Markie, Speckles, and Classical Foundationalism

Similar documents
ACQUAINTANCE AND THE PROBLEM OF THE SPECKLED HEN

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

Phenomenal Conservatism and the Internalist Intuition

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach

I guess I m just a good-old-fashioned internalist. A prominent position in philosophy of religion today is that religious experience can

Acquaintance and Skepticism about the Past

Direct Realism, Introspection, and Cognitive Science 1

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

EpistemicJustification without Virtue: An Intermittent Rainman Dilemma for Ernest Sosa's Virtue Condition

Let s Bite the Bullet on Deontological Epistemic Justification: A Response to Robert Lockie 1 Rik Peels, Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam.

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology

5AANA009 Epistemology II 2014 to 2015

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism

Belief Ownership without Authorship: Agent Reliabilism s Unlucky Gambit against Reflective Luck Benjamin Bayer September 1 st, 2014

Acquaintance and assurance

Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke,

SKEPTICISM, ABDUCTIVISM, AND THE EXPLANATORY GAP. Ram Neta University of North Carolina, Chapel Hill

Experience and Foundationalism in Audi s The Architecture of Reason

Self-Knowledge for Humans. By QUASSIM CASSAM. (Oxford: OUP, Pp. xiii +

Title II: The CAPE International Conferen Philosophy of Time )

Finite Reasons without Foundations

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Philosophy 125 Day 4: Overview

ABSTRACT: In this paper, I argue that Phenomenal Conservatism (PC) is not superior to

SELLARS AND SOCRATES: AN INVESTIGATION OF THE SELLARS PROBLEM FOR A SOCRATIC EPISTEMOLOGY

Perceptual Reasons. 1 Throughout, we leave out basic, but it should be taken as understood.

PHENOMENAL CONSERVATISM, JUSTIFICATION, AND SELF-DEFEAT

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Craig on the Experience of Tense

PHILOSOPHY 5340 EPISTEMOLOGY

There are two explanatory gaps. Dr Tom McClelland University of Glasgow

Is Klein an infinitist about doxastic justification?

IN SEARCH OF DIRECT REALISM

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

PL 399: Knowledge, Truth, and Skepticism Spring, 2011, Juniata College

Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence. Abstract

What Should We Believe?

4AANB007 - Epistemology I Syllabus Academic year 2014/15

Perceptual Justification and the Phenomenology of Experience. Jorg DhiptaWillhoft UCL Submitted for the Degree of PhD

From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Basic Knowledge and the Problem of Easy Knowledge (Rough Draft-notes incomplete not for quotation) Stewart Cohen

Philosophy 427 Intuitions and Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2011

Lecture 5 Rejecting Analyses I: Virtue Epistemology

Seeing Through The Veil of Perception *

Internalism and Properly Basic Belief. Matthew Davidson, CSUSB Gordon Barnes, SUNY-Brockport

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE

Yuval Dolev, Time and Realism, MIT Press, 2007

PHILOSOPHICAL PERSPECTIVES

Physicalism and Conceptual Analysis * Esa Díaz-León.

On the intentionality-relative features of the world

Varieties of Apriority

Epistemic Circularity and Common Sense: A Reply to Reed

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Class 4 - The Myth of the Given

Skepticism and Internalism

An Ontologically Liberating Skepticism?

17. Tying it up: thoughts and intentionality

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

Divisibility, Logic, Radical Empiricism, and Metaphysics

FOUNDATIONALISM AND ARBITRARINESS

The Problem of the Criterion 1

Notes for Week 4 of Contemporary Debates in Epistemology

Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

Phenomenal Conservatism and the Demand for Metajustification *

EPISTEMOLOGY for DUMMIES

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Externalism and Skepticism

Theories of epistemic justification can be divided into two groups: internalist and

Phenomenal Knowledge, Dualism, and Dreams Jesse Butler, University of Central Arkansas

Foundationalism Vs. Skepticism: The Greater Philosophical Ideology

Précis of Empiricism and Experience. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

MSc / PGDip / PGCert Epistemology (online) (PHIL11131) Course Guide

Is there a distinction between a priori and a posteriori

DO TROPES RESOLVE THE PROBLEM OF MENTAL CAUSATION?

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

Ayer on the argument from illusion

Overcoming Cartesian Intuitions: A Defense of Type-Physicalism

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Phil Notes #9: The Infinite Regress Problem

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

Please remember to sign-in by scanning your badge Department of Psychiatry Grand Rounds

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

RETHINKING THE A PRIORI/A POSTERIORI DISTINCTION

What is Physicalism? Meet Mary the Omniscient Scientist

Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes

Common Sense: A Contemporary Defense By Noah Lemos Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. xvi

General Philosophy. Stephen Wright. Office: XVI.3, Jesus College. Michaelmas Overview 2. 2 Course Website 2. 3 Readings 2. 4 Study Questions 3

foundationalism and coherentism are responses to it. I will then prove that, although

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

How Successful Is Naturalism?

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

Primary and Secondary Qualities. John Locke s distinction between primary and secondary qualities of bodies has

Tom Vinci. Dalhousie University

Transcription:

Markie, Speckles, and Classical Foundationalism In Classical Foundationalism and Speckled Hens Peter Markie presents a thoughtful and important criticism of my attempts to defend a traditional version of foudationalism. That foundationalism claims that there is noninferential justification for S to believe P when S is directly acquainted with the truthmaker for P (the fact that P), the thought that P, and the thought s corresponding to the fact that P. As Paul Moser once reminded me, for that justification to render S s belief justified, S would also have to base his belief that P on the justification he has for believing P. Sosa (2003a and 2003b) appeals to the old example of the way a many speckled hen looks to cast doubt on the kind of traditional foundationalism I put forth. It seems plausible to claim that the surface of a hen with forty-eight speckles can present to me a forty-eight speckled appearance. When it does, I can be directly acquainted with the relevant experience but have no justification for believing that I am appeared to fortyeight-speckled-ly. As Markie points out, even if in such a situation I whimsically believe that the experience is one of forty-eight speckles and through sheer luck arrive at the truth, the belief won t be noninferentially justified. More generally, it seems plausible to claim that when I am acquainted with an experience, that experience might have any number of properties of which I am ignorant. And if this is true, the argument goes, we need more to explain noninferential justification than is offered by the radical foundationalist trying to identify the source of noninferential justification with direct awareness of experience. Now the claim that conscious experience has properties of which I am ignorant is not in itself particularly controversial. No classical foundationalist thinks that in becoming directly aware of an experience one becomes directly aware of all of the properties exemplified by that experience. The experience, for example, has infinitely many relational properties many of which one couldn t discover even through exhaustive empirical investigation. So any defensible form of radical foundationalism claims only that we are sometimes directly acquainted with some of the properties of an experience. The relevant properties are, presumably, non-relational properties characterizing the intrinsic nature of the experience. And even here one must be careful. If one is liberal with one s ontological commitments and one posits a property for every meaningful predicate expression that can be formed, one can come up with complex truth-functional properties (e.g. being blue if not red and orange when it is not either square or not square ) that characterize (in a sense) the intrinsic nature of the experience but which are far too complex for many to grasp in an act of acquaintance. Similarly, the fortyeight speckled appearance is also an experience having the number of speckles equal to the square root of 1104, and relatively few philosophers want to claim that one has direct acquaintance with that property. So all that the classical foundationalist is going to claim is that when one is directly acquainted with an experience, one is often directly acquainted with some of the non-relational properties of that experience. In Speckled Hens and Objects of Acquaintance I presented a menu of responses to Sosa s objection. I proceeded this way because the plausibility of various responses depends on controversial metaphysical presuppositions, about some of which I am agnostic. I suggested, for example, that the appearing theorist might have a response that is not as obviously available to the sense-datum theorist. I argued that there is 1

nothing to prevent an appearing theorist from claiming that it is simply false that when visually experiencing the speckled hen, one is appeared to forty-eight-speckled-ly. Rather, one is appeared to only many-speckled-ly, and when one is directly acquainted with the exemplification of that property as one has the relevant thought and awareness of the relevant correspondence, one has only noninferential justification for believing that one is appeared to many-speckled-ly. Markie claims that such a view is obviously false. He argues in effect that one can count the number of speckles present in the experience and get an inferentially justified belief that there are in fact forty-eight. This claim is tricky, however, in part because it is not clear how the adverbialist even conceives of the presence of speckles in the visual field. In rejecting the sense-datum theory, the adverbialist is rejecting the claim that there is some object that exemplifies phenomenal properties like being blue, being square, having eight sides, or having a surface containing forty-eight speckles. All of these descriptions get converted to adverbs describing the way in which one is experiencing an object. The adverbial theorist denies that my visual field is red or contains forty-eight speckles, and claims instead that I have the non-relational property of being appeared to red-ly or being appeared to forty-eight speckled-ly. Of course, Markie might well respond that any view that implies that we can t count speckles in our visual field is for that reason false, since we obviously can do just that. And although I am sympathetic to an adverbial theory, I am also sympathetic to the idea that the nonrelational properties that constitute having experiences are often complex in a way that allows for necessary connections between, say, being appeared to three-speckled-ly and being appeared to at-least-one-speckled-ly. And I am sympathetic to the claim that one cannot be appeared to many-speckled-ly, in the example at hand, without being appeared to more determinately. Still, as one focuses one s attention on one s experience, the total experience obviously does change--the way in which one is experiencing the world does change. It may be that the only change is a second order relation one bears to features of the experience, but it may also be the case that the first order property of being appeared to a certain way itself changes. It what follows, however, let s consider the view that it is sense data with which we are directly acquainted in experience. (The hyphenated expressions invented by the adverbial theorist are difficult to work with and if we admit that ways of being appeared to have the relevant complexity, we can translate mutatis mutandis the points made below into the adverbial theory). Presupposing that there is some determinate number of speckles present in the visual field, I want to examine more closely Markie s objections to two alternative responses I propose to Sosa s objection. I suggest, in effect, that as one has an experience, one might sometimes be acquainted with certain determinable properties without being acquainted with the determinate properties upon which they supervene. Alternatively, one might argue that while the experience is perfectly determinate in its character, one can only discover a relation of correspondence between the abstract thought of being many-speckled and the determinate state of affairs which involves (as it turns out) having forty-eight speckles. It s not that we can t have the thought of containing forty-eight speckles it s just that we can t discover introspectively the correspondence relation holding between that thought and the fact with which we are acquainted. 2

It seems to me almost a datum that we sometimes know only truths about the determinable character of experience. As I see someone flee the scene of an accident, and I try to reconstruct the experience for the police investigating the incident, I might seem to remember only that the clothing looked a dark color. Now perhaps the relevant visual experience had a perfectly determinate phenomenological character it was either a dark blue datum, dark purple datum, a black datum, and so on. But if we can trust memory, it often doesn t seem to us that we had knowledge of any such determinate property it seems only that we know that our thought was of a dark colored visual datum, a thought we introspectively discovered corresponding to the reality of our experience. Again, there are two alternative accounts of this phenomenon available to the direct acquaintance theorist. On the one account, the explanation is that we had direct acquaintance only with the determinable property of being dark. On the other, we were directly acquainted only with a correspondence between an abstract thought and the determinate character of the experience. As I understand Mackie, he rejects both these views on the grounds that they can t provide a plausible explanation of the fact that through learning one can increase the kinds of empirical truths one can noninferentially know. The idea is that one can get better at discovering (noninferentially) properties of experience. Consider the way in which the character of one s experience of music can change as a result of studying closely the score. Again, one of two things happens. Either the auditory experience itself changes, or one becomes aware of features of the musical experience that were previously hidden. I m inclined to think it is the latter and, therefore, that Mackie is right in claiming that one can, through a learning process, get oneself in a position to know (noninferentially) features of musical experience that were previously epistemically hidden. Now I suggested above that the classical foundationalist can accommodate this phenomenon. You will recall that the direct acquaintance theorist holds only that some properties of experiences can be discovered noninferentially. If there are both determinate and determinable properties, I don t see why one can t be acquainted initially only with determinable properties and later, perhaps as a result of learning, become acquainted with more determinate properties. Markie s complaint is that this foundationlist has no answer to the question of precisely how a learning process results in this expansion of the properties with which one can be acquainted: Given the mysterious, sui generic nature of direct acquaintance, the classical foundationalist has no reply. Our ability to extend the range of our foundationally justified beliefs cannot be fully explained. Markie (correctly) speculates that some classical foundationalist may complain that this criticism demands too much of their view. This foundationlist certainly does. I don t have a causal explanation of why we are (causally) capable of having some thoughts and not others. Nor do I have a causal explanation of why we notice some properties and not others. Markie suggests, however, that there is an important difference between certain forms of externalism (e.g. virtue theory or reliabilism) and acquaintance theories when it comes to explaining how we increase our capacity to form noninferentially justified beliefs. The reliabilist, or 3

the virtue theorist can, in principle, explain how, through learning, one s belief producing processes can evolve in such a way that they increase the kinds of reliably produced beliefs we can form. We can empirically study how people become more responsive (noninferentially) to aspects of their experience. By contrast, we can t empirically study how one can increase the range of properties with which one is acquainted, nor can we study how one can increase direct acquaintance with various thoughts and their correspondence with reality. Now I m not sure I see why one can t empirically study how the range of properties with which we can be directly acquainted is increased. As Markie notes, I have argued that although one cannot define direct acquaintance, one can construct definite descriptions that denote it, and in that way provide a kind of ostensive definition of the concept. I suggested, for example, that we can discover acquaintance when one thinks of situations in which one is in pain, gets distracted for awhile and doesn t notice it, and then becomes aware again of the pain. Direct acquaintance is that relation we had to our pain before and after the distraction. There is a world of difference between merely believing that one is in pain (however reliably produced that belief is) and being aware of pain. A Freudian might become convinced that she has anger of which she is unaware. Believing on theoretical grounds that one has such anger is quite different from actually being aware of the anger felt. Even if as a result of Freudian therapy one somehow comes to be noninferentially responsive to hidden anger with a reliably produced noninferential belief, that isn t the same thing as being directly aware of the anger. Now Markie might argue, of course, that attempts to point at direct awareness fail to pick out the alleged relation. But if I have successfully directed attention to awareness, then I don t see why we can t study the way in which awareness of properties increases under various conditions. To be sure, one will need to rely on subjects reports of their internal states to ascertain that the change in question occurs to ascertain that the explanandum is present. But that presents no special difficulty for the classical foundationalist. The epistemological fact is that even hard core physicalists rely on first-person reports of mental states in their attempt to explain why a person is in one psychological state rather than another (see Fumerton, 2007). But when a person moves from awareness of one sort of property exemplified by experience to awareness of another sort of property exemplified by experience, that change is something of which the person can be introspectively aware. And relying on their first-person reports to conclude that the explanadum is present, we can study the surrounding conditions in an attempt to get the relevant explanation for the change. I certainly don t know what the explanation is, but then it isn t my job, qua philosopher, to explain such things. I m also not sure what the mechanism is that produces belief when one has direct acquaintance with property exemplification. I suspect, however, that if one wants an explanation of how belief-independent, unconditional reliability comes about, one should often turn to acquaintance with properties as at least part of the explanans. 4

References: Fumerton, Richard. 2005. Speckled Hens and Objects of Acquaintance, Philosophical Perspectives 19, 121-39.. 2007. Render Unto Philosophy that which is Philosophy s. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, XXXI, 56-67. Sosa, Ernest. Sosa, Ernest. 2003a. Privileged Access. In Consciousness: New Philosophical Essays, ed. Quentin Smith, 273-92. Oxford University Press. Sosa, Ernest, and Bonjour Laurence. 2003b. Foundations vs Virtues. Blackwell. 5