The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 83, No. 6. (Jun., 1986), pp

Similar documents
Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Philosophical Review.


DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

History of Education Society

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 100, No. 3. (Jul., 1991), pp

Philosophical Review.

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 110, No. 3. (Jul., 2001), pp

Journal of Philosophy, Inc.

Royal Institute of Philosophy

The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 83, No. 5. (May, 1986), pp

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

Commentary on Professor Tweyman's 'Hume on Evil' Pheroze S. Wadia Hume Studies Volume XIII, Number 1 (April, 1987)

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

The Social Atom and Death. J. L. Moreno. Sociometry, Vol. 10, No. 1. (Feb., 1947), pp

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Zimmerman, Michael J. Subsidiary Obligation, Philosophical Studies, 50 (1986):

Let us begin by first locating our fields in relation to other fields that study ethics. Consider the following taxonomy: Kinds of ethical inquiries

Should We Assess the Basic Premises of an Argument for Truth or Acceptability?

DOES STRONG COMPATIBILISM SURVIVE FRANKFURT COUNTER-EXAMPLES?

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

Objective consequentialism and the licensing dilemma

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE

Equality of Resources and Equality of Welfare: A Forced Marriage?

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Hume s Law Violated? Rik Peels. The Journal of Value Inquiry ISSN J Value Inquiry DOI /s

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

Practical Wisdom and Politics

Making Decisions on Behalf of Others: Who or What Do I Select as a Guide? A Dilemma: - My boss. - The shareholders. - Other stakeholders

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik

Altruism, blood donation and public policy:

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1

Ethics. PHIL 181 Spring 2018 SUMMARY OBJECTIVES

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 82, No. 3. (Jul., 1973), pp

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

Realism and the success of science argument. Leplin:

On Some Alleged Consequences Of The Hartle-Hawking Cosmology. In [3], Quentin Smith claims that the Hartle-Hawking cosmology is inconsistent with

Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1

Natural Goodness, Rightness, and the Intersubjectivity of Reason: A Reply to Arroyo, Cummisky, Molan, and Bird-Pollan

Modal Realism, Counterpart Theory, and Unactualized Possibilities

International Phenomenological Society

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

On the Concept of a Morally Relevant Harm

DESIRES AND BELIEFS OF ONE S OWN. Geoffrey Sayre-McCord and Michael Smith

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the. Gettier Problem

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH

Instrumental Normativity: In Defense of the Transmission Principle Benjamin Kiesewetter

4 Liberty, Rationality, and Agency in Hobbes s Leviathan

Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science

Journal of Philosophy, Inc.

Two Approaches to Natural Law;Note

Two Kinds of Moral Relativism

Divine Eternity and the Reduplicative Qua. are present to God or does God experience a succession of moments? Most philosophers agree

SUNK COSTS. Robert Bass Department of Philosophy Coastal Carolina University Conway, SC

New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon

Attfield, Robin, and Barry Wilkins, "Sustainability." Environmental Values 3, no. 2, (1994):

Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social

Many Minds are No Worse than One

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), doi: /bjps/axr026

Realism and instrumentalism

Journal of Philosophy, Inc.

IS GOD "SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?''

A CONSEQUENTIALIST RESPONSE TO THE DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Nicholas R. Baker, Lee University THE DEMANDS OF ACT CONSEQUENTIALISM

SOCRATES, PIETY, AND NOMINALISM. love is one of the most well known in the history of philosophy. Yet some fundamental

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

Virtue Ethics. I.Virtue Ethics was first developed by Aristotle in his work Nichomachean Ethics

Brain Death and Irreplaceable Parts Christopher Tollefsen. I. Introduction

THE ROLE OF COHERENCE OF EVIDENCE IN THE NON- DYNAMIC MODEL OF CONFIRMATION TOMOJI SHOGENJI

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 87, No. 4. (Oct., 1978), pp

PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC AND LANGUAGE OVERVIEW FREGE JONNY MCINTOSH 1. FREGE'S CONCEPTION OF LOGIC

STILL NO REDUNDANT PROPERTIES: REPLY TO WIELENBERG

Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is

Philosophy 1100: Ethics

in Social Science Encyclopedia (Routledge, forthcoming, 2006). Consequentialism (Blackwell Publishers, forthcoming, 2006)

Conditions of Fundamental Metaphysics: A critique of Jorge Gracia's proposal

PHIL 100 AO1 Introduction to Philosophy

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

R. M. Hare (1919 ) SINNOTT- ARMSTRONG. Definition of moral judgments. Prescriptivism

proper construal of Davidson s principle of rationality will show the objection to be misguided. Andrew Wong Washington University, St.

Reliabilism and the Problem of Defeaters

Evidential arguments from evil

Rawls, rationality, and responsibility: Why we should not treat our endowments as morally arbitrary

Four Arguments that the Cognitive Psychology of Religion Undermines the Justification of Religious Belief

Legal Positivism: the Separation and Identification theses are true.

Transcription:

Moral Realism, Moral Conflict, and Compound Acts Holly M. Smith The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 83, No. 6. (Jun., 1986), pp. 341-345. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0022-362x%28198606%2983%3a6%3c341%3amrmcac%3e2.0.co%3b2-9 The Journal of Philosophy is currently published by Journal of Philosophy, Inc.. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/journals/jphil.html. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital repository providing for long-term preservation and access to leading academic journals and scholarly literature from around the world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers, and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission to help the scholarly community take advantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. http://www.jstor.org Fri Mar 28 15:43:57 2008

MORAL CONFLICT COMMENTS AND CRITICISM RIOIU12 REXI ISXI, MOKAL CONFI.ICT, Ah11 CORIPOUND ACTS TORBJ~RNTANNSJ~argues that moral conflict can be generated by just one principle, together with one future moral dereliction." For example, Tannsjo claims, act utilitarianism (AU) yields both the following prescriptions: (1) I ought not to invite a certain friend for dinner. (2) I ought to invite this frier~d for dinner and settle m) dispute with hirn. AU yields both prescriptions in a case where it would maximize utility for me to invite-my-friend-and-settle-our-disputebut where it is sadly true that, if I do invite my friend, I will not settle the dispute but will quarrel with him instead. Tannsjo argues that conflicts such as that between (1)and (2) can be countenanced because they do not undermine moral realism. Moral realism can be interpreted as holding that normative properties are properties possessed by concrete actions. In general there is no reason to expect that a property of a concrete whole should be possessed by each part of it; we do not expect the leg of a table to have a three-foot diameter just because it is a part of a whole (the table itself) that has a three-foot diameter. Similarly we should not expect the concrete act of inviting my friend to dinner to be obligatory just because it is part of a larger concrete act (inviting-my-friend-to-dinner-and-settling-our-dispute)that is obligatoi-y. Thus moral realism can survive, even in the presence of conflicting properties possessed by different concrete acts. Tannsjo defends his acceptance of this form of moral conflict by avowing a radical split between a moral principle's role as a theoreti- * "hloral Conflicts and hlol-al Realisn~," this JOURS.A~., I.XXXII, 3 (hlarch 1985): 113-117. Tannsjii actually emplovs the terms 'rational method of deliheration' and 'criteria of rightness' (114/5). He descrihes himself as following Eugene Bales here [see "Act Utilitarianism: Account of Right-making C:haracteristics or Decision-making Procedure?" Am~rica~l Philosophical Quartrrly, VIII, :'I (July 1971): 257-2651, But this is somewhat misleading. Bales is i~lterested in AL's capacity to guide the decisions of decision-makers who lack adequate infornlation, whereas Tannsjii is interested onlv in cases where decision-making prohlen~s arise from the structure of the rnoral theo17, not from the inadequacies of the decision-maker. I have therefore substituted my own term in place of that used hv Tan~lsjii. Although in the text I argue that a principle's decision-guiding suitability places constraints on its suitahility as a criterion of rightness, I helieve there are limitations to these const~rints. 0022-362X/86/8306/0341/$0~1,50 6 1986 The,lournal of Philosopt~y, Inc.

342 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY ' cal criterion of rightness, and any role it might serve as a decisionmaking guide.' He admits that AU, because it generates incompatible prescriptions in this kind of case, cannot serve as a decision-making guide, but avers that this does not affect its adequacy as a criterion of rightness. But permitting such a radical split between these two roles of a moral principle is misguided, and so too is Tannsjo's proposal. A principle's capacity to serve as a decision-making guide affects its acceptability as a theoretical account of rightness. Since Tannsjo's version of AU cannot be used for making decisions, it cannot be used as a criterion of rightness either. We can begin to see the strong link between decision-making guides and criteria of rightness by asking what sorts of entities can possess the property of rightness. Can natural events, such as rainstorms or late frosts, be right? No: we say that such events and states can be good, but not that they can be right. The reason for this is that such entities are not voluntary-they are not the objects of effective choice. Goodness can apply to entities that are not controlled by choices, but rightness is reserved for entities, namely acts, that are controllable by choosing agents. Thus, despite Tannsjo's attempt to separate a criterion of rightness from questions of decision-making, it is actually built into the concept of rightness that it applies only to entities about which decisions can be made. Indeed, we can press the matter further and note that not even all acts can be properly said to be right. Although my act of returning your lost wallet is right, and your act of thanking me is right, the compound act of my-returningyour-wallet-and-your-thanking-me cannot be right. It cannot be right because there is no single agent who could decide to do this act. Thus rightness may be possessed only by entities that are controllable by a possible single choice.' But why do we need a normative property in addition to goodness? Why is there a special normative property, rightness, reserved for just those entities which can be chosen? The obvious answer is that the criterion of rightness provides the kind of evaluation of choos- It might be thought that the alleged compound act mentioned in this paragraph is not a genuine act, because it is not an event (or sequence of events) involving a single body. But we can see that even compound acts involving a single body may not be the proper objects of moral assessment. Imagine a compound act comprising the separate acts of two persons who successively inhabit the same body (e.g., Locke's prince-and-cobbler case) or comprising the separate simultaneous acts of one body animated by 2 persons (e.g., a split-brain case). We would not say that such compound acts are right or wrong, because no single choice can govern them.

MORAL CONFLICT 343 able events which can form the basis for guiding choices with respect to those events. It is precisely because we need some standard of evaluation to serve this function that we have criteria of rightness in addition to criteria of goodness. Although criteria of goodness may have structural features that disable them for this job, criteria of rightness must be free of such disabilities. Applying this idea to Tannsjo's dinner case shows us, somewhat surprisingly, that a criterion of rightness should not directly evaluate all actions that are objects of agents' possible single choices. A principle that offers too generous a range of evaluations generates conflicting prescriptions and so robs itself of the capacity to guide choices. Thus a principle that tells the agent both that he ought not to invite his friend for dinner and that he ought to invite-the-friendand-settle-their-dispute, delivers evaluations that cannot guide the agent's choice because they cannot both be followed. Tannsjo is mistaken to accept a criterion of rightness which delivers incompatible evaluations. Such a criterion cannot do the ver) job it was needed to do, namely provide a basis for making decisions. Why is Tannsjo willing to accept such a principle, and such a split between the criteria1 and decision-guiding functions of a moral principle? He gves two reasons. First, he claims, we must accept the two prescriptions generated by AU in the above case if we are to adapt our actions to our future moral mistakes, as he believes we must. This thought leads him to accept the prescription not to invite his friend to dinner (gven that he would only quarrel further). But we can adapt our actions to future derelictions without accepting a moral principle that delivers incompatible prescriptions. I have described and argued for such a principle in a previous paper.3 The basic proposal is that moral principles, such as AU, are to be applied only to maximal conjunctive acts. A maximal conjunctive act is, roughly, the most extensive compound act of which it is true that if the agent wanted to perform that compound act, he would. How does this proposal apply in cases such as the one Tannsjo describes? The description of the case suggests that although the agent could perform the compound act of inviting-and-then-quarreling, and also not-inviting-and-not-settling-the-dispute, he could not perform the compound act of inviting-and-then-not-quarreling. No matter how "Doing the Best One Can", in Alvin I. Goldman and.jaegwon Kim, V alz~~s and Morals (Boston: Reiclel, 1978),pp. 18.5-214. This paper was puhlished under the name of "Holly S. Goldman." Tannsjii cites the paper, hut seems to have misunderstood its implications for cases such as the case he descrihes.

344 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY strongly he set himself (now) to invite the friend and then not quarrel with him, in fact, when the time came, he would start a quarrel. Since the compound act of inviting-and-then-not-quarreling is not an act the agent can perform,, it is not available for assessment by AU. Comparing the utilities of the remaining available compound acts results in a prescription to not-invite-and-not-settle. This prescription obviously is fully adapted to the agent's future moral derelictions, just as Tannsjo wants our prescriptions to be. But, since the sub-act of (say) inviting the friend for dinner is only a proper part of the most extensive compound act that the agent can perform at this time, it is not available for direct assessment by AU. Hence it cannot be prescribed, and no incompatible prescriptions can be generated.4 It is worth pointing out that there is an alternative interpretation of Tannsjo's example. Perhaps the agent could bring it about that he invites-the-friend-and-does-not-quarrel, even though it is also true that if he invited the friend, he would then quarrel. How could this be so? It might be true that his inviting the friend would lead to a quarrel-but only because he now would not commit himself strongly enough not to quarrel with the friend once they are together. But the agent could make a strong enough commitment now to avoid the quarrel. In this version of the case, the principle I advocate recommends inviting-and-not-quarreling, since this is the best possible maximal conjunctive act for the agent. This recommendation seems right: agents should not be released from their duties merely because of their current lack of moral motivation. Future failures of motivation are another matter, because they are not under the agent's current control. * In assessing this proposal it is helpful to keep in mind the traditional distinction between objective and subjective rightness. An act is objectively right (according to utilitarianism) if it would actually maximize utility. Thus not-inviting-and-not-settling-the-dispute is the objectively right act. An act is subjectively right (according to utilitarianism) if the agent believes that it can be performed and would maximize utility. But of course agents may be mistaken. If I (falsely) believe I can settle the dispute with my friend and that doing so would maximize utility, then it would be subjectively wrong for me to not-invite-my-friend-and-not-settle-our-disputeeven though this act is objectively right. An act that is subjectively right or wrong possesses its moral status in virtue of the agent's mental state, namely, his or her beliefs about the act's empirical properties. Nonetheless, subjective rightness and wrongness are properties possessed by concrete actions; moral realism can countenance such properties as easily as it can countenance objective rightness or wrongness. Being feared by Michele is no less real a property of, say, a lion than being behind a tree is; by the same token, being subjectively wrong is no less real a property of an act than being objectively wrong is.

k1or4l CONFLICT 345 Thus we can adapt morality's recommendations to future moral derelictions, and still avoid conflicting prescriptions, if we restrict the application of our moral principle to maximal conjunctive acts defined in the way I have suggested. Tannsjo's first reason for accepting principles that generate conflicting prescriptions thus collapses under examination. What about his second reason? The second reason put forward by Tannsjo is that moral realism requires each concrete action to be right or wrong: it is inconsistent with realism that some acts, e.g., sub-acts such as inviting the friend to dinner, have no moral status. On my proposal, such sub-acts do not always have any moral ~tatus.~ But I fail to see that this is damagng to moral realism. Moral realism will be confirmed so long as some acts have moral properties. And we can affirm this without abandoning the important role that moral principles must play as guides for making choices. The existence of moral conflict need not be accepted. University of Arizona HOI.1.Y 51. SMITH MORE ON MORAL DILEMMAS LYLE V. ANDERSON'S "Moral Dilemmas, Deliberation, and Choice,"" is a paper that moves in many directions and attempts to cover much ground. But, sorting through these intricacies, one can see that Anderson sets for himself two major tasks: one is to reject some of the principal claims made by Ruth Barcan Marcus in her recent work on moral dilemmas;+ the other, to "onme do. FOI- example, suppose that A-and-R is a maximal act fol- an agent which is reconimended by his principle at tl, the time of A. He perfornis A, and now is at t,, the time at which R could be pel-formed. If R is not part of any la]-ger compound act within the agent's control, then the moral principle applies to R by itself. But A is nevel- evaluated by the principle. Ure might choose to designate A as right insofal- as it is a part of a conipound that is I-ight, but not insofal- as the principle directly applies to A. * This JOUKNAI., LXXXII, 3 (March 1985): 139-1 62. References to this papel- will be given parenthetically. "hloral Dilemnias and Consistency," this JOURNAL., I.XXVII, 3 (hlarch 1980): 121-136. References to this paper will be given parenthetically. Both the pagination and the context will niake it clear whether the reference is to Anderson 01- to hlarcus. 0022-362X/86/8306/0345$00.50 62 1986 The Journal of Philosophy, Inc.