PHI 1700: Global Ethics

Similar documents
Peter Singer, Famine, Affluence, and Morality

Princeton University Press and Wiley are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophy &Public Affairs.

CRITIQUE OF PETER SINGER S NOTION OF MARGINAL UTILITY

24.03: Good Food 2/15/17

How should I live? I should do whatever brings about the most pleasure (or, at least, the most good)

The Experience Machine and Mental State Theories of Wellbeing

1. PETER SINGER. Famine, Affluence, and Morality First published, in Philosophy and Public Affairs 1:3 (.spring 1972):

Suppose... Kant. The Good Will. Kant Three Propositions

No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships

Take Home Exam #2. PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert

World Hunger and Poverty

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

What must I do? Give most of your possessions to the poor

Mill s Utilitarian Theory

FINAL EXAM SHORT-ANSWER QUESTIONS PHILOSOPHY 13 FALL, 2004

Famine, Affluence, Morality. and

Chapter 2 Reasoning about Ethics

Utilitarianism. But what is meant by intrinsically good and instrumentally good?

IS ACT-UTILITARIANISM SELF-DEFEATING?

Ethical Egoism. Ethical Egoism Things You Should Know. Quiz: one sentence each beginning with The claim that

TWO APPROACHES TO INSTRUMENTAL RATIONALITY

B. C. Johnson. General Problem

Equality, Fairness, and Responsibility in an Unequal World

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

24.01: Classics of Western Philosophy

Living High and Letting Die

Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

INTRODUCTORY HANDOUT PHILOSOPHY 13 FALL, 2004 INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY---ETHICS Professor: Richard Arneson. TAs: Eric Campbell and Adam Streed.

The Moral Relevance of the Past (Hanna)

Against Collective Consequentialism

Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 110W Fall 2013 Russell Marcus

"Book Review: FRANKFURT, Harry G. On Inequality. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press, 2015, 102 pp., $14.95 (hbk), ISBN

Chapter 2: Reasoning about ethics

24.02 Moral Problems and the Good Life

PHIL%13:%Ethics;%Fall%2012% David%O.%Brink;%UCSD% Syllabus% Part%I:%Challenges%to%Moral%Theory 1.%Relativism%and%Tolerance.

Autonomous Machines Are Ethical

Correspondence. From Charles Fried Harvard Law School

Criticizing Arguments

WHEN is a moral theory self-defeating? I suggest the following.

Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 110W Spring 2011 Russell Marcus

Deontology, Rationality, and Agent-Centered Restrictions

A CONSEQUENTIALIST RESPONSE TO THE DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Nicholas R. Baker, Lee University THE DEMANDS OF ACT CONSEQUENTIALISM

Kant. Deontological Ethics

Deontological Ethics. Kant. Rules for Kant. Right Action

SATISFICING CONSEQUENTIALISM AND SCALAR CONSEQUENTIALISM

Logic and Thought Experiments. 9th September Carnegie Mellon University. Introduction to Philosophy. Evaluating Arguments. Thought Experiments

The Non-Identity Problem from Reasons and Persons by Derek Parfit (1984)

Adapted from The Academic Essay: A Brief Anatomy, for the Writing Center at Harvard University by Gordon Harvey. Counter-Argument

Lecture 2: What Ethics is Not. Jim Pryor Guidelines on Reading Philosophy Peter Singer What Ethics is Not

Compatibilist Objections to Prepunishment

Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social

Kantian Deontology. A2 Ethics Revision Notes Page 1 of 7. Paul Nicholls 13P Religious Studies

Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1

Hello again. Today we re gonna continue our discussions of Kant s ethics.

(i) Morality is a system; and (ii) It is a system comprised of moral rules and principles.

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

A lonelier contractualism A. J. Julius, UCLA, January

Is It Morally Wrong to Have Children?

The Sinfulness of Humanity

OPEN Moral Luck Abstract:

Rawls, rationality, and responsibility: Why we should not treat our endowments as morally arbitrary

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

Utilitarianism JS Mill: Greatest Happiness Principle

Utilitarianism pp

Reasons to Reject Allowing

Philosophy 110W: Introduction to Philosophy Spring 2011 Class 26 - April 29 Kantian Ethics. Hamilton College Russell Marcus

Animal Disenhancement

Testing Fairmindedness

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

Caring for People at the End of Life

Ethics and Poverty. By Peter Singer

DOES CONSEQUENTIALISM DEMAND TOO MUCH?

Capital Punishment, Restoration and Moral Rightness

Spinoza s Ethics. Ed. Jonathan Bennett Early Modern Texts

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

James Rachels. Ethical Egoism

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

Moral Philosophy : Utilitarianism

Williams The Human Prejudice

Critical Reasoning and Moral theory day 3

Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

WHAT IT MEANS TO ''LOVE ONE ANOTHER''...AND WHY YOUR BROTHER IS NEVER WRONG.

The Harm of Coming into Existence

Comment on Martha Nussbaum s Purified Patriotism

Florida State University Libraries

forthcoming in Res Philosophica, special issue on transformative experiences Transformative Experiences and Reliance on Moral Testimony

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

CLIMBING THE MOUNTAIN SUMMARY CHAPTER 1 REASONS. 1 Practical Reasons

Lecture 12 Deontology. Onora O Neill A Simplified Account of Kant s Ethics

Chapter 2 Normative Theories of Ethics

The free will defense

Phil 114, April 24, 2007 until the end of semester Mill: Individual Liberty Against the Tyranny of the Majority

Bernard Hoose - Proportionalism

Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule

Making Decisions on Behalf of Others: Who or What Do I Select as a Guide? A Dilemma: - My boss. - The shareholders. - Other stakeholders

University of York, UK

MILL. The principle of utility determines the rightness of acts (or rules of action?) by their effect on the total happiness.

Maximalism vs. Omnism about Reasons*

Transcription:

PHI 1700: Global Ethics Session 12 March 17 th, 2016 Nozick, The Experience Machine ; Singer, Famine, Affluence, and Morality

Last class we learned that utilitarians think we should determine what to do using the Greatest Happiness Principle (GHP): Ø actions are right in proportion as they tend to promote happiness,» where happiness = pleasure, and the absence of pain, Ø wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness, clarifying that the pleasure/pain we are measuring is not our own, but that of all the people potentially affected by our action. Ø Some objections we considered: This view uses majority opinion to rank pleasures (and then, inconsistently, also insists that pleasures of reason are always best). Mill s reply: (none) Only focusing on the consequences of an action neglects the moral significance of the motivation for an action. Mill s reply: The agent s motive just isn t morally significant. We can t know in advance what the consequences of a specific action are. Mill s reply: we can know what the consequences of that type of action are, generally speaking. 2

Ø But yet another worry is that a society where everyone s happiness is maximized would not be a morally ideal society. Robert Nozick (1938 2002) demonstrated the problem with weighing happiness too heavily with a famous thought experiment called The Experience Machine. If Mill is right that the best actions promote the most happiness, then someone s moral obligations to us are complete if they can make us as happy as possible. But is being maximally happy what we ought to be aiming for?» Nozick suggests we d actually be dissatisfied if we only focused on maximizing happiness. 3

Nozick proposes the thought experiment as follows: Suppose there were an experience machine that would give you any experience you desired.» Superduper neuropsychologists could stimulate you brain so that you would think and feel you were writing a great novel, or making a friend, or reading an interesting book.» You can pick and choose [your simulated life] from [a] large library or smorgasbord of [desirable] experiences» All the time you would be floating in a tank, with electrodes attached to your brain. Ø Should you plug into this machine for life, preprogramming your life s experiences? The key question this thought experiment raises is What else matters to us, other than how our lives feel from the inside? Nozick proposes that in addition to having certain experiences, we want to do certain things, & not just have the experience of doing them. we want to be a certain way, to be a certain sort of person. We want to feel like we have the potential to be in contact with a deep reality. 4

Nozick suggests that perhaps what we desire is to live ourselves, in contact with reality. Hence, a constraint on utilitarianism might be that: right actions not only fulfill people s desires for pleasure & freedom from pain, but also fulfill people s desires to live their lives authentically & autonomously, i.e., by acting on their own behalf, in accordance with their personal preferences and aspirations.» We will consider the importance of autonomy further next class,» given its centrality to Kantian ethics. 5

Peter Singer (1946 present) proposes that we apply utilitarianism as a solution to global poverty in his famous 1971 essay Famine, Affluence, & Morality. Singer insists that the suffering & death that are occurring [in the developing world] now are not unavoidable it is not beyond the capacity of the richer nations to give enough assistance to reduce any further suffering to very small proportions. Unfortunately, at the individual level, people have not responded to the situation in any significant way. At the government level, no government has given the sort of massive aid that would enable the refugees to survive for more than a few days. Alarmingly, the British government values a supersonic transport [an airplane called Concorde] more than thirty times as highly as it values the lives of the nine million refugees in India in 1971. I shall argue that the way people in relatively affluent countries react to a situation like that in Bengal cannot be justified; Ø indeed, the whole way we look at moral issues needs to be altered, & with it, the way of life that has come to be taken for granted in our society. 6

Singer lays out some assumptions his argument takes for granted: I begin with the assumption that suffering & death from lack of food, shelter, and medical care are bad...most people will agree about this Those who disagree need read no further. My next point is this: if it is in our power to prevent something bad from happening, without thereby sacrificing anything of comparable moral importance, we ought, morally, to do it. By without sacrificing anything of comparable moral importance I mean without causing anything else comparably bad to happen, or doing something that is wrong in itself, or failing to promote some moral good, comparable in significance to the bad thing that we can prevent. This principle seems almost as uncontroversial as the last one. It requires us only to prevent what is bad, and not to promote what is good, Ø An application of this principle would be as follows: if I am walking past a shallow pond and see a child drowning in it, I ought to wade in and pull the child out. This will mean getting my clothes muddy, but this is insignificant, while the death of the child would presumably be a very bad thing. (231) 7

The uncontroversial appearance of the principle just stated that we morally ought to to prevent a bad outcome, if it doesn t require a comparable moral sacrifice is deceptive, Singer explains. Ø If it were acted upon our lives, our society, and our world would be fundamentally changed. For the principle takes no account of proximity or distance. It makes no moral difference whether the person I help is a neighbor s child ten yards away from me or a Bengali whose name I shall never know, ten thousand miles away. The fact that a person is physically near to us, so that we have personal contact with him, may make it more likely that we shall assist him,» but this does not show that we ought to help him rather than another who happens to be further away. If we accept any principle of impartiality, universalizability, equality, or whatever,» we cannot discriminate against someone merely because he is far away from us (231-2) 8

Admittedly, Singer notes, it is possible that we are in a better position to judge what needs to be done to help a person near to us than one far away, and perhaps also to provide the assistance we judge to be necessary. If this were the case, it would be a reason for helping those near to us first. [But] Unfortunately for those who like to keep their moral responsibilities limited, instant communication & swift transportation have changed the situation. Ø Singer is suggesting that globalization and advances in technology mean that today, it is no more difficult to help someone far away than it is to help someone nearby. There would seem, therefore, to be no possible justification for discriminating on geographical grounds. (232) 9

Another reason why Singer thinks his proposed moral principle would transform our world: Ø the principle makes no distinction between [a] cases I which I am the only person who could possibly do anything & [b] cases in which I am just one among millions in the same position. I admit that there is a psychological difference between the cases; one feels less guilty about doing nothing if one can point to others, similarly placed, who have also done nothing. But this can make no real difference to our moral obligations. Should I consider that I am less obliged to pull the drowning child out of the pond if on looking around I see other people, no further away than I am, who have also noticed to child but are doing nothing?» One only has to ask this question to see the absurdity of the view that [the number of people capable of helping] lessen[s] obligation.» It is a view that is an ideal excuse for inactivity; unfortunately, most of the major evils poverty, overpopulation, pollution are problems in which everyone is almost equally involved. 10

Singer notes that The view [held by his opponents] that numbers do make a difference can be made plausible if stated in this way: 1) If everyone in circumstances like mine gave $5 to the Bengal Relief Fund, there would be enough to provide food, shelter, and medical care for the refugees; 2) There is not reason why I should give more than anyone else in the same circumstances as I am 3) Therefore I have no moral obligation to give more than $5. But Singer objects that this argument is flawed: it is based on a hypothetical premise, [but] the conclusion is not stated hypothetically. The argument would be sound if the conclusion were: 3) If everyone in circumstances like mine were to give $5, I would have no moral obligation to give more than $5. If the conclusion were so stated it would be obvious that the argument has no bearing on a situation in which [everyone does not give $5]. This, of course, is the actual situation not everyone in circumstances like mine will give $5. So there will not be enough to provide the needed food, shelter, and medical care.» Therefore by giving more than $5 I will prevent more suffering than I would if I gave just $5, and thus one is morally obligated to do so. (233) 11

Singer remarks that an apparent consequence of his arguments is that I and everyone else in similar circumstances ought to give as much as possible, that is, at least up to the point at which by giving more one would begin to cause serious suffering for oneself and one s dependents If everyone does this, however, there will be more than can be used for the benefit of the refugees, and some of the sacrifice will have been unnecessary. Thus, if everyone does what he ought to do, the result will not be as good as it would be if everyone did a little less than he ought to do, or if only some do all that they ought to do. He clarifies that this apparent consequence rests on a misunderstanding: those giving after it has become known that many others are giving and those giving before are not in the same circumstances, and thus their obligations to give differ from one another. The outcome where people give more than is necessary would only arise if [people] think they are giving when others are not, but in fact they are giving when others are which is a highly unlikely scenario. Ø The result of everyone doing what he really ought to do cannot be worse than the result of everyone doing less than he ought to do. (234) 12

According to Singer, the principle (that if it is in our power to prevent something very bad from happening, without thereby sacrificing anything else morally significant, we ought, morally, to do it) dissolves the traditional distinction between duty & charity, or at least suggests that these categories ought to be redefined. Ø Because giving money is regarded as an act of charity [as opposed to the fulfillment of a moral duty] it is not thought that there is anything wrong with not giving. The charitable man may be praised, but the man who is not charitably is not condemned. People do not feel in any way ashamed or guilty about spending money on new clothes or a new car instead of giving it to famine relief.» This way of looking at the matter cannot be justified, Singer claims. 13

Singer explains that we ought to feel guilty and be blameable for spending our money on things that enhance our own comfort, when we could be saving lives instead.» When we buy new clothes not to keep ourselves warm but to look well-dressed we are not providing for any important need. We would not be sacrificing anything significant if we were to continue to wear our old clothes, and give the money to famine relief. By doing so we are preventing another person from starving.» It follows that we ought to give money away, rather than spend it on clothes which we do not need to keep us warm.» To do so is not charitable, or generous, but rather mandatory. Nor is it [a superogatory act] which it would be good to do, but not wrong not to do. Singer s point is that On the contrary, we ought to give the money away, and it is wrong not to do so. Ø our regard of giving money to save lives as charity (rather than duty) cannot be supported. (235) 14

Singer anticipates that One objection to the position [he has] taken might be simply that it is too drastic a revision of our moral scheme. People do not ordinarily judge [their obligations] in the way I have suggested they should. Most people reserve their moral condemnation for those who violate some moral norm, such as the norm against another person s property. They do not condemn those who indulge in luxury instead of giving to famine relief. Ø But the way people do in fact judge has nothing to do with the validity of my conclusion. Singer is saying that the fact that people currently do not see themselves as morally obligated to do everything in their power to prevent other people s suffering doesn t mean that they don t have this obligation, or that they are incapable of recognizing this obligation; it just indicates that they haven t yet been persuaded that they genuinely ought to condemn people (including themselves) for not giving when it is in their power to do so. 15

Singer invites us to consider why our society, and most other societies, do judge differently from the way I have suggested they should. He hypothesizes that Moral attitudes are shaped by the needs of society, and no doubt society needs people who will observe the rules that make social existence tolerable. Ø From the point of view of a particular society, it is essential to prevent violations of norms against killing, stealing, & so on,» so people in that society are taught that it is their duty not to do any of these dangerous things. Ø It is quite inessential, however, to help people outside one s own society, so doing so is not treated as a moral duty. If this is an explanation of our common distinction between duty & supererogation, however, it is not a justification of it. The moral point of view requires us to look beyond the interests of our own society, Singer insists. Previously, this may hardly have been feasible, but it is quite feasible now.» the prevention of the starvation of millions of people outside our society must be considered at least as pressing as the upholding of property norms within our society. (236-7) 16

He considers the objection that it is unreasonable to expect ordinary people to follow the principle he has defended. It has been argued by some writers that we need to have a basic moral code which is not too far beyond the capacities of the ordinary man, for otherwise there will be a general breakdown of compliance with the moral code. Crudely stated, this argument suggests that if we tell people that they ought to refrain from murder and give everything they do not really need to famine relief, they will do neither, [presumably because they will rebel against such high moral demands] whereas if we tell them that they ought to refrain from murder and that it is good to give to famine relief but not wrong to do so, they will at least refrain from murder. (237)» In summary, some of his opponents think that imposing lots of moral obligations on people will backfire by overwhelming them. 17

Singer acknowledges that it is worthwhile to think strategically about what kind of moral code people will be willing and capable of following. His opponents objection raises the question: Where should we draw the line between conduct that is required and conduct that is good although not required, so as to get the best possible result? Singer s answer is that we need to consider the effect that moral standards can have on the decisions we make. What it is possible for a man to do & what he is likely to do are both very greatly influenced by what people around him are doing & expecting him to do. (237)» He suggests that setting high moral standards will cultivate a society in which it is simply the norm, and not something extraordinary, to abandon some of one s own wealth to ensure the lives of those who are less fortunate. 18

Singer addresses another objection, which targets the basis of his view is utilitarian ethics. It follows from some forms of utilitarian theory that we all ought, morally, to be working full time to increase the balance of happiness over misery. Given the present conditions in many parts of the world, it does follow from my argument that we ought, morally, to be working full time to relieve great suffering of the sort that occurs as a result of famine or other disasters. This conclusion is one which we may be reluctant to face. I cannot see, though, why it should be regarded as a criticism of the position for which I have argued, rather than a criticism of our ordinary standards of behavior.» Since most people are self-interested to some degree, very few of us are likely to do everything that we ought to do.» It would, however, hardly be honest to take this as evidence that it is not the case that we ought to do it. (238) Ø Singer is saying that the problem is not that utilitarianism asks too much from us, but rather than we expect too little from ourselves & from each other. 19

He then considers some practical concerns: It is sometimes said that overseas aid should be a government responsibility, and that therefore one ought not to give to privately run charities. Giving privately, it is said, allows the government and the noncontributing members of society to escape their responsibilities. (239) Singer replies that it doesn t make sense to assume that governments will give less if individuals give more: instead, a government would be likely to take a high amount of individual giving as a sign that their citizenry cares about that issue and would want their government to give on their behalf.» He says it stands to be shown that increased private giving leads to less government giving. Another, more serious reason for not giving to famine relief funds is that until there is effective population control, relieving famine merely postpones starvation from overpopulation. Singer responds that if one is certain that population control, rather than famine relief, is the real cure to refugees suffering, then one ought to be doing all one can to promote population control, such as giving to organizations dedicated to that cause. (240) 20

One last concern is that by doing all that one can to prevent the suffering of refugees, one would reduce oneself to very near the material circumstances of a Bengali refugee, since we are supposed to give until the point of marginal utility, at which by giving more, I would cause as much suffering to myself or my dependents as I would relieve by my gift. Singer says that this only seems like an awful outcome to us because we live in a culture where we expect to have way more than what is necessary for our survival & well-being: consumer society has had a distorting effect on the goals and purposes of its members : If we hadn t been exposed to a lifestyle where luxuries like smartphones seem to be necessary for our survival, we wouldn t see a life without these things as a life of deprivation. He advises that we should be willing, because of our moral obligations to others, to live with much less than we currently do. 21