FEUERBACH AND THE RISE OF DIALECTICAL ATHEISM

Similar documents
Resolutio of Idealism into Atheism in Fichte

Spinoza: Does Thought Determine Reality? Thomistic Studies Week 2018 St. Isaac Jogues Novitiate Michael Scott, Nov

Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things:

Cf. Ed. Eugene, Kamenka, Introduction, The Portable Karl Marx, (Penguin Books: The Viking Portable Library, 1983). 4

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

1/8. Descartes 3: Proofs of the Existence of God

Ludwig Feuerbach The Essence of Christianity (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 10/23/13 9:10 AM. Section III: How do I know? Reading III.

Atheism, the Offspring of Deism in Berkeley. philosophical system in order to prevent the advancements of Atheism and undercut Materialism.

1/12. The A Paralogisms

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

Thursday, November 30, 17. Hegel s Idealism

Chapter 24. Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel: The Concepts of Being, Non-being and Becoming

Kant and his Successors

Tuesday, November 11, Hegel s Idealism

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

Mind and Body. Is mental really material?"

A Philosophical Study of Nonmetaphysical Approach towards Human Existence

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

SPINOZA, SUBSTANCE, AND SUBJECTIVITY IN HEGEL S LECTURES ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION

MEDITATIONS ON THE FIRST PHILOSOPHY: THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

1/5. The Critique of Theology

A Critique of the Notion of Atheism According to Cornelio Fabro

Hume on Ideas, Impressions, and Knowledge

FOLLOWING CHRIST IN THE WORLD

Chapter 25. Hegel s Absolute Idealism and the Phenomenology of Spirit

The Challenge of God. Julia Grubich

Creation & necessity

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

Descartes Theory of Contingency 1 Chris Gousmett

Reid Against Skepticism

Descartes: A Guide for the Perplexed

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to

Logical Mistakes, Logical Aliens, and the Laws of Kant's Pure General Logic Chicago February 21 st 2018 Tyke Nunez

Review of Ronald Dworkin s Religion without God. Mark Satta Ph.D. student, Purdue University

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

The Cosmological Argument: A Defense

Anthony P. Andres. The Place of Conversion in Aristotelian Logic. Anthony P. Andres

Chapter 16 George Berkeley s Immaterialism and Subjective Idealism

The Other Half of Hegel s Halfwayness: A response to Dr. Morelli s Meeting Hegel Halfway. Ben Suriano

Lecture 18: Rationalism

Marx: Marx: Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts in Karl Marx: Selected Writings, L. Simon, ed. Indianapolis: Hackett.

It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition:

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

Do you have a self? Who (what) are you? PHL 221, York College Revised, Spring 2014

THE FICHTEAN IDEA OF THE SCIENCE OF KNOWLEDGE. by Jean Hyppolite*

Teleological: telos ( end, goal ) What is the telos of human action? What s wrong with living for pleasure? For power and public reputation?

The Holy Trinity. Part 1

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between

BENEDIKT PAUL GÖCKE. Ruhr-Universität Bochum

Critique of Cosmological Argument

From the fact that I cannot think of God except as existing, it follows that existence is inseparable from God, and hence that he really exists.

CATHOLIC UNIVERSITY OF AMERICA SCHOOL OF PHILOSOPHY FOUNDATIONS OF J. G. FICHTE S 1794 WISSENSCHAFTSLEHRE: A CRITICAL EXPOSITION OF HIS STARTING POINT

God and Creation, Job 38:1-15

Qué es la filosofía? What is philosophy? Philosophy

d) The (first) debate about Pantheism

PHIL 4242 German Idealism 德意志觀念論 Fall 2016 Professor Gregory S. Moss

Study on the Essence of Marx s Political Philosophy in the View of Materialism

Nagel, Naturalism and Theism. Todd Moody. (Saint Joseph s University, Philadelphia)

William Hasker s discussion of the Thomistic doctrine of the soul

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

STAR-CROSSED LOVERS: THE POLITICS & PHILOSOPHY OF MODERN FREEDOM

Some Notes Toward a Genealogy of Existential Philosophy Robert Burch

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Affirmative Dialectics: from Logic to Anthropology

The purpose of philosophy and Karl Marx s Towards a Critique of Hegel s philosophy of right: Introduction

1/9. Leibniz on Descartes Principles

Philosophy in Review XXXIII (2013), no. 5

Reviewed by Colin Marshall, University of Washington

Introduction to Philosophy

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Definitions of Gods of Descartes and Locke

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 3

Tuesday, September 2, Idealism

Why Feuerbach Is both Classic and Modern

Common sense dictates that we can know external reality exists and that it is generally correctly perceived via our five senses

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

THE CRISIS OF THE SCmNCES AS EXPRESSION OF THE RADICAL LIFE-CRISIS OF EUROPEAN HUMANITY

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Contemporary Theology II: From Theology of Hope to Postmodernism. Introduction: Review and Preview. ST507 LESSON 01 of 24

The Ground Upon Which We Stand

Quaerens Deum: The Liberty Undergraduate Journal for Philosophy of Religion

EUTHYPHRO, GOD S NATURE, AND THE QUESTION OF DIVINE ATTRIBUTES. An Analysis of the Very Complicated Doctrine of Divine Simplicity.

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

On the Object of Philosophy: from Being to Reality

Religious Studies. Name: Institution: Course: Date:

Building Systematic Theology

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair


Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

COPLESTON: Quite so, but I regard the metaphysical argument as probative, but there we differ.

DALLAS BAPTIST UNIVERSITY THE ILLOGIC OF FAITH: FEAR AND TREMBLING IN LIGHT OF MODERNISM SUBMITTED TO THE GENTLE READER FOR SPRING CONFERENCE

Chapter 1 Emergence of being

1/10. Descartes and Spinoza on the Laws of Nature

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

Wittgenstein s The First Person and Two-Dimensional Semantics

Transcription:

THOMISTIC WEEK 2018 MODERN ATHEISM FEUERBACH AND THE RISE OF DIALECTICAL ATHEISM Sem. Andy Barth The philosophers who we have studied so far were smart men, and as the centuries progressed, the theological implications of the Cartesian cogito only became clearer to them. Yet so far, none have been willing to offer us a straightforward denial of the existence of God. They ve left plenty of hints tucked away in their tomes of philosophic prose, but the religious propriety that held on until the middle of the 19 th century kept them tiptoeing around the subject. Popular piety was waning, though; everyone in the German idealistic schools watched as Fichte got booted out of the University of Jena for his openly atheistic take on the concept of a personal God, 1 but this only added force to a gigantic shift that stirred beneath Germany s intellectual soil. The youth felt it, especially the members of the Young Hegelians. This left-wing school was home to a number of revolutionary philosophers, and one of their earliest members was named Ludwig Feuerbach. One fine day, having recently made some comments that were similarly Fichtean in their career-ruining consequences, and now in the twilight of his academic aspirations, he decided to be very candid. He pointed towards the crumbling edifice of German idealist Christianity and wrote, Hey, that s actually atheism. In 1841, he published The Essence of Christianity, in which he boldly penned what the idealists before him had only whispered: that man is the ultimate principle and determinant of man, and that anything beyond the scope of his consciousness cannot exist. In his own words: The divine being is nothing else than the human being, or, rather, the human nature purified, freed from the limits of the individual man, made objective. 2 1 Ameriks, Karl. The Cambridge Companion to German Idealism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006. p. 259 2 Fabro, Cornelio. God in exile ; modern atheism. A study of the internal dynamic of modern atheism, from its roots in the Cartesian cogito to the present day. N.Y.: Newman, 1968. Part 5, p. 662

Out of the woodwork came a bunch of philosophers and theologians who had been laying low up till then. German theologian David Strauss called the book the truth of our time. 3 It freed an entire generation of skeptical minds from Georg Hegel s troublesome metaphysics, and blazed the trail as atheism marched into a new era of intellectual legitimacy. In this paper I ll talk about Feuerbach s notion of being and the concept of man that flows from this. That will lead into his interpretation of the Christian Gospel, in which theology becomes anthropology. Finally, we ll look briefly at Cornelio Fabro s critique of this system in light of the good old cogito. I will do my best to stay within these boundaries; Dr. Joseph Papa will be delving a lot a deeper into some aspects of Feuerbach on Friday. Background: Hegel Feuerbach studied under Hegel for two years in Berlin, and he builds his philosophy upon Hegelian foundations. It was unthinkable to begin elsewhere; at the time everyone thought Hegel s work was the best systematic philosophy out there. Simultaneously, Feuerbach s work is also a radical criticism of the Hegelian system, and his main concern is to get out of the abstract principles of idealism and back to the solid ground of material reality. This tension between reliance upon and critique of Hegel is mirrored in the history surrounding his death. When Hegel died in 1831, German philosophy divided into two distinct schools: the old conservative Hegelians, and the Young Hegelians who we ve already mentioned. The latter believed that a tremendous upheaval was brewing beneath Prussian Germany s changing social and economic climate, and saw in Hegel s philosophy a tool to help effect that social change. Hegel himself left a lot of room for the augmentation of his system, so they felt vindicated in their unorthodox shift towards materialism. 4 3 Harvey, Van A. Feuerbach and the Interpretation of Religion. Cambridge Univ. Press, 2007. p. 26 4 Stepelevich, Lawrence S. The young Hegelians: an anthology. Amherst, NY: Humanity Books, 1999. p. ix

Let s quickly review Hegel s three step process of the dialectic which Brother Cesar covered. In step one, we start with the Spiritual Idea, which really is a transcendent being. We proceed to step two as this Idea projects itself into the material realm and knows itself through mankind s collective thought, and we complete step three when it proceeds back into the spiritual realm with newly gleaned self-knowledge. Essentially, he goes from abstract Idea to concrete reality, back to abstract Idea. Feuerbach s Interpretation Feuerbach agrees with the triune structure of Hegel s dialectic, but he differs on one fundamental point: for Hegel, being is based in the spiritual thought of the Idea, and for Feuerbach, being is based squarely and completely in spatio-temporal reality, in matter. 5 Thus, Feuerbach aims to derive the materialistic version of the three step dialectic, and this turns out to be simple: he just 5 Copleston, Frederick C. A History of Philosophy. Vol. 7. New York: Image Books/Doubleday, 1994. p. 295

switches Hegel s subject and object. Man and the Idea-God change places. As straightforward as this sounds, he manages to compose a wonderfully puzzling sentence about it: Man this is the mystery of religion projects his being into objectivity, and then again makes himself an object to this projected image of himself thus converted into a subject; he thinks of himself as an object to himself, but as the object of an object, of another being than himself. 6 Lots of objects being objectified by other objects there. But to put it simply, let s start with a guy. He is capable of consciously understanding himself. But how? Precisely by objectifying himself; by using his mind to create an image of himself that he can know. Then he makes this error where, as 6 Harvey, Van A. Feuerbach and the Interpretation of Religion. Cambridge Univ. Press, 2007. p. 27

he makes the mental connection of himself to that image, he accidentally attributes an independent existence to it, as if it were outside his mind. Then he starts worshiping it. Whoops. So that flips Hegel on his head, (Feuerbach calls it setting Hegel on his feet, ) yet stays true to the three step dialectic. We still begin with a dissatisfied self-consciousness, and it still has to overcome its own self-alienating projection in order to be satisfied. Alienation happens when we don t realize our projection is actually dependent upon us for its existence, and the freedom obtained by realizing this is basically just being at home with ourselves. 7 But hey, can t we just not project a self image and avoid all the mess? Feuerbach and the idealists both say no, because we can only know ourselves through another; experiencing the other is the only way to climb out of ignorance of self, and human beings have to do this, they can t help it. Feuerbach s Anthropology So that s the situation of humankind, according to Feuerbach. But it leaves us wondering about that moment where we gum everything up and invent God. The process begins; I m pondering this projection of myself seminarian clerics I like sushi BAM! Next minute I m building a temple to some primitive sun god. How does that happen? Well first, we have to understand some of Feuerbach s anthropology. What does he think man is? For Feuerbach, man is an animal that is unique from all other animals because he can do science. When man does science, he makes statements that apply to entire species of things, not just individuals, and this implies that man can abstract the universal essences of things. Great so far, St. Thomas is nodding his head. Wait a minute, though, doesn t that intellectual power require a nonmaterial, spiritual principle? That s a problem for Feuerbach because he is a materialist, so man s potency to know abstract universals cannot flow from a soul. Instead, Feuerbach has to differentiate 7 Ameriks, Karl. The Cambridge Companion to German Idealism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006. p. 260

essences from particular finite things by calling them infinite; he can t assign immaterial or spiritual properties to them. As far as I can tell, infinite for Feuerbach simply means unlimited and unending in number. So here we are: man is a material being that has a unique level of consciousness with which he can know infinite essences. Strauss Contribution Next question: where does this potency come from? Feuerbach holds that man has the power to know infinite essences because his being has as its object its own species. 8 This principle reads more simply that his sentence about objects being objectified, but it s a lot more difficult to translate directly; at first it looks like a non sequitur. Actually, this idea is not original to Feuerbach; he takes it from David Strauss s Das Leben Jesu. This Life of Christ is a pretty good example of the historical critique of the scriptures that was in full swing in Germany at that time. Due to the resurgence of Spinozan pantheism as Hegel s work became more widespread, which we mentioned yesterday, the main body of German idealists had been encouraging a dismantling of orthodox understanding of scripture, and detachment from traditional and literal meaning in the Christian Gospels. This process only accelerated after Hegel s death, and Strauss had developed one of the main critical approaches of the time. In his Leben Jesu, he holds that Christ is a mythical image that represents the relationship of the individual to humanity as a whole. Strauss affirms that each man is capable of receiving the religious concept of the God-man, the unity of the divine nature and human nature in one being. But he says the Church s teaching that Jesus Christ is the only instance of this unity that will ever exist is false. In fact, the idea that this unity could ever be present in a single individual is absurd; rather, our awareness of this concept points to a reality that can only be actualized on the level of our species understood as a united whole. In Strauss s own words: 8 Fabro, Cornelio. God in exile ; modern atheism. A study of the internal dynamic of modern atheism, from its roots in the Cartesian cogito to the present day. N.Y.: Newman, 1968. Part 5, p. 658

Will not the idea of the unity of the divine and human natures necessarily be a real idea in an infinitely more lofty sense if I comprehend the whole of humanity in its actualization rather than singling out individuals as such?... If you try to think of the properties and functions which Church teaching attributes to Christ as being present in one individual, a God-Man, then you are faced with a contradiction. But there is no such difficulty if instead you think of them as present in the Idea of the Species. 9 Essentially, Strauss argues that the fact that each individual man can be cognizant of a perfect, universal being, but is clearly a particular and limited being himself, is the clue to understanding what man really is: he is a member of a species, all of whose members are, by their very essence, oriented toward the whole species, not their individual persons. Our preoccupation with God, with his attributes of perfect simplicity and unity, points to this. Thus, the proper way to conceive of man is as a species, not as an individual, because here, together, the combined perfections of the human race actually achieve the same unity and fullness as the transcendental perfections that compose our image of God. Feuerbach calls this our species being, and agrees with Strauss that this being is the essentially true manifestation of man, while the individual man, in his mortality and ephemeral nature, is hardly a being at all. It is here that we can really start to touch upon the immanent bent within Feuerbach s development of man; the primacy he puts on the mind, and his relegation of the individual to the status of a disposable sensory organ. At the same time, in light of the species being, we can truly say that Man is God, or, more correctly, God is Man; there is no God. Feuerbach comments on the process of arriving at this conclusion with uncharacteristic simplicity: " 'Pantheism' is the necessary consequence of theology (or theism) it is consistent and consequential theology; 'atheism' is the necessary consequence of 'pantheism'-it is consistent and consequential 'pantheism. 10 9 D. F. Strauss, Das Leben Jesu, Vol. II (Tübingen, 1836), pp. 734 (Cited in C. Fabro, God in exile ; modern atheism. A study of the internal dynamic of modern atheism, from its roots in the Cartesian cogito to the present day. N.Y.: Newman, 1968. Part 5, p. 655) 10 Fabro, Cornelio. God in exile ; modern atheism. A study of the internal dynamic of modern atheism, from its roots in the Cartesian cogito to the present day. N.Y.: Newman, 1968. Part 5, p. 657

Consciousness as an Infinite Being Feuerbach goes to great lengths to express the implications of a consciousness that knows essences, and is essentially ordered towards its own unified species. The main consequence of this is that our individual consciousness becomes infinite in the same way that species being is infinite. He extrapolates this with a syllogism that basically looks like this: -Man is conscious of his own essence. His own essence is infinite. >Ergo, man s consciousness is infinite. Feuerbach holds, as Hegel does, that consciousness in the strict and proper sense and consciousness of the Infinite are inseparable and that consciousness is essentially infinite and allembracing in nature. 11 Because of this, Religion arises as "consciousness of the infinite" (Bewusstsein des Unendlichen), and since this consciousness is nothing more than self-consciousness, religion is the consciousness that man has of himself. 12 So at this point we understand why man is conscious of the concept of an infinite being, and why he is attracted to it. It is himself, and he is his own object. But we re still not sure why he makes the mistake of giving this infinite being existence outside of the collective mind of man, and develops religion out of it. Feelings Feuerbach says this happens because of our feelings. Back down on the depressing level of individual men, we experience a feeling of dependence upon the material realm, since we actually do depend on it in order to not starve and do other important corporeal things. Feuerbach traces the rise of nature religions and the deification of material phenomena throughout our human history, and says that the divine essence which manifests itself in Nature is nothing else but Nature which reveals and manifests itself to man and imposes 11 Ibid. p. 659 12 Ibid.

itself on him as a divine being. 13 Once we infuse this with the infinitude which flows from our essence, we ve got God, and we re all set for some serious self-alienation. The Feuerbach Code So Feuerbach has his six-shooters in his hands. He s got his species being, and an explanation of how man mistakenly creates God by casting his own essence on reality. Now he s ready to put serious holes in Christianity. One of the first Christian mysteries that he decodes is the concept of the Divine Trinity. His rationale is a great example of how he s able to flex the ambiguity of the species being. For Feuerbach, our concept of the Triune God is the result of our anthropomorphizing the three main faculties that flow from man s essence. The members of this trio are reason, will, and love. Since they come from man s essence, they don t belong to the individual as a personal principle; and thus the individual cannot control their operation the way we can control our sensory faculties. For example, when we don t want to see something, we can shut our eyes, but try not reasoning for a moment and you ll realize that s impossible. We re always drawing conclusions and making predications, it s inherent to our thinking. So reason, will, and love are an irresistible driving force that acts on us at all times, independent of our individual desires. Feuerbach says that throughout history these powers have exhibited one purpose: to perfect themselves for their own sake. Fabro paraphrases Feuerbach, saying: Love, will reason are powers of the species which dominate and ought to dominate the individual, his passions and his impulses. Hence, he says, we can understand how the object of man is man himself, i.e., his own objective essence; and Feuerbach actually writes "consciousness of the objective is the self-consciousness of man". 14 13 Feuerbach, Ludwig, Friedrich Jodl, and Wilhelm Bolin. Ludwig Feuerbachs sa mtliche Werke. Stuttgart-Bad Canstatt: Frommann, 1960. p. 180 14 Fabro, Cornelio. God in exile ; modern atheism. A study of the internal dynamic of modern atheism, from its roots in the Cartesian cogito to the present day. N.Y.: Newman, 1968. Part 5, p. 659

This answers why Feuerbach and the idealists say man doesn t have a choice in whether he projects a self image or not. Man is more or less possessed by reason, will, and love, so he has to enter the process of the three step dialectic. This is why Feuerbach, in a sense, looks on religion in a positive light; for him it is just one chapter of progress in the grand timeline of man s self-realization. Christianity, as the summit of religious development, is basically just the best series of symbols that we have to date, which expresses the structure of the communal human consciousness of the "species" wherein is actualized the truth of the being of man. 15 We could spend the rest of the day looking at more Feuerbachian interpretations of Christian symbols and myths, but there isn t time. Let s take a look now at what Fabro says about Feuerbach s philosophy. Immanence Taken to its Logical Conclusion Actually, Fabro says that everything that Feuerbach claims about religion is completely true IF the consciousness he refers to from the start is the cogito of Descartes. And it is. Fabro has surprisingly little to say in critique of Feuerbach, probably because they re both essentially in agreement about Descarte s cogito resulting in atheism; they re just on completely opposite ends of the same truth. Fabro says that: [Feuerbach] is therefore significant, not so much for his lapse into sensualism and materialism as rather for his elucidation of the crucial point that, in the wake of the cogito, the being of the world is the limiting horizon for the existent who is man. 16 We can see this quite clearly in a quote where Feuerbach is talking about his own method of anthropology. He says: 15 Ibid. p. 654. 16 Ibid. p. 654. it posits in the "here", i.e., makes present, determined and definite, realized, that divine essence, that divine nature which common theology, out of fear or incomprehension, had posited in the remote beyond." 17

By here, Feuerbach refers to our consciousness, and Present, determined, and definite, realized have an oddly similar ring to Descarte s criteria for knowing truth, which is that the thing be known clearly and distinctly in his mind. The validity of Feuerbach s system, in his opinion, lies in the fact that it bases all speculation inside the locus where knowledge is clearly present: our mind in its act of sense-knowing. From the very start, despite his rejection of Hegel s idealism, he has accepted the even deeper fundamental that truth is determined by the mind. For example, in defending his atheism against the pantheistic idealist Christians of his time, who had effectively brought God down into the world and subjected his will to the laws of nature, as Michael hit on yesterday, he says that The negation of the subject is held to be irreligion, nay atheism; though, not so the negation of the predicates. But that which has no predicates or qualities, has no effect upon me; and that which has no effect upon me has no existence for me. To deny all the qualities of a being is equivalent to denying the being himself. 18 Essentially, he has made the question of God s existence dependent upon the mind that predicates the qualities that make God to be God. And as soon as he has posed the question this way, it becomes empirical for him, since the human mind is only concerned with the reality it can sense, just as Hobbes and Locke had done. Now we reach the same impassable contradiction of trying to prove with our senses a being that, by our very definition, transcends the senses. Unlike the others, who spin their wheels and find elaborate solutions to get around this problem, Feuerbach simply says that s nonsense. At rock bottom, says Feuerbach, this was an error of humans in 17 Feuerbach, Vorläufige Thesen zur Reform der Philosophie, 1843; C. W., ed. Bolin-Jodl, Vol. II (Stuttgart, 1904) (Cited in C. Fabro, God in exile ; modern atheism. A study of the internal dynamic of modern atheism, from its roots in the Cartesian cogito to the present day. N.Y.: Newman, 1968. Part 5, p. 654) 18 Fabro, Cornelio. God in exile ; modern atheism. A study of the internal dynamic of modern atheism, from its roots in the Cartesian cogito to the present day. N.Y.: Newman, 1968. Part 5, p. 663

forming the concept of a being who had in him the essence of sensible being without any of the signs (Zeichen) of that sort of (sensible) being. 19 Feuerbach elucidates how there is no way ever that a modern philosopher who operates according to the Cartesian cogito will ever produce a convincing proof for the existence of God. For if they re trying to conclude from the interior reality of reason a being that is exterior to that reality, while at once holding that the interior reality is the only existent reality, they are entertaining something completely illogical from the start. He happily suggest that the only refuge from complete contradiction once immanentism is accepted is atheism. Conclusion In summary, Ludwig Feuerbach was a materialist atheist who took the dialectic that Hegel had developed, and inverted it into a system that denied all transcendental realities. He used this to develop Strauss s concept of man as a species, not as an individual, and for a large section of the younger German philosophers, closed the debate about God s existence completely. Talking about atheism only makes sense if theism makes sense, but if God and theism turn out to be nonsense syllables, atheism is also devoid of meaning. What is left is man, and Feuerbach put it nicely when he said Man is what he eats. Fabro finishes his analysis of him by saying that Feuerbach claims with good reason, it seems to us that this dissolution or "precipitation" he has effected of the cogito into the sheer presence in act of reality thanks to sensible consciousness that this constitutes the final assignment of modern thought. 20 19 Fabro, Cornelio. God in exile ; modern atheism. A study of the internal dynamic of modern atheism, from its roots in the Cartesian cogito to the present day. N.Y.: Newman, 1968. Part 5, p. 671 20 Ibid. p. 669.

Despite the fact that his primary works are all themed on Christianity, and focus mainly on the interpretation of religious themes, very little of this work is more than a development of what Hegel had already laid down in his Phenomenology of Spirit. Feuerbach s real contribution is that atheism is now a completely legitimate point of departure for philosophers of the future; he has reframed the whole philosophical question to focus on material reality and the various social and political difficulties man finds therein. Freedom is, as we mentioned, that being at home with ourselves, which is to say that it s now up to man to reconcile his own moral difficulties and determine his own ends. Bibliography:

-Fabro, Cornelio. God in exile ; modern atheism. A study of the internal dynamic of modern atheism, from its roots in the Cartesian cogito to the present day. N.Y.: Newman, 1968. Part 5 - Ameriks, Karl. The Cambridge Companion to German Idealism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006. - Harvey, Van A. Feuerbach and the Interpretation of Religion. Cambridge Univ. Press, 2007. - Stepelevich, Lawrence S. The young Hegelians: an anthology. Amherst, NY: Humanity Books, 1999. - Copleston, Frederick C. A History of Philosophy. Vol. 7. New York: Image Books/Doubleday, 1994.