conditions?

The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions. Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction Defining induction...

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 1. Background Material for the Exercise on Validity

Academic argument does not mean conflict or competition; an argument is a set of reasons which support, or lead to, a conclusion.

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Semantic Entailment and Natural Deduction

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

Instructor s Manual 1

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

Selections from Aristotle s Prior Analytics 41a21 41b5

Macmillan/McGraw-Hill SCIENCE: A CLOSER LOOK 2011, Grade 1 Correlated with Common Core State Standards, Grade 1

Intro Viewed from a certain angle, philosophy is about what, if anything, we ought to believe.

Critical Thinking. The Four Big Steps. First example. I. Recognizing Arguments. The Nature of Basics

What is an argument? PHIL 110. Is this an argument? Is this an argument? What about this? And what about this?

A R G U M E N T S I N A C T I O N

Logic: A Brief Introduction. Ronald L. Hall, Stetson University

Deductive Forms: Elementary Logic By R.A. Neidorf READ ONLINE

Study Guides. Chapter 1 - Basic Training

Chapter 9- Sentential Proofs

McDougal Littell High School Math Program. correlated to. Oregon Mathematics Grade-Level Standards

Lecture 3 Arguments Jim Pryor What is an Argument? Jim Pryor Vocabulary Describing Arguments

A Brief Introduction to Key Terms

Logic, Deductive And Inductive By Carveth Read READ ONLINE

PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy

Reductio ad Absurdum, Modulation, and Logical Forms. Miguel López-Astorga 1

Logic: The Science that Evaluates Arguments

4.1 A problem with semantic demonstrations of validity

Introduction to Logic

Statements, Arguments, Validity. Philosophy and Logic Unit 1, Sections 1.1, 1.2

How Gödelian Ontological Arguments Fail

Pastor-teacher Don Hargrove Faith Bible Church September 8, 2011

A Liar Paradox. Richard G. Heck, Jr. Brown University

b) The meaning of "child" would need to be taken in the sense of age, as most people would find the idea of a young child going to jail as wrong.

ON WRITING PHILOSOPHICAL ESSAYS: SOME GUIDELINES Richard G. Graziano

Module 5. Knowledge Representation and Logic (Propositional Logic) Version 2 CSE IIT, Kharagpur

Lecture 4.2 Aquinas Phil Religion TOPIC: Aquinas Cosmological Arguments for the existence of God. Critiques of Aquinas arguments.

Philosophical Arguments

Grade 7 Math Connects Suggested Course Outline for Schooling at Home 132 lessons

Deduction by Daniel Bonevac. Chapter 1 Basic Concepts of Logic

Pictures, Proofs, and Mathematical Practice : Reply to James Robert Brown

INTERMEDIATE LOGIC Glossary of key terms

What would count as Ibn Sīnā (11th century Persia) having first order logic?

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Chapter 2 Analyzing Arguments

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece

Handout 2 Argument Terminology

Chapter 1. Introduction. 1.1 Deductive and Plausible Reasoning Strong Syllogism

Evaluating Arguments

MATH1061/MATH7861 Discrete Mathematics Semester 2, Lecture 5 Valid and Invalid Arguments. Learning Goals

Test Item File. Full file at

PLEASE DO NOT WRITE ON THIS QUIZ

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

CRITICAL THINKING (CT) MODEL PART 1 GENERAL CONCEPTS

2. Refutations can be stronger or weaker.

Russell s Problems of Philosophy

The way we convince people is generally to refer to sufficiently many things that they already know are correct.

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Content Area Variations of Academic Language

Criticizing Arguments

In a previous lecture, we used Aristotle s syllogisms to emphasize the

UC Berkeley, Philosophy 142, Spring 2016

PHI Introduction Lecture 4. An Overview of the Two Branches of Logic

Syllabus Fall 2014 PHIL 2010: Introduction to Philosophy 11:30-12:45 TR, Allgood Hall 257

Genre Guide for Argumentative Essays in Social Science

I think, therefore I am. - Rene Descartes

Suppressed premises in real life. Philosophy and Logic Section 4.3 & Some Exercises

Informalizing Formal Logic

The Development of Laws of Formal Logic of Aristotle

The Roman empire ended, the Mongol empire ended, the Persian empire ended, the British empire ended, all empires end, and none lasts forever.

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Module 9- Inductive and Deductive Reasoning

PHIL 155: The Scientific Method, Part 1: Naïve Inductivism. January 14, 2013

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows:

REASONING ABOUT REASONING* TYLER BURGE

e x c e l l e n c e : an introduction to philosophy

Introduction to Logic

2.3. Failed proofs and counterexamples

Also, in Argument #1 (Lecture 11, Slide 11), the inference from steps 2 and 3 to 4 is stated as:

Reasoning, Argumentation and Persuasion

Transcription:

Dr. Isidoro Talavera Franklin University, Philosophy Ph.D. in Philosophy - Vanderbilt University M.A. in Philosophy - Vanderbilt University M.A. in Philosophy - University of Missouri M.S.E. in Math Education - Harding University Introducing Our New Faculty Academic Experience Tennessee State University / Vanderbilt University Nashville High-Tech Institute / Lipscomb University University of Missouri / Harding University Universidad Francisco Marroquin / Universidad Del Valle / Colegio Metropolitano Multiple presentations and contributions to scholarly publications Dr.Talavera@gmail.com Honors 1999-2000 recipient of the Burke Award for Teaching Excellence at Vanderbilt University

CRITICAL THINKING: THE VITAL CONNECTION AMONG DEVELOPMENTAL COURSES Math Writing Reading

ASSUMPTION #1 "The goal of instruction should be to allow students to deal sensibly with problems that often involve evidence, quantitative consideration, logical arguments, and uncertainty; without the ability to think critically and independently, citizens are easy prey to dogmatists, flimflam artists, and purveyors of simple solutions to complex problems." American Association for the Advancement of Science, 1989

ASSUMPTION #2 For logic, by perfecting and by sharpening the tools of thought, makes men and women more critical and thus makes less likely their being misled by all the pseudoreasonings to which they are incessantly exposed in various parts of the world today. Alfred Tarski, Introduction to Logic and to the Methodology of Deductive Sciences, 1994

OBJECTIVES: PART I 1. Why is critical thinking the vital connection among developmental courses? 2. What exactly is critical thinking? Writing Math Reading

OBJECTIVES: PART II 3. What is an argument? 4. How do we identify arguments? 5. How do we identify deductive and inductive arguments?

OBJECTIVES: PART III 6. Why is the translation of verbal statements to symbolic statements (and symbolic statements back to verbal statements) a key aspect of critical thinking in developmental mathematics, reading, and writing? Example: If I am not hungry, then I am tired. translates to ~H T.

OBJECTIVES: PART IV 7. How do we analyze reasoning and evaluate that reasoning according to the intellectual standards of (i) validity and soundness for deductive arguments, and (ii) strength and cogency for inductive arguments?

PROPOSAL: To improve the theory and practice of developmental education at all levels by highlighting the common ground of developmental courses: critical thinking. 1) All cats have four legs. 2) I have four legs. ----------------------------- 3) Thus, I am a cat.

SOME OBSERVATIONS Developmental students have problems recognizing premises and conclusions within passages. This may reveal the logical connections and arguments in reading. Developmental students have problems recognizing the logical connections and arguments. This may clarify meaning in reading, writing, and mathematics. Developmental students have problems choosing statements carefully and making proper inferences. This is imperative for justifying a thesis in expository writing or a solution in a math problem. Developmental students have problems showing why something is the case. This is important in connecting -the-dots (evaluating the reasoning and information involved ) and developing critical thinking skills.

OBJECTIVES: PART I 1. Why is critical thinking the vital connection among developmental courses? 2. What exactly is critical thinking? Writing Math Reading

Why is critical thinking the vital connection among developmental courses? Every developmental course has its logical structure and so can be understood through logic reasoning, thinking, argument, or proof. enables learners to face challenges within and across subjects by learning how to formulate and evaluate arguments.

Moreover also provides a solid foundation for overcoming obstacles to reliable reasoning and clear thinking. Accordingly, the goal of teaching is to create a context in which students can think.

What exactly is critical thinking? thinking is a purposeful mental activity that takes something apart, via analysis, and evaluates it on the basis of an intellectual standard (Mayfield). In this discussion that something is an argument.

OBJECTIVES: PART II 3. What is an argument? 4. How do we identify arguments? 5. How do we identify deductive and inductive arguments?

What is an argument? Logic is the study of arguments. An argument is a sequence of statements (claims): a set of premises and a conclusion. A statement (claim) is a declarative sentence that is either true or false, but not both.

1) All cats have four legs. 2) I have four legs. ----------------------------- 3) Thus, I am a cat. The conclusion is the statement that one is trying to establish by offering the argument. Premises are also statements, but are intended to prove or at least provide some evidence for the conclusion.

How do we identify arguments? for Inference indicators: 1. Premise Indicators: Words used for giving reasons: For, Since, Because, Assuming that, Seeing that, Granted that, This is true because, The reason is that, In view of the fact that, etc. 2. Conclusion indicators: Words used for adding up consequences: So, Thus, Therefore, Hence, Then, Accordingly, Consequently, This being so, It follows that, etc. (Nolt).

for Inference indicators (example) Students who don t come to class are thus depriving themselves of the learning process. This is true because coming to class is an essential part of learning the subject matter. 1) Coming to class is an essential part of learning the subject matter. ------------------------------------- 2) Thus, students who don t come to class are depriving themselves of the learning process.

How do we identify deductive and inductive arguments? Look for how the premises logically support the conclusion: 1. In deductive arguments, the premises are intended to prove the conclusion and so the conclusion follows with certainty. 2. In inductive arguments, the premises are intended to provide some (strong or weak) evidence for the conclusion and so the conclusion follows with some uncertainty.

DEDUCTION: Look for how the premises logically support the conclusion (example) Deductive Argument: 1) x is greater than y. 2) y is greater than z. --------------------------------- 3) Thus, x is greater than z. (Where x, y, and z are real numbers) The conclusion follows with certainty because if each premise used to demonstrate the conclusion is true, then the conclusion also must be true. So, truth is preserved. We will call arguments that satisfy this condition, VALID arguments.

INDUCTION: Look for how the premises logically support the conclusion (example) Inductive Argument: 1) 90% of smokers get lung cancer. 2) John is a smoker. ------------------------------- 3) Thus, John will probably get lung cancer. The conclusion follows with some uncertainty because even if the premises were true, the conclusion could still be false (some people smoke all their lives and don t get the disease). So, truth may not be preserved.

Unlike the previous Inductive Argument that only called for few premises, in the example below we have n premises (as many as you want to list). 1) Smoking gives person #1 lung cancer. 2) Smoking gives person #2 lung cancer. 3) Smoking gives person #3 lung cancer. i) Etc. n) Smoking gives person #n lung cancer. ------------------------------------------- n+1) Thus, smoking probably causes lung cancer in all people. The conclusion follows with some uncertainty because even if each premise of the sequence of statements used to demonstrate the conclusion were true, the conclusion could still be false. So, truth may not be preserved. But, as the observed number of cases of people who smoke and get lung cancer increases, the argument gets stronger; as the observed number of cases decreases, the argument gets weaker.

OBJECTIVES: PART III 6. Why is the translation of verbal statements to symbolic statements (and symbolic statements back to verbal statements) a key aspect of critical thinking in developmental mathematics, reading, and writing? Example: If I am not hungry, then I am tired. translates to ~H T.

Why is translation a key aspect of critical thinking? Translation of a verbal statement to a symbolic statement helps one to examine the structure of the declarative sentence (analysis) to reveal logical connections. And, recognizing logical connections may clarify meaning in reading, writing, and mathematics.

Moreover Translation of verbal statements to symbolic statements helps one to examine the structure of an argument (a sequence of statements) in detail (analysis). Symbolizing this structure can show how premises and a conclusion are related in valid, or invalid, argument forms (evaluation).

To symbolize a statement we need: A statement indicator, an uppercase letter, used to symbolize a simple statement (e.g., H used to indicate "I am hungry ). A connective indicator (e.g., & used to indicate and )used with statement indicators to symbolize a complex statement. Connectives are words like AND, OR, NOT, and IF-THEN.

For instance, given the following conditions: Let the statement indicator H substitute I am hungry. Let the statement indicator T substitute I am tired. Let connective indicator & substitute the connective AND. Let connective indicator v substitute the connective OR. Let connective indicator ~ substitute the connective NOT. Let connective indicator substitute the connective IF-THEN.

Practice translating the following statements: 1. I am hungry. ANSWER: H 2. I am not hungry. ANSWER: ~H 3. I am both hungry and tired. ANSWER: H & T 4. I am hungry or I am tired. ANSWER: H v T 5. If I am not hungry, then I am tired. ANSWER: ~H T 6. ~ T ~ H ANSWER: If I am not tired, then I am not hungry.

Practice translating the following arguments: EXERCISE #1: 1) If I am hungry, then I am tired. 2) I am hungry. -------------------------- 3) Thus, I am tired. Note: Use lower case letters when designating the basic form of the valid deduction. ANSWER: 1) H T. 2) H. --------------- 3) Thus, T. Modus Ponens: 1) If p, then q. 2) p. ------------------- 3) Thus, q.

EXERCISE #2: 1) If I am hungry, then I am tired. 2) I am not tired. ------------------------ 3) Thus, I am not hungry. Note: Use lower case letters when designating the basic form of the valid deduction. ANSWER: 1) H T. 2) ~ T. ----------------- 3) Thus, ~ H. Modus Tollens: 1) If p, then q. 2) Not q. ------------------- 3) Thus, not p.

OBJECTIVES: PART IV 7. How do we analyze reasoning and evaluate that reasoning according to the intellectual standards of (i) validity and soundness for deductive arguments, and (ii) strength and cogency for inductive arguments?

ANALYSIS: Examine the structure of the argument in detail and symbolize this structure or component parts. Consider the following deductive argument. 1) All people grow old. 2) Mary is a person. ---------------------------- 3) Thus, Mary grows old.

The key to translating All people grow old in the argument above is to interpret the universal statement as the conditional statement If it is a person, then it grows old (for every member of its subject class: people). Again, let the connective indicator substitute the connective IF-THEN. Interpreting P (for it is a person) and O (for it grows old) as statement indicators, If P, then O is finally translated as P O. The symbolized argument is as follows. 1) P O 2) P --------------- 3) Thus, O

EVALUATION: Is the deductive argument valid? Is it sound (= valid + true premises)? This argument about people growing old is a valid deductive argument because it has the following underlying valid argument form we studied. Modus Ponens: 1) If p, then q. 2) p. ------------------- 3) Thus, q. Moreover, it is also a sound deductive argument because it has true premises.

Consider the following deductive argument. 1) All cats have four legs. 2) I have four legs. ----------------------------- 3) Thus, I am a cat.

ANALYSIS: Examine the structure of the argument in detail. The key to translating All cats have four legs in the argument above is to interpret the universal statement as the conditional statement If it is a cat, then it has four legs (for every member of its subject class: cats).

The argument depicted by the cartoon becomes 1) If it is a cat, then it has four legs. (Assume this is a true premise) 2) It has four legs. (Assume this is a true premise) ------------------------------------------------------------------------ 3) Thus, it is a cat. (A false conclusion) What is wrong with this argument?

EVALUATION: Is the deductive argument valid? Is it sound (= valid + true premises)? The little dog is guilty of using his reasoning and the information involved to derive something false from something true. Since this argument has true premises and a false conclusion, it is an invalid deductive argument. Symbolized, the argument reveals its invalid form.

ANALYSIS: Symbolize the structure or component parts. Again, let the connective indicator substitute the connective IF-THEN. Interpreting C (for it is a cat) and F (for it has four legs) as statement indicators, If C, then F is finally translated as C F. The symbolized argument is as follows. 1) C F 2) F --------------- 3) Thus, C

Generally speaking, arguments that share the same INVALID deductive form below commit the fallacy of AFFIRMING THE CONSEQUENT. Affirming the Consequent: 1) p q 2) q ------------- 3) Thus, p 1) C F 1) S G 2) F 2) G --------------- --------------- 3) Thus, C 3) Thus, S Interpret S (for I study) and G (for I get good grades) as statement indicators above.

ANALYSIS: Consider the following inductive argument. 1) Legalized marijuana eliminates criminal profiteering. 2) Criminal profiteering is bad. 3) Legalized marijuana eliminates many health dangers by controlling quality. 4) Eliminating health dangers is good. 5) Legalized marijuana permits its medical use. 6) The medical use of marijuana is good. ---------------------------------------------------------------------- 7) Thus, marijuana should be legalized.

EVALUATION: Is the inductive argument strong? Is it cogent (= strong + true premises)? The conclusion that marijuana should be legalized follows with some uncertainty because even if each premise of the sequence of statements used to demonstrate the conclusion were true, the conclusion could still be false. But, as the number of relevant reasons/premises about the legality of marijuana increases, the argument gets stronger; as the number decreases, the argument above for the conclusion that marijuana should be legalized gets weaker. Cogency here would require a strong argument with true premises.

Consider the following math problem found in a basic Algebra course: Given that two more than a number is ten, find the number (i.e., find X). Analysis, here, requires that we translate an open statement to its corresponding open algebraic expression. Two more than a number is ten translates to X + 2 = 10. Accordingly, given that X + 2 = 10, we must show or prove what X is (Let X be a real number).

We can use open statements as if they were statements, given additional information. For instance, the open statement X + 2 = 10 may simply be given as true. Further analysis requires that we put the argument in natural order (put the premises first and draw the conclusion at the end): 1) X + 2 = 10....Given. 2) (X + 2) 2 = (10) 2. Go to Premise#1, Subtract 2. ------------------------------------------------------------------------------ 3) Therefore, X = 8.Go to Premise#2, Simplify.

EVALUATION: Is the deductive argument valid? Is it sound (= valid + true premises)? Evaluating this algebraic argument requires that we ask: Is this deductive argument valid? Is it the case that if each premise of the sequence of statements used to demonstrate the conclusion is true, then its conclusion cannot be false? Is it the case that the conclusion also must be true, so, truth is preserved?

The open statement X + 2 = 10 is true (we know that because it was Given) and (X + 2) 2 = (10) 2 must also true (because Premise#1 is given to us as true and by subtracting the same amount from both sides of the equation we don t change the equality). On the basis of this sequence of statements, then, the conclusion X = 8 cannot be false. The conclusion that X = 8 must also be true. So, the deductive argument is valid.

So if the critical thinker asks Why is the solution the number eight?, then one may respond on the basis of logical reasoning because Given that X + 2 = 10, we still maintain the equality by subtracting the same amount from both sides of the equation so that (X + 2) 2 = (10) 2. And by simplifying, we conclude that X = 8.

This elementary example, therefore, asks students to evaluate the reasoning and information involved in order to solve the problem (find X). And by so doing, it accentuates the crucial difference between showing why the solution is the case and showing how the solution is the case. A how question asks how do you do the problem? But, the aim of critical thinking is not to have the learner ask the teacher to merely show the class how to solve the problem to just show the class how to plug-in the values to solve for instances (i.e., examples) of the problem. Showing why something is the case allows the student to connect-the-dots (evaluate the reasoning and information involved) and develop critical thinking skills. And in this sense, there certainly is more to teaching than simply giving-out instructions or recipes that show how to do a problem.

CONCLUSION: Recognizing premises and conclusions within passages may reveal the logical connections and arguments in reading. Recognizing the logical connections and arguments may clarify meaning in reading, writing, and math. Choosing statements carefully and making proper inferences is imperative for justifying a thesis in expository writing or a solution in a math problem. Showing why something is the case allows the student to connect-thedots (evaluate the reasoning and information involved) and develop critical thinking skills.

WHAT NEXT? Caste, N. J., & Kiersky, J. H. (1995). critically: Techniques for logical reasoning (p. 264). St. Paul, MN: West Publishing Co. Epstein, R. L. & Kernberger, C. (2006). The Pocket guide to critical thinking. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth. Mayfield, M. (2001). for yourself: Developing critical thinking skills through reading and writing (pp. 4-6). USA: Thomson Learning, Inc.

WHAT NEXT? Nolt, J., & Rohatyn, D. (1988). Schaum s outline of theory and problems of logic (p. 3). New York, NY: McGraw-Hill, Inc. Tarski, A. (1994 ). Introduction to logic and to the methodology of deductive sciences. New York, NY: Oxford University Press, Inc. Weston, A. (2009). A rulebook for arguments. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Co., Inc.