FOUNDATIONALISM AND ARBITRARINESS

Similar documents
Is Klein an infinitist about doxastic justification?

THREE ARGUMENTS AGAINST FOUNDATIONALISM: ARBITRARINESS, EPISTEMIC REGRESS, AND EXISTENTIAL SUPPORT

Three Arguments Against Foundationalism: Arbitrariness, Epistemic Regress, and Existential Support

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

Arbitrary Foundations? On Klein s Objection to Foundationalism

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

Foundationalism Vs. Skepticism: The Greater Philosophical Ideology

RATIONALITY AND THEISTIC BELIEF, by Mark S. McLeod. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, Pp. xiv and 260. $37.50 (cloth).

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Finite Reasons without Foundations

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

I guess I m just a good-old-fashioned internalist. A prominent position in philosophy of religion today is that religious experience can

Phenomenal Conservatism and the Demand for Metajustification *

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

Bon Jour s Basic Antifoundationalist Argument and the Doctrine of the Given

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach

ACQUAINTANCE AND THE PROBLEM OF THE SPECKLED HEN

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Reliabilism and the Problem of Defeaters

Phenomenal Conservatism and the Internalist Intuition

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE AND META-ETHICS

SUPPOSITIONAL REASONING AND PERCEPTUAL JUSTIFICATION

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke,

foundationalism and coherentism are responses to it. I will then prove that, although

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett

Robert Audi, The Architecture of Reason: The Structure and. Substance of Rationality. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xvi, 286.

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Reliabilism: Holistic or Simple?

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

Lost in Transmission: Testimonial Justification and Practical Reason

Analytic Philosophy IUC Dubrovnik,

Goldman on Knowledge as True Belief. Alvin Goldman (2002a, 183) distinguishes the following four putative uses or senses of

Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence. Abstract

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

Internalism and Properly Basic Belief. Matthew Davidson, CSUSB Gordon Barnes, SUNY-Brockport

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

Why There s Nothing You Can Say to Change My Mind: The Principle of Non-Contradiction in Aristotle s Metaphysics

Acquaintance and assurance

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

METHODISM AND HIGHER-LEVEL EPISTEMIC REQUIREMENTS Brendan Murday

CARTESIANISM, NEO-REIDIANISM, AND THE A PRIORI: REPLY TO PUST

Markie, Speckles, and Classical Foundationalism

The stated objective of Gloria Origgi s paper Epistemic Injustice and Epistemic Trust is:

The Problem with Complete States: Freedom, Chance and the Luck Argument

DENNETT ON THE BASIC ARGUMENT JOHN MARTIN FISCHER

ON JESUS, DERRIDA, AND DAWKINS: REJOINDER TO JOSHUA HARRIS

Huemer s Problem of Memory Knowledge

Constructive Logic, Truth and Warranted Assertibility

Physicalism and Conceptual Analysis * Esa Díaz-León.

NOT SO PROMISING AFTER ALL: EVALUATOR-RELATIVE TELEOLOGY AND COMMON-SENSE MORALITY

ELEONORE STUMP PENELHUM ON SKEPTICS AND FIDEISTS

What God Could Have Made

Moore s paradoxes, Evans s principle and self-knowledge

UC Berkeley, Philosophy 142, Spring 2016

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

Scott Soames: Understanding Truth

Interest-Relativity and Testimony Jeremy Fantl, University of Calgary

Gale on a Pragmatic Argument for Religious Belief

Bigelow, Possible Worlds and The Passage of Time

Nested Testimony, Nested Probability, and a Defense of Testimonial Reductionism Benjamin Bayer September 2, 2011

Criticizing Arguments

BLACKWELL PUBLISHING THE SCOTS PHILOSOPHICAL CLUB UNIVERSITY OF ST ANDREWS

Review of J.L. Schellenberg, Divine Hiddenness and Human Reason (Ithaca, NY: Cornell UP, 1993), i-x, 219 pages.

Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox

Mentalist evidentialism vindicated (and a super-blooper epistemic design problem for proper function justification)

SCHAFFER S DEMON NATHAN BALLANTYNE AND IAN EVANS

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

HANDBOOK. IV. Argument Construction Determine the Ultimate Conclusion Construct the Chain of Reasoning Communicate the Argument 13

Skepticism and Internalism

McDowell and the New Evil Genius

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Towards Richard Rorty s Critique on Transcendental Grounding of Human Rights by Dr. P.S. Sreevidya

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

The Representation of Logical Form: A Dilemma

The Paradox of the Question

Shieva Kleinschmidt [This is a draft I completed while at Rutgers. Please do not cite without permission.] Conditional Desires.

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works

10 CERTAINTY G.E. MOORE: SELECTED WRITINGS

THE FREGE-GEACH PROBLEM AND KALDERON S MORAL FICTIONALISM. Matti Eklund Cornell University

PHILOSOPHY EPISTEMOLOGY ESSAY TOPICS AND INSTRUCTIONS

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

Mentalist Evidentialism Vindicated (and a Super-Blooper Epistemic Design Problem for Proper Function Justification)

Nagel, Naturalism and Theism. Todd Moody. (Saint Joseph s University, Philadelphia)

Is There Immediate Justification?

Klein on the Unity of Cartesian and Contemporary Skepticism

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Why there is no such thing as a motivating reason

PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy

in defence of an argument for evans s principle 167

Transcription:

FOUNDATIONALISM AND ARBITRARINESS by DANIEL HOWARD-SNYDER Abstract: Nonskeptical foundationalists say that there are basic beliefs. But, one might object, either there is a reason why basic beliefs are likely to be true or there is not. If there is, then they are not basic; if there is not, then they are arbitrary. I argue that this dilemma is not nearly as decisive as its author, Peter Klein, would have us believe. A particular belief of a person is basic just in case it is epistemically justified and it owes its justification to something other than her other justified beliefs or their interrelations; a person s belief is nonbasic just in case it is epistemically justified but not basic. Foundationalists agree that if one has a nonbasic belief, then at rock bottom it owes its justification to at least one basic belief. There are justified beliefs (if any) because and only because there are basic beliefs. Such is the genus Foundationalism. 1 In this essay I assess Peter Klein s recent case against Foundationalism, which is centered on the charge that basic beliefs are arbitrary. 2 Klein sets his case against Foundationalism in the context of a dialogue between himself and the Foundationalist, call her Freeda, which, for all practical purposes, goes like this: Foundationalists advocate believing certain things arbitrarily. We do? Ya, but you call them basic beliefs. Oh, I see. There must be some misunderstanding. We advocate believing certain things without reasons, not arbitrarily. 3 Ha! Now there s a distinction without a difference! What... what do you mean? To believe something without a reason entails believing it arbitrarily. After all, firstly, if you believe something without a reason, then there is nothing that makes it even slightly Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 86 (2005) 18 24 Published by Blackwell Publishing Ltd, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA. 18

FOUNDATIONALISM AND ARBITRARINESS 19 better to believe than any of its contraries. And, secondly, if there s nothing that makes it even slightly better to believe than any of its contraries, then you believe it arbitrarily. Ah. I see. There really is a misunderstanding here. It s that first premise of yours. Let me explain. We advocate believing something without a reason only when there is some meta-justification for it, an argument to the effect that belief in it has some property P, and any belief that has P is likely to be true. Of course, we foundationalists squabble about what P is, exactly; but that s beside the point. The point is that we advocate believing something without reasons only when there is some such meta-justification, something that indicates that one is believing it in a truthconducive fashion. In that case, we can hardly be charged with advocating believing something arbitrarily, wouldn t you agree? Now we hear from Klein in his own voice: Can [the foundationalist] avoid advocating the acceptance of arbitrary reasons by moving to meta-justifications?... Pick your favorite accounts of the property, P. I think... that the old Pyrrhonian question is reasonable: Why is having P truth-conducive? Now, either there is an answer available to that question or there isn t.... If there is an answer, then the regress continues at least one more step, and that is all that is needed here, because that shows that the offered reason that some belief has P or some set of beliefs has P does not stop the regress. If there isn t an answer, the assertion is arbitrary. 4 To clarify matters, Klein insists, My point is merely that moving to the meta-level, that is, arguing that such beliefs [i.e. basic beliefs] are likely to be true because they possess a certain property, P, will not avoid the problem faced by foundationalism. Either the meta-justification provides a reason for thinking the base proposition is true (and hence the regress does not end) or it does not (hence, accepting the base proposition is arbitrary). 5 And finally, he concludes: To generalize: Foundationalism... cannot avoid the regress by appealing to a meta-claim that a belief having some property, P, is likely to be true. That claim itself requires an argument that appeals to reasons.... For surely a reason is required to justify the belief that propositions with property, P, are likely to be true; and whatever justifies that claim will require a reason; and well, you get the point. 6 Now, what exactly is Klein s argument here? Pretty clearly, he intends a dilemma, specifically this:

20 PACIFIC PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY 1. Either there is a meta-justification or there is not. 2. If there is, then there are no basic beliefs (i.e., Foundationalism is false). 3. If there is not, then Foundationalism advocates arbitrariness at the base. 4. So, either there are no basic beliefs (i.e., Foundationalism is false) or Foundationalism advocates arbitrariness at the base. What should we make of this dilemma? Note that the conclusion is disjunctive and only one of the disjuncts is the denial of Foundationalism. One might object that, in that case, it is hardly an argument against Foundationalism. Perhaps the foundationalist can rest content with arbitrary basic beliefs. Unfortunately, the foundationalist cannot find solace in arbitrariness. That s because justification just is being nonarbitrary in the relevant sense; if one justifiedly believes something, then it is at least slightly better to believe it rather than its contraries. Consequently, an arbitrary belief is unjustified. But by definition, a basic belief is justified. Thus, if the basic beliefs that Foundationalism advocates are arbitrary, then they are at once justified and not justified a contradiction. So the arbitrariness option reduces to the denial of Foundationalism. In what follows, I will take it that if Klein s premises are true, then Foundationalism is false (full stop). So, what about the premises? In particular, why should we suppose that premise 2 is true? Klein s case for it goes like this: 2a. If there is a meta-justification, then the regress does not end. 2b. If the regress does not end, then there are no basic beliefs. 2. So, if there is a meta-justification, then there are no basic beliefs (i.e., Foundationalism is false). What should we make of this argument? Premise 2a is false, I suggest. Let s consider a particular case. Suppose S believes that there are some red things. Her reason for this is that there are red balls. Her reason for this is that there is a red ball in front of her. And, finally, her reason for this is that the ball in front of her looks red. Now, suppose she has no reason for believing that the ball in front of her looks red; that is, given Klein s thesis that only beliefs can be reasons, suppose that there is no other belief of hers which serves as a reason for her believing that the ball looks red. So S believes that the ball looks red without reasons. Now, suppose that there is a meta-justification for S s belief; her belief that the ball looks red has some property P such that any belief that has P is very likely to be true. If Klein s premise 2a is true, it follows that the regress does not end. It does not follow, however.

FOUNDATIONALISM AND ARBITRARINESS 21 To see why, keep three points in mind. First, the person whose noetic structure is under discussion is our friend S, and it is the regress of her reasons which, according to Klein, does not end in the scenario above. In particular her regress of reasons does not end with her belief that the ball in front of her looks red. Second, S s regress of reasons continues if and only if she believes that the ball looks red on the basis of some other reason, some other belief of hers (given Klein s thesis that only beliefs can be reasons). Third, arguments are abstract entities; thus, given the scenario described above, there exists, in the abstract, some ordered set of propositions schematically expressed in English like this: 1. S s belief that the ball looks red has feature P. 2. Beliefs having P are very likely to be true. 3. So, S s belief that the ball looks red is very likely to be true. Thus, if Klein s premise 2a is true, then, it follows from the fact that this meta-justification exists in the abstract that S believes that the ball looks red on the basis of some other reason, some other belief of hers. But that can t be right. The sheer existence of the meta-justificatory argument, in the abstract, does not determine S s psychological structure. The sheer existence of the meta-justification is not sufficient for her to believe that the ball looks red on the basis of that meta-justificatory argument. So 2a is false. Perhaps Klein meant to say that when the contemporary foundationalist appeals to meta-justifications in order to meet the challenge of arbitrariness, the regress continues. (See the second quote from him above.) It s not their sheer existence that suffices for the continuation of the regress; it s the appeal to them that suffices. In that case, 2a should be modified as follows: 2a. If the contemporary foundationalist appeals to a meta-justification in order to explain why basic beliefs are not arbitrary, the regress does not end. But 2a is just as clearly false as 2a. Does the contemporary foundationalist s moving to the meta-level, that is, arguing that [basic] beliefs are likely to be true because they possess a certain property, P, suffice to bring it about that the regress of reasons in S s noetic stucture continues? Imagine Sappho, some ancient Greek attending a circus; she sees a black bear in front of her playing with a red ball and comes to believe that the ball looks red. Twenty-five hundred years later some foundationalist moves to the meta-level, arguing that beliefs such as hers are likely to be true because they possess a certain property, P. If 2a is true, it follows that Sappho, back then at the circus, believed that the ball looks red on the

22 PACIFIC PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY basis of the contemporary foundationalist s appeal to a meta-justification for her sort of belief. But this consequence is surely false. Even friends of backward causation will deny that contemporary foundationalists have this much power (even if Foundationalism is correct). A question naturally arises at this point: if it is neither the sheer existence of a meta-justification nor the contemporary foundationalist s appeal to one that makes it the case that the regress of reasons continues in S s noetic structure, then what does make it the case that it continues? Perhaps Klein will insist that the meta-justification must be subjectively available to S. Perhaps he ll say that if there is a meta-justification, then, if it is to be at all relevant to meeting the challenge of arbitrariness in S s case, it must be properly hooked up with S s own beliefs. 7 If that s the way we are to understand Klein, then his explicit statement of his case against Foundationalism is slightly misleading. The fact that there are no basic beliefs does not follow from the fact that there is a meta-justification or the fact that the foundationalist appeals to a metajustification to meet the charge of arbitrariness. Rather, if there is a metajustification that explains how a particular individual s basic belief can be justified without reasons, then that meta-justification must be properly hooked up with her own beliefs; otherwise, her belief is arbitrary. We need, therefore, to revise Klein s case against Foundationalism. Let S be any human person, and let Bp be any allegedly basic belief that p. If we are to understand Klein in the way suggested, then Klein s case against Foundationalism is really this: 1. Either S has a meta-justification for her Bp that is properly hooked up with her own beliefs or she does not. 2. If she does, then S s Bp is not basic. 3. If she does not, then S s Bp is arbitrary (hence not justified, so not basic). 4. So, S s Bp is not basic. The conclusion is a contradiction (remember: S s Bp is ex hypothesi a basic belief). Therefore, it is impossible for there to be basic beliefs Foundationalism is false. What should we make of this revised dilemma? Of course, reliabilists of certain sorts will deny premise 3, but I want to focus on premise 2. Two sorts of questions arise immediately. First, what is this hook-up of which Klein speaks? And under what conditions is it properly exhibited? Unfortunately, he doesn t answer these questions; he leaves the notion undefined, so far as I can see. Let s suppose, for now, that we have a sufficient grasp of properly hooked up to move on. The second question is this: even if S has a meta-justification for her Bp that is properly hooked up with her own beliefs, why suppose it follows that

FOUNDATIONALISM AND ARBITRARINESS 23 her Bp is not basic? That is, why suppose 2 is true? Klein does not explicitly offer an argument, but I d like to suggest that it s no mystery as to what sort of thing he needs to say in defense of 2. He needs to say something like this: 2a. If S has a meta-justification for her Bp that is properly hooked up with S s own beliefs, then S believes the premises of the meta-justification. 2b. If S believes the premises of the meta-justification, then S s Bp is not basic. 2. So, if S has a meta-justification for her Bp that is properly hooked up with S s own beliefs, then S s Bp is not basic. (2a, 2b) This would be an excellent argument if premise 2b were true; unfortunately, it isn t. The fact that S believes the premises of a meta-justification does not imply that S s Bp derives its justification from her belief in those premises. To see why, consider the following case. Suppose you interrupt Sappho while she s looking at the ball at the circus and inform her that it is very likely that her belief that it looks red is true since it has P and P is truth-conducive. She reflects for a moment, and then concurs with you. Does it follow that her belief that the ball looks red derives its justification from the meta-justification she newly believes? Of course not. To suppose that it does is to confuse these two states of affairs: S believes the ball looks red and S believes the premises of a metajustification for her belief. S s belief that the ball looks red derives its justification from her belief in the premises of a meta-justification. The latter is not the former, and the former does not entail the latter. In that case, since S can believe the premises of a meta-justification without her Bp deriving its justification therefrom, the possibility remains that S s Bp is basic even though she believes the premises of the meta-justification. That is to say, 2b is false. There is only one way to bridge the gap that Klein needs to bridge here, and that way is to lay it down, explicitly or implicitly, that S s Bp is not properly hooked up to her belief in the premises of the meta-justification unless the justification of her Bp is derived from her belief in the premises of the meta-justification. Unfortunately, this way of bridging the gap leads to disappointment. For in that case, premise 3 of the revised dilemma, with its undefined locution properly hooked up, turns out to be way of saying in Klein s vocabulary that: 3*. If S s Bp does not derive its justification from S s belief in the premises of a meta-justification for her Bp, then S s Bp is arbitrary.

24 PACIFIC PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY And 3*, by contraposition and the semantic platitude that justification is nonarbitrariness par excellence, is just another way of saying 3**. If S s Bp is justified, then S s Bp derives its justification from S s belief in the premises of a meta-justification for her Bp. 3**, however, is nothing more than a stylistic variant on the denial of Foundationalism. Friends and foes of Foundationalism alike rightly wish for more than that as a premise in an argument against Foundationalism. Perhaps I m mistaken, but, so far as I can see, Klein s case against Foundationalism fails. Even so, Foundationalism may nevertheless be false. Thus, all we can conclude here is that if we wish to reject Foundationalism sensibly, we will have to look to someone other than Peter Klein for guidance. 8 Department of Philosophy Western Washington University NOTES 1 Three clarifications are in order. First, although I have characterized Foundationalism in terms of epistemic justification, it is not wedded to that family of concepts. Substitute whatever general terms of epistemic appraisal you like and the foundationalist will offer you a basic/nonbasic distinction. Second, a foundationalist need not deny that a belief s justification can have multiple sources. For example, suppose you believe with justification that your babies are crying, and your belief owes its justification to (i) your present auditory experience as well as (ii) an inference from the present testimony of your spouse. Is your belief basic or nonbasic? The foundationalist should say that it all depends. If, all else being equal, your belief would still be justified even if it did not owe its justification to your inference from your spouse s testimony, then it is basic; if it would not, then it is nonbasic. My assessment of Klein s case against Foundationalism does not hang on this modification of the characterization of basic belief in the text. Third, my characterization of Foundationalism does not imply that there are basic beliefs. It allows that Foundationalism could be true even if there were no believers and even if there were no justified beliefs. This is a virtue of my characterization, a virtue lacking in other characterizations. 2 Peter Klein (1999). Human Knowledge and the Infinite Regress of Reasons, Philosophical Perspectives, 13, pp. 297 325, hereafter HK. 3 Although Freeda goes along with Klein s claim that only beliefs can be reasons, many foundationalists do not. Since my concerns with Klein s argument go much deeper than this, I propose to let Freeda s concession stand. 4 HK p. 303. 5 HK p. 304. 6 HK p. 304. 7 See HK p. 300. 8 For comments on previous drafts, I thank William Alston, Michael Bergmann, Tom Downing, Hud Hudson, and Christian Lee. Michael Bergmann has authored an excellent critique of Klein s argument that differs from mine. See What s Not Wrong With Foundationalism, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 68 (2004), 161 65.