Aquinas and Alison on Reconciliation with God

Similar documents
Job s Suffering: A Hypostatic Cry

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

What We Are: Our Metaphysical Nature & Moral Implications

A Loving Kind of Knowing: Connatural Knowledge as a Means of Knowing God in Thomas Aquinas s Summa Theologica

Alife in peace is a basic human desire. It is also a basic human right, many

could one remember the evil committed (and remember it as evil), and at the

Building Your Theology

Wisdom in Aristotle and Aquinas From Metaphysics to Mysticism Edmond Eh University of Saint Joseph, Macau

Spiritual Theology by Jordan Aumann, OP. Study Questions - Chapter Four. -The Supernatural Organism-

VIOLENCE AND THE SACRED: INTERPRETATIONS OF RENÉ GIRARD IN CHRISTIAN PHILOSOPHY AND PEACE STUDIES

Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination

John Scottus Eriugena: Analysing the Philosophical Contribution of an Forgotten Thinker

Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence. Abstract

SYSTEMATIC RESEARCH IN PHILOSOPHY. Contents

On Truth Thomas Aquinas

by Wayne Northey discovery for me was when I began to see the uniqueness of the Bible, especially the Christian text, from the standpoint 1

7/31/2017. Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God

The Eucharist: Source and Summit of Christian Spirituality Mark Brumley

Method in Theology. A summary of the views of Bernard Lonergan, i taken from his book, Method in Theology. ii

On the Relation of Philosophy to the Theology Conference Seward 11/24/98

Dela Cruz 0. Luther s Place in European Intellectual History (Revised) Mariel Dela Cruz 21G.059 Spring 2008 Professor T. Nolden

The Five Ways THOMAS AQUINAS ( ) Thomas Aquinas: The five Ways

From Speculation to Salvation The Trinitarian Theology of Edward Schillebeeckx. Stephan van Erp

William Hasker s discussion of the Thomistic doctrine of the soul

Explaining the Trinity

You may not start to read the questions printed on the subsequent pages of this question paper until instructed that you may do so by the Invigilator

Reading the Nichomachean Ethics

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

AQUINAS S FOURTH WAY: FROM GRADATIONS OF BEING

1. What is Confession?

A Study of Order: Lessons for Historiography and Theology

The Ethics of Self Realization: A Radical Subjectivism, Bounded by Realism. An Honors Thesis (HONR 499) Kevin Mager. Thesis Advisor Jason Powell

RENÉ GIRARD, UNLIKELY APOLOGIST

Reasons for Belief Session 1 I Struggle With Doubt. Is That OK?

DIOCESE OF LANCASTER EDUCATION SERVICE LANCASTER RE

If Only You Had Eyes to See: The Threat of the Mythologizing Cross in the Space of Empire

Humanities 3 V. The Scientific Revolution

Ecstatic Hymns: The Hymn s Role in Encountering Mystery in Liturgical Worship

The Confessional Statement of the Biblical Counseling Coalition

In Concerning the Difference between the Spirit and the Letter in Philosophy, Johann

A Multitude of Selves: Contrasting the Cartesian and Nietzschean views of selfhood

Man and the Presence of Evil in Christian and Platonic Doctrine by Philip Sherrard

A Course In Miracle Workbook For Dummies

SOCIOLOGY AND THEOLOGY: RESPONSE (II) TO GREGORY BAUM

Jewish and Muslim Thinkers in the Islamic World: Three Parallels. Peter Adamson (LMU Munich)

The stated objective of Gloria Origgi s paper Epistemic Injustice and Epistemic Trust is:

A Quiz on the Doctrine of the Atonement

Lesson 5 Eucharist and Reconciliation

Community (Dictionary entry)

Fourth Meditation: Truth and falsity

Our presentation looks at Sin and Grace, perhaps polar opposites.

The Confessional Statement of the Biblical Counseling Coalition

The Early Church worked tirelessly to establish a clear firm structure supported by

Revelation and Reason. 1

ever read the whole of the Summa. College graduates, especially students of religion and philosophy, may have studied a few selections, but somehow th

Proclaiming Jesus Christ:

The Evangelical Turn of John Paul II and Veritatis Splendor

The Ladies Auxiliary, written by Tova Mirvis, illustrates a religious community struggling to

Applying the Concept of Choice in the Nigerian Education: the Existentialist s Perspective

Thomas Aquinas College Napa Institute, Saint Thomas Aquinas. Summa Theologiae First Part, Question 21

God is a Community Part 4: Jesus

Philosophy of Ethics Philosophy of Aesthetics. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

STATEMENT OF EXPECTATION FOR GRAND CANYON UNIVERSITY FACULTY

v.19 - READ: "For God was pleased to have all his fullness dwell in him,"

I include my own comments interleaved after the applicable paragraphs. The uncommented version is available in PDF format:aquinas on Liberty

Personal Bible Study-97 Galatians 4:16 It really is all about Truth.5 (Excursus: The Need for Philosophical Realism)

Made to love: the truth and beauty of love

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

James V. Schall characteristically introduces. Unserious Docility. Thomas P. Harmon

QUESTION 69. The Beatitudes

State Crisis and Civil Consciousness in Greece. A pilot study of Multiple Modernities

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between

RCIA CLASS 4 OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GOD, FATHER, SON AND HOLY SPIRIT

TOPIC 27: MORALITY OF HUMAN ACTS

THE GOD OF QUARKS & CROSS. bridging the cultural divide between people of faith and people of science

The Doctrine of the Covenant and the Immediate Vision and Fruition of the Trinity: The Deeper Protestant Conception

From the fact that I cannot think of God except as existing, it follows that existence is inseparable from God, and hence that he really exists.

Aquinas on Spiritual Change. In "Is an Aristotelian Philosophy of Mind Still Credible? (A draft)," Myles

Religion: Good or Bad?

Lifelong Learning Is a Moral Imperative

Ritual and Its Consequences

Chapter Six. Aristotle s Theory of Causation and the Ideas of Potentiality and Actuality

J. Krishnamurti on Education: Philosophical Perspective. Prakash Bhausaheb Salavi

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

Aquinas & Homosexuality. Five Dominicans Respond to Adriano Oliva

Thomas Aquinas on the World s Duration. Summa Theologiae Ia Q46: The Beginning of the Duration of Created Things

PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE LET THOMAS AQUINAS TEACH IT. Joseph Kenny, O.P. St. Thomas Aquinas Priory Ibadan, Nigeria

The Soul Journey Education for Higher Consciousness

What Does Islamic Feminism Teach to a Secular Feminist?

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

The Gifts of the Holy Spirit. What Are They & What Do They Do?

Prologue: Maps to the Real World

Celebrating the Sacrament of Reconciliation. Archdiocese of Perth 25 August 2014

PHIL 480: Seminar in the History of Philosophy Building Moral Character: Neo-Confucianism and Moral Psychology

The Rationality of Religious Beliefs

but made Himself of no reputation, taking the form of a bondservant, and coming in the likeness of men. And being found in appearance as a man, He

So my heavenly Father will also do to every one of you, if you do not forgive your brother or sister from your heart. (Mt. 18:35)

QUESTION 53. The Corruption and Diminution of Habits. Article 1. Can a habit be corrupted?

Essays in Systematic Theology 45: The Structure of Systematic Theology 1

Practical Wisdom and Politics

Transcription:

Lumen et Vita 8:1 (2017), DOI: 10.6017/LV.v8i1.10503 Aquinas and Alison on Reconciliation with God Elizabeth Sextro Boston College School of Theology and Ministry (Brighton, MA) Abstract This paper compares the concept of reconciliation in the works of Thomas Aquinas and James Alison through a soteriological lens. For both authors, the problem of sin confronts humanity with grave implications for our salvation that cannot be fixed on our own; therefore, Christ must enact a new way for humanity to live in right relationship with God. The paper examines Thomas and Alison s anthropologies through the lens of three questions regarding salvation: What does sin do to the human?; What does Christ have to do because of sin?; and finally, What does Christ enable humans to do in order that we may participate in reconciling ourselves to God? Text Introduction Since the beginning of Christianity, theologians have had to confront the problem of the plight of humanity and how we are to escape our plight through salvation. This paper will examine the anthropologies of Thomas Aquinas and James Alison as they pertain to reconciliation. In order to examine reconciliation through a soteriological lens, I will proceed by asking three questions of both Thomas s and Alison s theological anthropologies: What does sin do to the human?; What does Christ have to do because of sin?; and finally, What does Christ enable humans to do in order that we may participate in reconciling ourselves to God? My aim here is simply to explore what interface might exist in the concept of reconciliation between these two thinkers. Thomas Aquinas: Restoring God s Friendship God s Friendship For Thomas, it is most helpful to view reconciliation in terms of restoration of God s friendship. However, we should begin by briefly reviewing Thomas s anthropology, as it will be necessary for our understanding of human friendship with 40

God. Thomas constructs an anthropology that is hylomorphic, meaning that the human is made up of form and matter: the form is our rational soul, and the matter is our body. He further argues that the rational soul is the higher part of the human over and above the body: Now the human soul is the highest and noblest of forms. Wherefore it excels corporeal matter in its power by the fact that it has an operation and a power in which corporeal matter has no share whatever. This power is called the intellect. 1 Within this hierarchy of soul over body, the soul directs and animates the body. The body remains hierarchically ordered to the soul only to the extent that the soul remains ordered to God. If our intellectual powers are not focused on God, our bodily appetites confuse us and blur our ability to choose the good. Daniel Schwartz argues that for Aquinas, the goal of the human is to remain bonded in friendship with God through conformity of our will to God s. 2 Thomas drawing from an Aristotelian definition of friendship is suggesting that the human use her intellectual powers to seek and know God s will. Though he admits that humans can never fully know God s will, he does posit the following: The will of God cannot be fully known to us. Hence, neither can we fully conform our will to His [sic]. But we can conform to it in proportion to the knowledge which we have [ ]. 3 In other words, since God has created the human with certain functions of the rational soul that can and should naturally lead her back to God, friendship with God is achievable in some sense. Therefore, despite a vast cognitive separateness between ourselves and God, Thomas would say that friendship with God is both possible and desirable. 4 Taken within the framework of God s friendship, we ask our first question. Operating within a Thomistic worldview, what happens to us when we sin? The short answer is that sin disrupts and disorders our friendship with God, but we must look more carefully at the Summa to understand why. Thomas argues that there are three natural goods of human nature. The first is our constitutive principles (such as reason); the second is a natural inclination to virtue ; and the third is the gift of original justice. 5 When sin is introduced, two of the three natural goods are affected: sin diminishes the second natural good (our inclination to virtue) and it completely destroys the third natural good (the state of original justice). 6 However, sin neither diminishes nor destroys our constitutive principles, meaning that our capacity to think, reason, choose, or act are completely maintained. After all, we need these capacities to be able to sin in the first place. 1 Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, I, q. 76, a. 1 (hereafter cited as ST). 2 Daniel Schwartz, Aquinas on Friendship (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2007), 46. 3 Ver. Q. 23 a. 7c. [207-11] as cited in Schwartz, Friendship, 46. 4 Schwartz, Friendship, 125. 5 ST, I-II, q. 85, a.. 1. 6 ST. I-II, q. 85, a. 1. 41

However, we see that sin very much affects the ordering of human habit. In both natural goods that are affected by sin, we observe a change in disposition of our will. As virtue is nothing other than a good habit, for sin to diminish our inclination towards virtue means that it diminishes our disposition to act in a way that is fulfilling to us, meaning that we become more inclined to act in ways that are not fulfilling to us. Thomas s notion of original sin likewise introduces a privation of the good into original justice, thereby completely destroying original justice and forever changing the disposition of the human toward the good. Therefore, our will becomes confused as we become more inclined to act in ways that are not in conformity with God s will. In terms of friendship, Schwartz will argue that every wrong we commit against God damages our friendship with God: God is both the first victim of every wrong and the friend of the offender, inasmuch as she is a potential recipient of His [sic] grace and love. 7 Therefore, sin simply makes acting virtuously more difficult because it confuses our will, making it more difficult to seek, know, and act in conformity with God s will. Reconciliation in Penance The second question we must ask of Thomas is what Christ has to do because of our sin. Aquinas will argue that the redemptive act of Christ s suffering and death is the very cause of our reconciliation to God. 8 There are two reasons for this explanation: Christ s passion takes away our sins that have offended God and damaged our friendship with God; and Christ s passion is an ample sacrifice that appeases God s anger at our sin. 9 It would seem, for Thomas, that there are certain things the human is incapable of doing because our sin has so offended and angered God. Christ s passion, then, acts as the possibility of our reconciliation or restoration of friendship with God. Only Christ s superabundant satisfaction can make possible our satisfaction through penance, which brings us to our third question. How do we participate in reconciliation with God? Thomas will emphasize a sacramental participation in the restoration of God s friendship through penance. Penance describes a series of steps one should go through to amend for one s act of offence against either God and/or a fellow human being. 10 Penance is not only a sacrament, but it is also a moral virtue which re-establishes just relationship between offender and offended. In this case, God is the offended, and we owe God satisfaction for our sins. Satisfaction is defined as a sequence of acts and attitudes 7 Schwartz, Friendship, 142. 8 ST, III, q. 49, a. 4. 9 ST, III, q. 49, a. 4. 10 Schwartz, Friendship, 143. 42

necessary for the offender to atone for his wrongs in the eyes of the victim. 11 As we can see, satisfaction must transform the very way that we act within the world. Our satisfaction, according to Schwartz, is both backward-looking and forwardlooking. It is backward looking in that we seek to restore the situation (as much as we can) that offended God in the first place, and it is forward-looking in that we seek to establish reconciliation with God and reform our own behavior as the offenders. 12 Our satisfactory acts, then, must transform our very intellectual powers so that they again will be re-aligned with God s in hope that we do not continue to offend God by sinning in the future. James Alison: A Girardian Conversion Sin as Complicity James Alison, a contemporary systematic theologian, primarily uses the hermeneutic of René Girard s work to approach the doctrine of original sin in his work The Joy of Being Wrong. In order to fully understand how Alison conceives of reconciliation, we must take a brief look at his Girardian anthropology and the elements within it that will help us to understand our first question: operating within an Alisonian framework, what happens to us when we sin? Girard s theory centers on the scapegoat mechanism: the foundation of which lies in the notion of mimesis; the idea that the I is constituted by the desires of the other. Thus, according to Girardian thought, I am formed by the other in my imitation of the desires of the other. However, in my imitation of the desires of the other, Girard argues that I will never not fall into rivalry with the other. 13 The danger of mimetic rivalry comes in my claim that my desires are absolutely original. I fail to admit the fact that I have modeled the desires of my neighbor, and autonomy of desire is only ever an illusion. Mimetic rivalry manifests itself in a multitude of relational patterns. As it reaches the group level, it transforms into a mimetic crisis. The phenomenon of a mimetic crisis refers to a group dynamic in which rivalries are happening on large scales, and so much tension, hate, and envy builds within the group, that something must be done to relieve the chaos of the war of all against all. 14 The only way a group can relieve itself of chaos is through the election and exclusion of a scapegoat. This person will be someone who is an outcast, someone who perhaps looks or acts differently than the rest of the group. The war of all against all transforms into all against one, meaning that any rivalries that once existed among the group are now morphed into a single energy that must exclude 11 Schwartz, Friendship, 142. 12 Schwartz, Friendship, 143. 13 René Girard, I See Satan Fall Like Lightning (New York: Orbis Books, 2001), 11. 14 Girard, 24. 43

this one scapegoat. After the exclusion, the scapegoat is held up as that which brought peace to the community. In a cathartic moment after the expulsion of the victim, the community feels that order has been restored, and they no longer feel the all-consuming hostility they once did. 15 The life of the continuous cycle relies on the participants unawareness of what is driving them ; otherwise, the cycle might be broken and exposed for what it is. 16 Now, what does this cycle have to do with sin? For Alison, mimesis affects our patterns of relationality with the other. 17 To sin, for Alison, is a falling into the rivalistic desires that find their foundation in mimesis. Of course, imitating the desires of the other is not an inherently bad thing for Alison or Girard: in fact, we have to do so in order to learn fundamental human things such as eating and speaking. However, human desire unavoidably will turn into rivalry and violent exclusion of a victim. Therefore, sin is our complicity in the process of victimization of the other. 18 This represents a major point of contrast between Thomas and Alison: for Thomas, one must actively contradict the properties of her rational soul in order to sin; and for Alison, it is as if we are all-too-easily swept away by sin because of the very pervasiveness of mimetic rivalry. However, I do believe that both Thomas s hylomorphic anthropology and Alison s mimetic anthropology are directly related to these patterns of relationality to which Alison calls our attention. By this, I mean that Thomas is very much concerned with how sin affects our everyday habits, which ultimately affect how we relate to God in friendship, while Alison is concerned with our relationship to victims and how we constantly fall into the role of the victimizer. Jesus as Forgiving Victim and Our Conversion The second question we ask of Alison is: what did Jesus have to do because of this complicity in violent exclusion? For Alison, in Jesus s passion and death, he becomes victim to the cruelty of the cycle of violence, just as all of us do at some point in our lives. However, the Resurrection for Alison is the linchpin of a theory of reconciliation. The Resurrection is Jesus s way of showing us that the death of violent exclusion does not have the last word on human lives. Even further, the Resurrection is a completely gratuitous act. 19 We could imagine that the story of Jesus passion and death could have simply ended with the death, as any other myth would. But the gratuitousness of the Resurrection lies in the fact that Jesus does not 15 Girard, 36-37. 16 Girard, 154. 17 James Alison, The Joy of Being Wrong: Original Sin through Easter Eyes (New York: The Crossroad Publishing Company, 1998), 57. 18 Alison, 39. 19 Alison, 74. 44

take part in the violence of the human story; rather, the Resurrection marks the possibility of a totally new human story. 20 The presence of the Resurrected Jesus was forgiveness as a person. 21 It is God who stands before us a humans, forgiving us for killing him where he could have easily contributed to our violence; this God is radically other from our violence, but shows us that violent exclusion is not the only way for us to be human. In the Resurrection, Jesus forgives our participation in cycles of violence and calls us to a conversion. This brings us to our third and final question for Alison: How does the human partake in reconciliation? She does so by seeing the world with a new kind of intelligence that is constituted by the Resurrection: the intelligence of the victim. Jesus, as the ultimate forgiving victim, has offered us two shifts in perception: first, we discover humans as formed in violence, ; and second, we discover God as entirely without violence. 22 The intelligence of the victim must lead us to these discoveries in order for us to participate God s way of being without violence. I use Alison s words here: It is clear, then, that the intelligence of the victim is not a simple illumination, but a creative and constitutive revelation, creative and constitutive of a new way of being human: as reconciled with each other around the body of the self-giving victim. Furthermore, this creative and constitutive revelation is not seen as something entirely new, but as bringing to light what God had always intended society to be. 23 Reconciliation, then, comes about only through our participation in this new way of being human, a new way apart from death, apart from rivalistic desires, and apart from group-think victimization. Our conversion comes about in recognizing our complicity as victimizers by seeing cycles of violence through the eyes of the victim. For Alison, our patterns of relationality which are so often constituted by rivalry and violence can be transformed by imitation of the only person in history that we can imitate without worry of falling into rivalry: Jesus. Conclusion The value of this project lies in the interface between Thomas and Alison and how humans function as actors in our salvation. In both cases, Jesus enables a new kind of relationality so that we may work to reconcile ourselves with God and 20 Alison, 74. 21 Alison, 75. 22 Alison, 83. 23 Alison, 87. Italics mine. 45

others. In Thomas s case, Jesus s redemptive death makes possible our reconciliation with God through penance. Only Jesus s sacrifice on the cross can appease God s anger, which makes possible our reconciliation with God. For Alison, Jesus s Resurrection makes possible our ability to see the world through the intelligence of the victim. It is only through Jesus s example as the ultimate forgiving victim that we become reconciled to each other in a way that does not include violent means. A valuable point of connection is that both thinkers ask us to make a relational conversion, whether it be vertical or horizontal, as we act as participants in salvation. For both thinkers, we are asked to restore relationship in the manner that God intended. Bibliography Alison, James. The Joy of Being Wrong: Original Sin Through Easter Eyes. New York: The Crossroad Publishing Company, 1998. Aquinas, Thomas. Summa Theologiae. Translated by Fathers of the English Dominican Province. Benziger Bros. edition, 1947. Accessed online at http://www.dhspriory.org/thomas/summa/ index.html. Girard, René. I See Satan Fall Like Lightning. Maryknoll: Orbis Books, 2001. Schwartz, Daniel. Aquinas on Friendship. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2007. 46