WHY RELATIVISM IS NOT SELF-REFUTING IN ANY INTERESTING WAY

Similar documents
Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett

(i) Morality is a system; and (ii) It is a system comprised of moral rules and principles.

10 CERTAINTY G.E. MOORE: SELECTED WRITINGS

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

appearance is often different from reality, and it s reality that counts.

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Henrik Ahlenius Department of Philosophy ETHICS & RESEARCH

Relativism. We re both right.

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

MOORE, THE SKEPTIC, AND THE PHILOSOPHICAL CONTEXT * Wai-hung Wong

Hume s Law Violated? Rik Peels. The Journal of Value Inquiry ISSN J Value Inquiry DOI /s

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis. David J. Chalmers

Naturalist Cognitivism: The Open Question Argument; Subjectivism

Lost in Transmission: Testimonial Justification and Practical Reason

ON JESUS, DERRIDA, AND DAWKINS: REJOINDER TO JOSHUA HARRIS

IS GOD "SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?''

Review of Steven D. Hales Book: Relativism and the Foundations of Philosophy

Review of David J. Chalmers Constructing the World (OUP 2012) David Chalmers burst onto the philosophical scene in the mid-1990s with his work on

5: Preliminaries to the Argument

Prompt: Explain van Inwagen s consequence argument. Describe what you think is the best response

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

R. M. Hare (1919 ) SINNOTT- ARMSTRONG. Definition of moral judgments. Prescriptivism

1/9. Locke on Abstraction

WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Informalizing Formal Logic

Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence. Abstract

Truth and Molinism * Trenton Merricks. Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, 2011.

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

PLEASESURE, DESIRE AND OPPOSITENESS

THE PROBLEM OF CONTRARY-TO-FACT CONDITIONALS. By JOHN WATLING

A CRITIQUE OF THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. A Paper. Presented to. Dr. Douglas Blount. Southwestern Baptist Theological Seminary. In Partial Fulfillment

ZAGZEBSKI ON RATIONALITY

24.00: Problems of Philosophy Prof. Sally Haslanger November 16, 2005 Moral Relativism

Lynch s Metaphysical Pluralism

THE RELATION BETWEEN THE GENERAL MAXIM OF CAUSALITY AND THE PRINCIPLE OF UNIFORMITY IN HUME S THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE

2. Refutations can be stronger or weaker.

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

Are Miracles Identifiable?

PROSPECTS FOR A JAMESIAN EXPRESSIVISM 1 JEFF KASSER

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

PHIL 202: IV:

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

The Kripkenstein Paradox and the Private World. In his paper, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Languages, Kripke expands upon a conclusion

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Instrumental reasoning* John Broome

Judith Jarvis Thomson s Normativity

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Noncognitivism in Ethics, by Mark Schroeder. London: Routledge, 251 pp.

INTERPRETATION AND FIRST-PERSON AUTHORITY: DAVIDSON ON SELF-KNOWLEDGE. David Beisecker University of Nevada, Las Vegas

On The Logical Status of Dialectic (*) -Historical Development of the Argument in Japan- Shigeo Nagai Naoki Takato

Should We Assess the Basic Premises of an Argument for Truth or Acceptability?

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

Scanlon on Double Effect

Final Paper. May 13, 2015

Is Content Holism Incoherent? 1. Kirk A. Ludwig Department of Philosophy University of Florida Gainesville, FL

CHAPTER III. Of Opposition.

THINKING ANIMALS AND EPISTEMOLOGY

METAETHICAL MORAL RELATIVISM AND THE ANALOGY WITH PHYSICS

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth).

Contextualism and the Epistemological Enterprise

FOUNDATIONALISM AND ARBITRARINESS

Self-Evidence in Finnis Natural Law Theory: A Reply to Sayers

NOT SO PROMISING AFTER ALL: EVALUATOR-RELATIVE TELEOLOGY AND COMMON-SENSE MORALITY

Wolterstorff on Divine Commands (part 1)

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE

Comments on Lasersohn

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

Faith and Philosophy, April (2006), DE SE KNOWLEDGE AND THE POSSIBILITY OF AN OMNISCIENT BEING Stephan Torre

1 John Hawthorne s terrific comments contain a specifically Talmudic contribution: his suggested alternative interpretation of Rashi s position. Let m

Philosophers and Scientists Are Social Epistemic Agents. Seungbae Park, Ulsan National Institute of Science and Technology

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

Reason fundamentalism and what is wrong with it John Broome For the Oxford Handbook of Reasons and Normativity, edited by Daniel Star

In Reference and Definite Descriptions, Keith Donnellan makes a

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

by Blackwell Publishing, and is available at

On David Chalmers's The Conscious Mind

C. Exam #1 comments on difficult spots; if you have questions about this, please let me know. D. Discussion of extra credit opportunities

AN EPISTEMIC PARADOX. Byron KALDIS

REASONS-RESPONSIVENESS AND TIME TRAVEL

1. Lukasiewicz s Logic

Philosophy 427 Intuitions and Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2011

Please remember to sign-in by scanning your badge Department of Psychiatry Grand Rounds

Searle vs. Chalmers Debate, 8/2005 with Death Monkey (Kevin Dolan)

Presuppositional Apologetics

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Transcription:

Preliminary draft, WHY RELATIVISM IS NOT SELF-REFUTING IN ANY INTERESTING WAY Is relativism really self-refuting? This paper takes a look at some frequently used arguments and its preliminary answer to the question is: No, not in any interesting way. Of course, much depends on what you mean by relativism and by self-refuting. The first section presents the main, common, features of relativism, and it is followed by sections discussing three types of selfrefutation. First, logical reductio, secondly performative inconsistency, and last the claim that one of the components of relativism, incommensurability, makes a demand that is so strong that there can never be any viable relativism. In each case typical examples of lines of argument arguing the different forms of selfrefutation are discussed, with the expectation that the discussion is of relevance to all forms of that type of self-refutation. RELATIVISM: A PRELIMINARY CHARACTERISATION There are two main features of relativism: relativistic dependence and antagonistic incommensurability. Relativistic Dependence Whatever else relativism is, any form of it includes that something is relative to something else, i.e. a two-place relation. Here we have three components of relativism: something, a relativatum, stands in a relation R-dependence to a relativiser. Relativatum. Some kind of status that is relativised. Most frequent candidates: truth, justification, rationality, existence, meaningfulness. For convenience relativata are extended to the carriers of the status, e.g. for truth: sets of statements, propositions, beliefs, etc. Relativiser. What the relativatum depends on for its relativisation. It is at least at the first glance of a different kind from the relativatum. Some candidates: paradigms, cultures, Lebensforme, classinterest. R-dependence. The relativisation can be of different nature and strength. It is not enough that something is a necessary condition for some status. The relativiser must (partly) control the content of the relativatum,

or the relativiser constitutes or creates the relativatum, or the relativatum is reducible to the relativiser. The contrary opposite of relativistic dependence is absolutism, the idea that there is such a thing as the view from nowhere to use Nagel s metaphor. There are many forms of dependence of course, not all of which are of relevance here. If we stipulate that humans are the only creatures with sufficient mental capacity in the universe, then epistemic justification depends on there being enought oxygen in the atmosphere. That is not a form of dependence that is of interest to philosophical relativism however. What forms of dependence are of interest then? Well, relativism has another typical feature beside dependence, and the kinds of dependence that are relevant to relativism typically are those that can give rise to antagonistic incommensurability. Antagonistic Incommensurability If relativism was a matter of relativistic dependence only, it would hardly be a concern outside of philosophy. What gives relativism its real bite is that it opens the door for antagonistic, incommensurable, alternatives. Two different relativisers might lead to two different relativata that are in relativistic conflict. Antagonism. If two relativata (each R-dependent on its own relativiser) are antagonistic in relation to each other, they are in real conflict. This implies that it is incompatible with (ideal?) rationality to accept both relativata at the same time. Incommensurability. That two relativata are incommensurable implies that there is no neutral, or absolute, way to evaluate which of them is superior with regard to the kind of status involved (more true, better justified etc.). Relativism implies that, due to differences in relativiser, there are or could be, or might have been alternative positions that are at once antagonistic and incommensurable. The contrary opposite of antagonistic incommensurability is universal, intersubjective agreement. REDUCTIO The most evident form av self-refutation is logical reductio ad absurdum. Can it be shown that relativism entails its own negation? For obvious reasons it is relativism about truth (truth is the status that is the relativatum) that is relevant here. A general argument that all forms of relativism are consistent cannot be given for the simple reason that it is quite easy to make up forms of relativism that is self-contradictory in the required sense: Every truth is relative and I mean every single one and that is

absolutely true. This is not a position anyone has wanted to defend, so we just leave it. Thomas Bennigson has attempted to show that even very strong forms of relativism about truth are consistent. 1 This paper takes another route. It attacks a well-known line of argument for the inconsistency of relativism. The idea is that self-contradiction follows from the claim (1) Every truth is relative alone, and surely that is a part of any form of global relativism about truth. You get self-contradiction by self-application. (1) is taken to entail the existence of incommensurable alternatives, which amounts to the claim: (2) For every true statement S, i.e every statement that is true R- dependent on some relativiser R 1, there is another relativiser R 2 R-dependent on which the contrary opposite of S is true If we apply this to (1), which, in the relativistic spirit, must be taken to entail Every truth is relative is true given our relativiser, we get the implication that there is some other relativiser given which (3) Something is absolutely true is true. But (3), if true at all, can only be absolutely true. Therefore, (1) if true, implies (3), i.e. that (1) is false. Therefore global relativism about truth cannot be true. As an argument against relativism this is not useful. There are, at least, five problems. (i) Even if it did work against global relativism about truth, this would still leave us with other, strong varieties of relativism. (ii) Why say that (1) implies (2)? Might not (1) mean only that every truth is relativistically dependent, leaving the question of incommensurable, antagonistic alternative open? (iii) Even if global, incommensurable, antagonism is included in the way (2) suggests, there are other forms of antagonism than contrary opposites, and a reductio cannot be produced from all of them. (Other forms of antagonism is discussed below.) (iv) One could claim that (2) is too strong and what is really implied by (1) is the weaker (2 ) For every true statement S, i.e every statement that is true R- dependent on some relativiser R 1, there could have been another relativiser R 2 R-dependent on which the contrary opposite of S would have been true. But from (2 ) the reductio cannot be derived. (v) Is it really the case that (3), if true, can only be absolutely true? From a relativistic point of view, what (3) in this context is saying is that based on our relativiser there is some other party P, and R-dependent on P s relativiser the claim that something is absolutely true is true, which is to say that (3) is true-r-dependent-on-p s-relativiser and this is based on our relativiser. Of course the members of P think nothing of our relativiser, and from within their relativiser it might well be correct that (3) is absolutely true (which obviously is an observation based on our relativiser). But 1 Bennigson 1999.

what is in question is whether our relativism is self-contradictory, and since, to us, (3) clearly is not absolutely true (nor absolutely false) no reductio can be produced. 2 There is another line of argument against relativism that has some resemblance to this reductio argument. The argument simply is that truth is absolute truth. There is no such thing as truth-for-us. The use in everyday language of expressions like true for us/them is an epistemic or doxastic usage; it refers to what we/they take to be true, not to what really is true. 3 (Thomas Nagel, for one, could be interpreted as invoking this line of argument.) Formally, this argument in beyond the scope of this paper. It does not say that relativism is self-refuting, i e that relativism, once it is stated, immediately destroys itself. It says that relativism about truth cannot even be stated. It is so close to the reductio argument that it is worth hinting some problems with this line of argument however. It can be doubted whether our everyday, working, notion of truth really is absolute truth. A parallel to a version of free will compatabilism is useful here. Admittedly we are easily lead to believe that responsibility and voluntariness are incompatible with determinism, but this is a mistaken impression. Our working criteria of voluntariness were described pretty well already by Aristotle in Nicomachean Ethics 4 and determinism is neither mentioned nor implied there. A similiar line of argument can be used with regard to truth: It is tempting to think that truth is absolute, but if we take a steady look at how our normal notion of truth actually works my personal favorite here is some form of slightly inflated minimalism we will see that it is not tied to absolutism. Even if an absolutistic analysis of our everyday notion of truth were correct, why should this be much of an embarrassment for relativists. Why not simply answer: So what! As Richard Brandt said of R M Hare s attempts (in his earlier works) to derive a normative theory from conceptual analysis. Where is the sting in being denied the use of a certain English expressions? 5 It might be that in ordinary usage truth is absolute truth. So much the worse for ordinary usuage. Relativism just turns into being also a suggestion for linguistic reform. It could be argued that absolute truth must be evidence-transcending truth, and that puts truth beyond our grasp. What we need is a revised notion of truth, relative truth. To really sink relativism about truth you would need some kind of transcendental argument showing that anything doing something like the work our ordinary notion of truth is doing must be of an absolute nature. To the best 2 A similiar argument is used by Tomoji Shogenji (Shogenji 1997) in reply to a formalised version of the reductio argument invoked by Steven Hales (Hales 1997), and by Bennigson 1999 p 221f. 3 Some might be tempted to take a similiar position with regard to existence. 4 Book III Chapt 1. 5 Brandt 1979 p 9.

of my knowledge nobody has even come close to presenting such an argument (though Nagel might have claimed that he has). PERFORMATIVE INCONSISTENCY Another version of the self-refutation argument against relativism is that the relativist falls into performative inconsistency when she asserts a relativistic position, 6 perhaps even when she believes it. Possibly Thomas Nagel could be interpreted as advocating a version of this, saying something along these lines: To assert is to assert that something is true and justified, and to be true and justified is to be absolutely true and absolutely justified, so if you assert global relativism of truth or justification your action contradicts the content of your position. A problem here is that I cannot see that Nagel gives any argument to support that the truth we claim must be absolute truth which probably is a good reason not to interpret Nagel this way. Assertions must abide by the basic rules of communication; notably, what you assert must be of relevance to your audience. But absolute truth is not a necessary condition here. Relative truth will do just as well, if its based on a relativiser you share with your audience (and mutatis mutandis for justification). A more promising version of the performative inconsistency argument against relativism invokes a Principle of Respect PR that is taken to be a part of relativism. PR says that if there is a position P that is an antagonistic and incommensurable alternative to your own position, P must be shown respect. This respect, of course, does not include that you must believe in, or live by, P, but it includes that you cannot claim that your own position is superior to P. If speaker S makes an assertion that p, S, by illocutionary implication, thereby creates an obligation for himself to believe that p and to have sufficiently good reason that p is the case. At the same time S s assertion creates a demand on others; it gives S a prima facie legitimate claim to be believed regarding that p. You must have some special reason to disregard what S says. If you just ignore him this is an insult. Now, this claim on others can be legitimate only if S has good reason to believe that the position that p is superior in truth and justification to its alternatives. It could be argued that combined with PR this creates a performative inconsistency for any relativist that accepts that relativism itself is only relatively true or justified. To assert relativism is to claim the superiority of relativism over its alternatives, and this contradicts the content of relativism, viz. PR. One might even make the case that believing in relativism also involves a performative inconsistency. To believe i.e. to believe rationally and not as just 6 Westacott 2000 uses arguments similiar to those presented in this section.

a totally blind leap of faith is to think that ones own position is superior in truth and justification. This argument might carry some weight as an ad hominem argument against certain individuals holding peculiar relativistic positions, but its useless as an across the board argument against relativism. There is a general problem with all arguments using performative inconsistency. As an example, let me use arguments of this nature that I think really works: G. E. Moore s argument against pyrrhonic scepticism. Anyone advocating this type of scepticism will contradict himself in words and actions. (If we happened to come across a sceptic that actually lived as he preached, we can just sit back; he will be dead within a week.) 7 But is this enough? We only have ad hominem arguments against anyone advocating the sceptical position, but these arguments do not touch the content of the sceptical position itself. We can expose anyone asserting scepticism and staying alive as a fraud, but what the defender of common sense needs to do is to expose scepticism itself. Correspondingly for the performative inconsistency argument against relativism. At best it could have shown that there is something odd about asserting relativism, but that might be only some human, psychological quirk. What the anti-relativist needs to do to be able to sleep well at night is to show that there is something wrong with the content of relativism itself, not just with those asserting relativism. Another weakness of this argument is the idea that PR is a component of relativism. The constituting components of relativism I listed in the first section of this paper, relativistic dependence and antagonistic incommensurability, are neutral with regard to respect of incommensurable alternatives. The attitude prescribed by PR to antagonistic and incommensurable alternatives is compatible with this kernel of relativism, but so is dislike or contempt of, or even open hostility towards, incommensurable alternatives. This means that for every variety of relativism R that contains PR, you can construct an equally consistent, corresponding version R with exactly the same relativistic content, except PR. Furthermore, what kind of claim to superiority does PR really forbid? PR is reasonable if interpreted as a ban on claims to absolute, or neutral, superiority to incommensurable alternatives. The superiority illocutionary invoked in assertions does not have to be absolute or neutral however. Something corresponding to agent-relative values or norms (good for us, right for them) will do nicely. To fulfill his speech-act commitments the speaker has to believe that what he asserts is superior in truth-for-us and justification-for-us (i.e. truth and justification is R-dependent on a relativiser shared by the speaker and his audience). If PR is interpreted this way, and for a relativist it does seem 7 I am aware that this argument is controversial. It is invoked here only to illustrate a certain kind of reasoning. The content of the position is not used in this paper.

to be the natural way to see it, it will not give rise to any performative inconsistency. THE IMPOSSIBILITY OF ANTAGONISTIC INCOMMENSURABILITY Two of the components of relativism, antagonism and incommensurability, pull in different directions. Antagonism pulls towards likeness to be able to contradict each other two positions must have much in common whereas incommensurability draws on difference. This might spell trouble for relativism. One could even argue that this makes relativism self-refuting. One of the demands at the core of relativism, the demand for the existence, or at least the possibility, of antagonistic, incommensurable, alternatives, is, in fact, so strong that it makes relativism impossible. There can never be any antagonistic, incommensurable, alternatives. If two positions are sufficiently different to be incommensurable, they are too different to contradict each other; they will simply be talking past each other. There are at least two kinds of reply the relativist can use here. The first line of defense is to argue that there are other kinds of antagonism beside logical contradicting. When two positions av antagonistic they are not rationally cotenable. If one position asserts that p, an alternative can be antagonistic without asserting, or implying, that not-p. The alternative position might be implying that p lacks truthvalue, or is irrelevant to what is at issue. 8 A more holistic approach is to deny that separate parts of the positions contradict each other individually. The positions are contradicting only as wholes. Or the antagonism might be of a pragmatic nature. The line of action following naturally from a position comes into practical conflict with the actions flowing from another position. The second reply is that there is no lack of examples of logical contradicting between incommensurable positions. Take one of Kuhn s example of incommensurability, the conflict between early Daltonians and pre-dalton chemists. One side was saying/implying that certain methods, results and problems were central, and the other side strictly contradicted this, and vice versa. You could argue that this is only an example of temporary incommensurability, which does not pose any threat to anti-relativism. If the pre-daltonians had known what we know today about the development of modern chemistry they would have been rationally compelled, even from their own point of view, to accept the Daltonian position as superior. Well, perhaps, but there are conflicts of a similiar nature alive today; some of the disagreements in the social sciences between ontological and methodological individualists and collectivistic approaches might be an example. How do we know that this 8 It could be argued that this is possible only if the two positions logically contradict each other at a metalevel.

incommensurability is always only temporary? Is it not an open possibility that the antagonistic incommensurability lingers on, perhaps even deepens. To be a relativist you only have to say that such a development is possible. One of the reasons for taking the combination of antagonism and incommensurability to be a problem is the idea that incommensurability implies incomprehensibility. An incommensurable position does not make sense to its opponents; they fail to completely understand it. This is not implied by the notion of incommensurability presented here though. The core of incommensurable antagonism is that a position is not acceptable to its opponents they might well be able to understand it completely, but they cannot accept it. Another reason is to take incommensurability to always imply differences in meaning. The only relativism available is semantic relativism, and it is rather harmless. When two sides are locked in an incommensurable confrontation they simply mean different things by the central terms in the conflict. Therefore their positions are not really antagonistic; the disagreement is merely verbal. As an example take a candidate for incommensurable ethical conflict: the disagreement between (some versions of) animal rights defenders and those that live by a more antropocentric ethic. This conflict is centred on rights and personhood; are only humans persons (and thereby have the rights associated with personhood). The semantic relativist will say that expressions like rights and person just mean different things to the two sides. Including several species of animals in the class of persons would of course make a difference to what we take to be paradigmatic examples of persons and rights. I doubt that saying that the two sides use the central terms with different meaning is a fruitful way to describe the conflict however. Since it is common, philosophical, wisdom that there is no strict line between meaning and theory, let us, for the sake of the argument, say that there is substantial difference of meaning between the two conflicting parties though. That will not turn the conflict into a harmless matter of wording. The conflict would be about which meaning of right and person is the ethically correct one, and that would be a substantial issue, with wide practical implications. It would not be a harmless matter of just words. anders.tolland@phil.gu.se References Bennigson, T 1999: Is Relativism Really Self-Refuting? Philosophical Studies 94, 1999, pp 211-236 Brandt, R B 1979: A Theory of the Good and the Right Oxford UP Hales, S D 1997: A Consistent Relativism Mind Vol 106 #421, Jan 1997, pp 33-52 Shogenji, T 1997: The Consistency of Global Relativism Mind Vol 106 #424, O 1997, pp 745-747

Westacott, E 2000: Relativism, Truth, and Implicit Commitments International Studies in Philosophy 32:2 pp 95-126