Propositional Attitudes and Mental Acts. Indrek Reiland. Peter Hanks and Scott Soames have recently developed similar views of propositional attitudes

Similar documents
Review of Peter Hanks Propositional Content Indrek Reiland

Propositions as Cognitive Acts Scott Soames. sentence, or the content of a representational mental state, involves knowing which

Propositions as Cognitive Acts Scott Soames. declarative sentence, or the content of a representational mental state,

The normativity of content and the Frege point

Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions. David Braun. University of Rochester

The Classificatory Conception of Propositions. Peter Hanks University of Minnesota

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Propositions as Cognitive Acts Scott Soames Draft March 1, My theory of propositions starts from two premises: (i) agents represent things as

Propositions as Cambridge properties

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

Faith and Philosophy, April (2006), DE SE KNOWLEDGE AND THE POSSIBILITY OF AN OMNISCIENT BEING Stephan Torre

Generic truth and mixed conjunctions: some alternatives

Coordination Problems

Solving the color incompatibility problem

15. Russell on definite descriptions

Advanced Topics in Metaphysics (L6/7) Alex Grzankowski Autumn 2016

Millian responses to Frege s puzzle

Necessity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pp. i-ix, 379. ISBN $35.00.

Semantic defectiveness and the liar

Theories of propositions

Generalizing Soames Argument Against Rigidified Descriptivism

Is mental content prior to linguistic meaning?

Propositions as Cognitive Event Types

Some proposals for understanding narrow content

The Representation of Logical Form: A Dilemma

Why the Traditional Conceptions of Propositions can t be Correct

Wittgenstein s Logical Atomism. Seminar 8 PHIL2120 Topics in Analytic Philosophy 16 November 2012

[3.] Bertrand Russell. 1

THE FREGE-GEACH PROBLEM AND KALDERON S MORAL FICTIONALISM. Matti Eklund Cornell University

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Understanding Belief Reports. David Braun. In this paper, I defend a well-known theory of belief reports from an important objection.

Situations in Which Disjunctive Syllogism Can Lead from True Premises to a False Conclusion

On Truth At Jeffrey C. King Rutgers University

Introduction. Cambridge University Press The Primitivist Theory of Truth Jamin Asay Excerpt More information.

Published in Analysis 61:1, January Rea on Universalism. Matthew McGrath

Phil 435: Philosophy of Language. P. F. Strawson: On Referring

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

Knowledge is Not the Most General Factive Stative Attitude

Puzzles of attitude ascriptions

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use

17. Tying it up: thoughts and intentionality

Aboutness and Justification

Scott Soames: Understanding Truth

Russellianism and Explanation. David Braun. University of Rochester

Russell on Denoting. G. J. Mattey. Fall, 2005 / Philosophy 156. The concept any finite number is not odd, nor is it even.

Direct Reference and Singular Propositions

How to Predict Future Contingencies İlhan İnan

The Metaphysics of Propositions. In preparing to give a theory of what meanings are, David Lewis [1970] famously wrote:

Penultimate Draft: Final Revisions not included. Published in Philosophical Books, 1995.

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

Foundations of Logic, Language, and Mathematics

Discovering Identity

Contextual two-dimensionalism

Objections to the two-dimensionalism of The Conscious Mind

10. Presuppositions Introduction The Phenomenon Tests for presuppositions

PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE

Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence. Abstract

Horwich and the Liar

Varieties of Apriority

Understanding Deflationism

Correct Beliefs as to What One Believes: A Note

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem?

KAPLAN RIGIDITY, TIME, A ND MODALITY. Gilbert PLUMER

Comments on Saul Kripke s Philosophical Troubles

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Published in Mind, 2000, 109 (434), pp

Conceivability and Possibility Studies in Frege and Kripke. M.A. Thesis Proposal. Department of Philosophy, CSULB. 25 May 2006

On possibly nonexistent propositions

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Philosophical Logic. LECTURE SEVEN MICHAELMAS 2017 Dr Maarten Steenhagen

A Problem for a Direct-Reference Theory of Belief Reports. Stephen Schiffer New York University

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE AND META-ETHICS

Russell: On Denoting

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

Judith Jarvis Thomson s Normativity

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

A Solution to the Gettier Problem Keota Fields. the three traditional conditions for knowledge, have been discussed extensively in the

On Possibly Nonexistent Propositions

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Kant on the Notion of Being İlhan İnan

Emotivism and its critics

Noncognitivism in Ethics, by Mark Schroeder. London: Routledge, 251 pp.

Is phenomenal character out there in the world?

Philosophy 1760 Philosophy of Language

RUSSELL, NEGATIVE FACTS, AND ONTOLOGY* L. NATHAN OAKLANDERt SILVANO MIRACCHI

Constructing the World

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant

Draft January 19, 2010 Draft January 19, True at. Scott Soames School of Philosophy USC. To Appear In a Symposium on

How Subjective Fact Ties Language to Reality

Early Russell on Philosophical Grammar

WHY WE REALLY CANNOT BELIEVE THE ERROR THEORY

(Forthcoming in Achourioti, Fujimoto, Galinon, and Martinez (eds.) Unifying the Philosophy of Truth) Truth, Pretense and the Liar Paradox 1

Presupposition and Rules for Anaphora

Privilege in the Construction Industry. Shamik Dasgupta Draft of February 2018

Can logical consequence be deflated?

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Expressing Credences. Daniel Rothschild All Souls College, Oxford OX1 4AL

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

International Research Journal of Interdisciplinary & Multidisciplinary Studies (IRJIMS) J.S. Mill on the Notion of Proper Name Soumen Roy Abstract

Epistemicism, Parasites and Vague Names * vagueness is based on an untenable metaphysics of content are unsuccessful. Burgess s arguments are

Transcription:

Penultimate version forthcoming in Thought Propositional Attitudes and Mental Acts Indrek Reiland Introduction Peter Hanks and Scott Soames have recently developed similar views of propositional attitudes on which they consist at least partly of being disposed to perform mental acts (Hanks 2007, 2011, 2013, Soames 2010, 2012, 2013). Both think that to believe a proposition is at least partly to be disposed to perform the primitive propositional act: one the performance of which is part of the performance of any other propositional act. And both think that to perform the primitive propositional act is to perform sub-propositional acts like thinking of something, predicating, negating, conjoining, disjoining etc. 1 Finally, both also think that the primitive propositional acts explain what ties together the constituents of structured propositions into a representational whole because propositions just are types of such acts. 2 However, they differ over the details. Soames takes the primitive propositional act to be the forceless entertaining and takes entertainings to consist of acts of thinking of and acts of predicating, which he thinks of as non-committal property ascription (Soames 2010, 2012, 2013). He then identifies the non-primitive propositional act of judging with entertaining + affirming, 1 For an interesting precursor to views like this see Searle 1969. 2 I m inclined to think that there s a part of their approach to propositions that is essential to it, and a part that is negotiable. The essential part is the idea the primitive propositional acts tie together the constituents of at least some structured propositions. The negotiable part is the claim that propositions just are types of such acts. For a view that retains the essential part while doing away with the negotiable one by identifying propositions with states of affairs see Reiland MS(b). 1

believing with being disposed to judge, and propositions with entertaining-types. In contrast, Hanks takes the primitive propositional act to be the forceful judging and takes judgments to consist of acts of referring and acts of predicating, which he thinks of as committal property ascription (Hanks 2011: 13-14). He then identifies believing with being disposed to judge and propositions with judgment-types. 3 My aim in this paper is to argue that Soames s forceless approach has an advantage over Hanks s forceful approach which faces a serious problem. I will proceed as follows. I ll start by showing how Soames s approach handles certain complex primitive propositional acts and how they pose a prima facie problem for Hanks s approach (Section 1). I ll then look at Hanks s purported solution and argue that it doesn t work, showing how serious the problem really is (Section 2). 3 Unlike Soames, Hanks doesn t think that the notion of forceless entertaining and the related notion of predication as non-committal property ascription make sense: I cannot understand what it would be to predicate a property of an object without committing yourself to the object s having that property. I do not see how it is possible to apply or attribute a property to an object and yet remain neutral about whether the object has that property. (Hanks 2013) This is why he takes the primitive propositional act to be the forceful judging. However, he nevertheless seems to think that an analogous notion does make sense: On my account, to judge that a is F is to predicate, in a non-neutral sense, the property of F of a. If we like, we can say that sometimes this act of predication is preceded by the subject s contemplation of the act of predicating F of a. That kind of contemplation would be the analog, on my account of neutral predication or of entertaining a proposition. (Hanks 2013) Unfortunately he doesn t tell us anything further about this analogous notion and how to think about it in terms of his proposal that the primitive propositional act is the forceful judging. I will therefore not discuss it further here. For general discussion of why we can t get by without the notion of forceless entertaining and the relations between entertaining and judging and judging and believing see Kriegel 2013, Reiland MS(a). 2

1. Complex Propositional Acts Soames takes the primitive propositional act to be the forceless entertaining. On his view to entertain the proposition that Bertrand is British is to perform the following sub-propositional acts: think of Bertrand, think of the property of being British, and predicate or non-committally ascribe the property of being British to Bertrand (hereafter predicate#), where the latter is what ties Bertrand and being British together in the proposition that Bertrand is British and makes it represent Bertrand as being British. Similarly, to entertain the proposition that Gottlob is German is to think of Gottlob, think of the property of being German, and predicate# being German of Gottlob. I will represent this with the following notation (where represents entertaining, SUBJ what is the subject of predication, and PRED# what is predicated#): (1) entertaining the proposition that Bertrand is British = <Bertrand SUBJ, being British PRED# > (2) entertaining the proposition that Gottlob is German = <Gottlob SUBJ, being German PRED# > In contrast, Hanks takes the primitive propositional act to be the forceful judging. On his view to judge that Bertrand is British is to perform the following sub-propositional acts: refer to Bertrand and to predicate or committally ascribe being British to him (hereafter predicate*), where the latter is again what ties Bertrand and being British together in the proposition that Bertrand is British and makes it represent Bertrand as being British. I will represent this with the following notation (where represents judging and PRED* what is predicated*): (3) judging that Bertrand is British = < Bertrand SUBJ, being British PRED* > 3

Now, Soames s forceless approach can easily handle certain complex primitive propositional acts like the entertaining of the proposition that it is false that Bertrand is German or the entertaining of the proposition that that either Bertrand is British or Gottlob is German. To entertain the proposition that it is false that Bertrand is British is to think of the relevant proposition, think of the property of being false and predicate# the property of being false of the proposition. Similarly, to entertain the proposition that either Bertrand is British or Gottlob is German is to think of the two propositions and disjoin# them. 4 What is required for us to think of propositions in these cases? Soames thinks that to explain what ties together the constituents of structured propositions into a representational whole we need to think that our entertainings of propositions are metaphysically prior to the propositions themselves. The idea is that what it is to perform such acts can be analyzed without reference to propositions whereas propositions can just be identified with types of those acts. However, on such a view there is no other way of thinking of our direct cognitive access to propositions than in terms of performing a token of the act-type that is the proposition. Thus, since on this way of thinking we can t make sense of our cognitive access to propositions independently of the primitive propositional acts, it follows that we must perform the relevant token of the act-type that is the proposition. And this means that on Soames s approach to think of a proposition in these cases one has to entertain it. 5 This leads to 4 Soames prefers to think of disjoining as a primitive act which doesn t presuppose grip on the property of being true (Soames 2010: 120-122). An alternative way is to think of it as predication of the property of being disjointly true where two propositions are disjointly true iff one or the other is true or one or more of them is true, but not both (Hanks 2011: 20). Since both ways of thinking about disjoining are compatible with both Soames s forceless and Hanks s forceful approach, I won t mention this further. 5 Not all cases where something is predicated# of propositions are like this. In the case of the above complex propositional acts the relevant propositions are thought of in a revealing manner or directly. However, we can think of propositions without entertaining them when we possess names of them. For example, if we name the proposition that Bertrand is German Jones and pass the name on to someone, then they can perhaps think of it and entertain the proposition that Jones is false. However, here the proposition is thought of in an unrevealing manner because one 4

the following view of the makeup of the entertainings of the propositions that it is false that Bertrand is German and that either Bertrand is British or Gottlob is German: (4) entertaining the proposition that it is false that Bertrand is German = < <Bertrand SUBJ, being German PRED* > SUBJ, being false PRED* > (5) entertaining the proposition that either Bertrand is British or Gottlob is German = < <Bertrand SUBJ, being British PRED* > SUBJ, < Gottlob SUBJ, being German PRED* > SUBJ, DISJ>> And this is unproblematic. It s clear that when you entertain the proposition that it is false that Bertrand is German you also entertain the proposition that Bertrand is German and when you entertain the proposition that either Bertrand is British or Gottlob is German you entertain both the proposition that Bertrand is British and the proposition that Bertrand is German. However, compare now how Hanks s forceful approach seems forced to handle complex primitive propositional acts like judging that it is false that Bertrand is German or judging that either Bertrand is British or Gottlob is German. To judge that it is false that Bertrand is British is to refer to the proposition that Bertrand is British and predicate* being false of it. Similarly, to judge that either Bertrand is British or Gottlob is German is to refer to the two propositions and disjoin* them. What is required for us to refer to propositions in these cases? Like Soames, Hanks thinks that to explain what ties together the constituents of structured doesn t have to know which proposition it is. Similarly, we can perhaps think of propositions indirectly by using a description. For example, if we describe the proposition that Bertrand is German as the proposition such that to entertain it one must subject Bertrand and predicate# being British of it then we can think of it like this and entertain the proposition that it is false. However, here the proposition is thought of in an indirect manner, as whatever it is that satisfies the description. 5

propositions into a representational whole we need to think that our judgings of propositions to be the case are metaphysically prior to the propositions themselves. The idea here is that what it is to perform such acts can be analyzed without reference to propositions whereas propositions can just be identified with types of those acts. However, on such a view there is no other way of thinking of our direct cognitive access to propositions than in terms of performing a token of the act-type that is the proposition. Thus, since on this way of thinking we can t make sense of our cognitive access to propositions independently of the primitive propositional acts, it follows that we must perform the relevant token of the act-type that is the proposition. And this means that on Hanks s approach to refer to a proposition in these cases one has to judge it to be the case. However, this leads to the following view of the makeup of the judgments that it is false that Bertrand is German and that either Bertrand is British or Gottlob is German: (6) judging that it is false that Bertrand is German = < ( <Bertrand SUBJ, being German PRED* > SUBJ ), being false PRED* > (7) judging that either Bertrand is British or Gottlob is German = < ( <Bertrand SUBJ, being British PRED* > SUBJ ), ( < Gottlob SUBJ, being German PRED* > SUBJ ), DISJ > And this is of course absurd. It can t be that when you judge that it is false that Bertrand is German you also judge that Bertrand is German or when you judge that either Bertrand is British or Gottlob is German you judge both that Bertrand is British and Bertrand is German. 6

Thus, although Soames s approach can easily handle certain complex primitive propositional acts, they pose a prima facie problem for Hanks s approach. In the next section I ll look at Hanks s purported solution and argue that it doesn t work, showing how serious the problem is. 2. Cancellation Here s Hanks s purported solution: We can start with George is clever or Karla is foolish. When a speaker assertively utters this sentence she neither asserts that George is clever nor that Karla is foolish, and she neither predicates cleverness of George nor foolishness of Karla. Frege took this to show that there is no assertive element in the contents of George is clever and Karla is foolish, but it would be just as reasonable to conclude that the assertive element in these contents is cancelled or overridden by the presence of or. This is the idea I want to pursue here. I maintain that by uttering these sentences inside a disjunction a speaker cancels the predicative acts she would have performed had she uttered them as stand-alone sentences. Although a speaker asserts neither disjunct by uttering George is clever or Karla is foolish, she still performs an assertion and hence an act of predication. The speaker asserts that George is clever or Karla is foolish. How should we understand the act of predication contained in this assertion? Let p and q be propositions expressed by declarative sentences, that is, types of predicative actions. To assert that p or q is to predicate a disjunctive relation, expressed by or, of p and q. Two propositions p and q bear this disjunctive relation just in case either p is true or q is true. As types of predicative acts, the propositions p and q are true or false and hence can stand in this disjunctive relation. In predicating disjunction of p and q, however, one does not perform tokens of p 7

and q themselves. In an utterance of p or q, the acts of predication one would otherwise find in tokens of p and q are cancelled by the use of or (Hanks 2011: 20, see also Hanks 2007: 153) What Hanks seems to say is that when you judge that it is false that Bertrand is German you predicate being German of Bertrand, but then cancel this predication when you further predicate being false of the proposition. 6 Similarly, when you judge that either Bertrand is British or Gottlob is German you predicate being British of Bertrand and being German of Gottlob, but then cancel these predications when you disjoin them. We can represent this idea with the following notation (where CANC represents cancellation): (8) judging that it is false that Bertrand is German = < ( CANC <Bertrand SUBJ, being German PRED* > SUBJ ), being false PRED* > (9) judging that either Bertrand is British or Gottlob is German = < ( CANC <Bertrand SUBJ, being British PRED* > SUBJ ), ( CANC < Gottlob SUBJ, being German PRED* > SUBJ ), DISJ > (compare Hanks 2011: 21) In order to see whether this purported solution works we need to know more about cancellation. 6 One might be taken aback by Hanks s remark above that In predicating disjunction of p and q, however, one does not perform tokens of p and q themselves. This seems to suggest that Hanks doesn t think that we can t make sense of our cognitive access to propositions independently of the primitive propositional acts and that to refer to a proposition in these cases one has to judge it to be the case. However, this is not how this remark is to be read. Rather, Hanks s idea is that you do perform the act, but then cancel a part of it so you don t end up performing the full act. If Hanks wouldn t think that to refer to a proposition one has to judge it to be the case then the problem I described in the previous section wouldn t arise. However, since he thinks that the problem arises and goes on to provide a solution he must think that to refer to a proposition in the above cases one has to judge it to be the case. Furthermore, he has confirmed that he does indeed think this (p. c.). 8

Although Hanks doesn t really say much about cancellation, it seems to me that there are only two possible ways of thinking about it. First, we could think that it completely obliterates the contribution of the previous act. Thus, it makes it the case that it is as if the previous act hadn t taken place. The problem with this is that then we lose what is supposed to tie together Bertrand and being German in the proposition that it is false that Bertrand is German. After all, a core part of Hanks s view is that those two constituents are tied together by the act of predicating* being German of Bertrand. However, if cancellation is complete obliteration of the contribution of the previous act, then we lose that. Thus, it seems that Hanks can t really adopt this way of thinking about cancellation. 7 The second way to think about cancellation is to think that it obliterates a part of the contribution of the previous act. For example, one could think that the cancellation of predication obliterates the forceful part and leaves intact the part that does the tying. The problem with this is that it requires us to think of predication as having these separate parts. And then it seems that one of the parts, the one that does the tying, looks like predicating# or non-committal property ascription. However, once we accept this we lose all sense in which judgments are the primitive propositional acts because now it seems that they consist partly of entertainings. This is Soames s approach. Thus, it seems that Hanks can t really adopt this way of thinking about cancellation either. And since it seems that there aren t any other ways of thinking about cancellation, we can conclude that Hanks s purported solution doesn t work, showing how serious the problem really is. 7 See also Hom & Schwartz MS for this point. 9

Acknowledgements Thanks to Chris Hom, Ben Lennertz, Karen Lewis, Peter Hanks, Uriah Kriegel, Mark Schroeder, Scott Soames, and an anonymous referee for helpful comments and/or discussion. References Hanks, P. 2007. The Content-Force Distinction. Philosophical Studies 56: 141-64. Hanks, P. 2011. Structured Propositions as Types. Mind 120: 11-52. Hanks, P. 2013. First-Person Propositions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 86: 155-82 Hom, C. & Schwartz, J. MS. Unity and the Frege-Geach Problem Kriegel, U. 2013. Entertaining as a Propositional Attitude: A Non-Reductive Characterization. American Philosophical Quarterly 50: 1-22 Reiland, I. MS(a). Entertaining, Considering, Judging, and Believing Reiland, I. MS(b). Propositions as States of Affairs 10

Searle, J. 1969. Speech Acts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press Soames, S. 2010. What is Meaning? Princeton: Princeton University Press. Soames, S. 2012. Propositions. In The Routledge Companion to the Philosophy of Language, ed. D. G. Fara, G. Russell, 209-220, London: Routledge Soames, S. 2013. Propositions as Cognitive Event Types. Forthcoming in New Thinking About Propositions, by J. King, S. Soames, J. Speaks. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 11