Further Reflection on True Successors and Traditions

Similar documents
David-Hillel Ruben s Traditions and True Successors : A Critical Reply John Williams, Singapore Management University

True Succession and Inheritance of Traditions: Looking Back on the Debate John Williams, Singapore Management University

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

Privilege in the Construction Industry. Shamik Dasgupta Draft of February 2018

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

QUESTION 47. The Diversity among Things in General

Prejudice and closed-mindedness are two examples of what Linda Zagzebski calls intellectual vices. Here is her list of such vices:

A Logical Approach to Metametaphysics

New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon

Deontology, Rationality, and Agent-Centered Restrictions

There are various different versions of Newcomb s problem; but an intuitive presentation of the problem is very easy to give.

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

Lecture 5 Rejecting Analyses I: Virtue Epistemology

Crehan begins the book by juxtaposing some of Gramsci s ideas alongside those of prominent intellectuals such as Michel Foucault, Gayatri Spivak,

The Problem of Major Premise in Buddhist Logic

Response to Gregory Floyd s Where Does Hermeneutics Lead? Brad Elliott Stone, Loyola Marymount University ACPA 2017

Markie, Speckles, and Classical Foundationalism

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

Anti-intellectualism and the Knowledge-Action Principle

INVESTIGATING THE PRESUPPOSITIONAL REALM OF BIBLICAL-THEOLOGICAL METHODOLOGY, PART II: CANALE ON REASON

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

Lecture 21: Abortion. Rosalind Hursthouse Virtue Theory and Abortion. A doula assisting a woman give birth.

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

Participants: Elliot Temple Justin Mallone Max Kaye

Firth and Hill: Two Dispositional Ethical Theories. Margaret Chiovoloni. Chapel Hill 2006

New people and a new type of communication Lyudmila A. Markova, Russian Academy of Sciences

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

12. A Theistic Argument against Platonism (and in Support of Truthmakers and Divine Simplicity)

Is Adventist Theology Compatible With Evolutionary Theory?

Review of Who Rules in Science?, by James Robert Brown

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

Philosophy Faculty Works

Adam Smith and the Limits of Empiricism

Plato's Epistemology PHIL October Introduction

Do Anti-Individualistic Construals of Propositional Attitudes Capture the Agent s Conceptions? 1

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Experience and Foundationalism in Audi s The Architecture of Reason

The stated objective of Gloria Origgi s paper Epistemic Injustice and Epistemic Trust is:

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law

World Religions: Exploring Diversity

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

Positivism A Model Of For System Of Rules

FREEDOM OF CHOICE. Freedom of Choice, p. 2

Attraction, Description, and the Desire-Satisfaction Theory of Welfare

Philosophy Conference University of Patras, Philosophy Department 4-5 June, 2015

HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD

Rethinking Unreached Peoples

PLANTINGA ON THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. Hugh LAFoLLETTE East Tennessee State University

THE ARETAIC SIGNIFICANCE OF MORAL BELIEFS. Sara Copic. Chapel Hill 2016

Student Outcome Statement

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology

Compromise and Toleration: Some Reflections I. Introduction

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

REVIEW. St. Thomas Aquinas. By RALPH MCINERNY. The University of Notre Dame Press 1982 (reprint of Twayne Publishers 1977). Pp $5.95.

The Ethics of Self Realization: A Radical Subjectivism, Bounded by Realism. An Honors Thesis (HONR 499) Kevin Mager. Thesis Advisor Jason Powell

The Summa Lamberti on the Properties of Terms

Subjective Logic: Logic as Rational Belief Dynamics. Richard Johns Department of Philosophy, UBC

A Contractualist Reply

Postmodal Metaphysics

To appear in Episteme Revised final version, March 17, 2015

Nancey Murphy, Bodies and Souls, or Spirited Bodies? (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006). Pp. x Hbk, Pbk.

THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN SCIENCE, RELIGION AND ARISTOTELIAN THEOLOGY TODAY

Sosa on Epistemic Value

Comments on Van Inwagen s Inside and Outside the Ontology Room. Trenton Merricks

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use

Published in Analysis 61:1, January Rea on Universalism. Matthew McGrath

Philosophy 1100 Honors Introduction to Ethics

TWO APPROACHES TO INSTRUMENTAL RATIONALITY

Time travel and the open future

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

Huemer s Clarkeanism

A Framework for the Good

Contemporary epistemologists often borrow from act

Weronika Wojtanowska. John McDowell s theory of moral sensibility. logos_i_ethos_2016_1_(41), s

6. Truth and Possible Worlds

Against the No-Miracle Response to Indispensability Arguments

The Colorado report: beyond the cheerleading

Cartesian Aseity in the Third Meditation

THE POSSIBILITY OF AN ALL-KNOWING GOD

Moore s paradoxes, Evans s principle and self-knowledge

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

Understanding the burning question of the 1940s and beyond

SPRING 2014 UNDERGRADUATE COURSE OFFERINGS

Four Arguments that the Cognitive Psychology of Religion Undermines the Justification of Religious Belief

Department of Philosophy

to representationalism, then we would seem to miss the point on account of which the distinction between direct realism and representationalism was

Relative and Absolute Truth in Greek Philosophy

Counterparts and Compositional Nihilism: A Reply to A. J. Cotnoir

what makes reasons sufficient?

Knowledge, Language, and Nonexistent Entities

Basic Church Profile Inventory Sample

Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp

The linguistic-cultural nature of scientific truth 1

Confucian Thoughts in Edo Period and Yukichi Fukuzawa

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Transcription:

Singapore Management University From the SelectedWorks of John N. WILLIAMS 2013 Further Reflection on True Successors and Traditions John WILLIAMS, Singapore Management University Available at: https://works.bepress.com/john_williams/95/

Further Reflection on True Successors and Traditions John Williams, Singapore Management University In his Reply to Williams (2013), a response to my David-Hillel Ruben s Traditions and True Successors : A Critical Reply. (2013), David Ruben reports that there is much that we disagree about concerning the nature of true succession. I am not entirely persuaded by what he says of these disagreements. I claimed that in some sense a true successor must be influenced by her predecessor (Williams 2013, 42) and I proposed an analysis of true succession, namely that An individual B is a true intellectual successor of an individual A if and only if B s central ideas were developed after those of A and the central ideas of B are largely consistent with those of A, largely similar to them, yet a valuable advancement over them, because they were influenced by them (Williams 2013, 44). By central ideas I meant not only beliefs but also aims, theories and explanations. Ruben objects, arguing that influence is a not necessary condition for true succession because it is perfectly correct to say that, for example, the true successors of the Luddites are certain groups of anti-global capitalist activists, even if the latter have never heard of the former (Ruben 2013, 8). I am not persuaded, because in his original Traditions and true successors. (2013), Ruben frequently uses true successor as a synonym of faithful successor. This was the sense of true successor I had in mind in my original Confucius, Mencius and the notion of true succession (Williams 1988) in which I reported (Williams 1988, 158) Whalen Lai as supporting the view that Mencius was a true successor of Confucius because he remained faithful to Confucius (Lai 1988, 55). I said that it was proper of Ruben to use true successor as a synonym of faithful successor (Williams 2013, 42). I added that In one sense of true I remain true to my wife insofar as I remain faithful to her. Likewise I remain true to the aims and central beliefs of socialism insofar as I continue to embrace them. But I cannot continue to embrace them if I have never heard of them (Williams 2013, 42). In his recent (2013) rejoinder Ruben does not address this objection. It still seems correct to me. Surely modern anti-global-capitalist activists cannot remain faithful to the ideas of the Luddites if they have never heard of their ideas. Nor, it seems to me, can they remain faithful to these ideas if they are not influenced by them, at least to the extent that an understanding of them results in their adoption. Analogously, my wife has a causal role in my remaining faithful to her. I am faithful to her insofar as I am influenced by her. Of course I might refrain from extra-marital affairs for other reasons, such as fear of scandal, but that would not count remaining faithful in the deepest sense of the word. It seems then that Ruben must either accept that influence 12

is a necessary condition for true succession or abandon his previous position that true successors are faithful successors. Being faithful also explains the need for the true successor s central ideas to be largely consistent with those of her predecessor. Modern anti-global-capitalist activists cannot remain faithful to the central ideas of the Luddites if their own central ideas are not largely consistent with them. Given that true successors are faithful successors, it follows that true successor is a term of praise a conclusion that Ruben seems reluctant to endorse because faithful is certainly a term of praise. Even true considered in isolation seems to be a term of praise or achievement, as in Jack is a true friend, Joan is true to the movement or After adjusting the spokes you ve made the front wheel run true. Moreover we could not find value in being truthful unless we valued saying what is true. I took this to support two claims, first that [e]ven if one does not endorse the value of the ideas of a particular thinker, to say that someone is her true successor or is faithful to her ideas is to say something praiseworthy of the successor and that [i]t is also to say that the successor owes something to her predecessor (Williams 2013, 42). On reflection I am now much less sure of this first claim. It might be objected that we could judge that certain modern neo-nazis are true successors of Hitler, and are faithful to his central ideas. Given that we reject Hitler s ideology, would we judge the modern neo-nazis to be praiseworthy insofar as they are faithful? The answer seems controversial, rather like the question of whether there is anything of intrinsic value in someone s loyalty to a movement one abhors, such as the Ku Klux Klan. A safer claim is that judging someone to be a true or faithful successor of the predecessor involves a commitment to judging her praiseworthy provided the predecessor s central ideas are praiseworthy. Ruben also takes issue with my original claim that If the central ideas of A and B were in fact identical we would say that at worst one was guilty of plagiarism and that at best, by a rare coincidence, independent minds had arrived at the same view. This would clearly rule out true succession, since an integral idea in succession is that, in some sense, the successor is influenced by the predecessor (Williams 1988, 158). He replies that even in the case of the so-called plagiarist, I am not sure that we do not want to rule out as a bona fide example of true succession the sycophant who repeats the master s views in their entirety, albeit with some paraphrase or changed formulation or expression (Ruben 2013, 9). My response is that there are cases and cases. A plagiarist is a kind of thief of ideas, someone who uses a predecessor s ideas as if they were his own. The worst of these does so with no understanding of them. What influences him is not his acceptance of the predecessor s central ideas but the expectation of personal gain from the misappropriation of their outward form. Such a person is not only dishonest but culpably 13

stupid. He is untrue to his predecessor as well as to the pursuit of truth. Like the Great Pretender, he is unworthy of succession. Compare him with a disciple of Confucius who fully understands the central teachings of the Master and who as a result, sincerely and accurately disseminates these, neither adding nor subtracting from them, while scrupulously acknowledging them to be the Master s own. What influences her is her acceptance of the predecessor s central ideas. She surely has more of a claim to be a true or faithful successor. But is the claim enough to be endorsed? Unlike the uncomprehending plagiarist, the disciple has in a sense made the Master s ideas her own, although these remain his as well. But she has not made any theoretical advance. We might call her a true successor, but what succeeds the Master is not anything of any more value than what was succeeded. As Ruben observes, what counts as a theoretical advance might be difficult to decide (Ruben 2013, 9), although other cases are clear-cut. For example, Einstein s ideas were certainly a theoretical advance over Newton s, partly because of their influence. But if a second disciple were to resemble the first yet also make a theoretical advance then surely she would be more praiseworthy still. I think that we need a term to denote such a thinker and I think we sometimes use true successor. We could of course coin another term to denote the first disciple, perhaps true follower, which makes it clear that there need be no ideological development. Ruben gives a second objection to my analysis of true succession: First, I assume the because is the because of causation or explanation. In the case of his account of true successor, it isn t clear whether Williams intends the scope of the explanandum that influence is meant to explain to be (a) similarity or (b) similarity and advancement or (c) just advancement. Influence isn t a good explanation of any of (a)-(c). Influence can cause someone to hold dissimilar ideas: Hegel s idealism was a major influence on Marx s rejection of idealism and adoption of historical materialism. Moreover, certainly some earlier thinker can influence a later thinker to adopt less advanced ideas (Ruben 2013, 8). I think that Ruben has misunderstood me and that I should have been clearer. The because is that of explanation and its scope is meant to be consistency, similarity and advancement. I agree that influence need not be a good explanation of any three, but that it is part of a good explanation is supposed to be stipulated as a necessary condition of true succession. In this respect my analysis is like Linda Zagzebski s analysis of an act of intellectual virtue: An act is an act of intellectual virtue I just in case it arises from the motivational component of I, is something a person with I would characteristically do in the circumstances, and is successful in leading to the immediate end of I and to the truth because of these features of the act (Zagzebski 2000, 175, my italics). 14

A clearer formulation is Williams, John. 2013. Further Reflection on True Successors and Traditions. An individual B is a true intellectual successor of an individual A if and only if B s central ideas were developed after those of A and at least part of the reason why the central ideas of B are largely consistent with those of A, largely similar to them, yet a valuable advancement over them, is that they were influenced by them. Consistency and similarity are independent requirements, because two thinkers may share a common core of ideas, each of which they hold central, while each also holding central another set of ideas that are inconsistent with each other. Likewise a clearer formulation of my original analysis of sameness of intellectual tradition (Williams 2013, 44) is: Group B is in the same intellectual tradition as Group A if and only if B s central ideas were developed after those of A and at least part of the reason why the central ideas of B are largely consistent with those of A and largely similar to them, is because they were influenced by them. This accommodates the fact that a school of thought may, but need not, represent a theoretical advance (Williams 2013, 44), contrary to Ruben s characterization of my original analysis as similarity because influenced by, but without advancement (Ruben 2013, 8). Finally, Ruben raises the interesting case of the true successor who produces a retrograde or degenerate version of an earlier body of ideas. It might be that some of the neo-aristotelians of late antiquity produced a version of Aristotelianism that was less of an advancement and more of a retreat from the classical position of Aristotle. It might have been problematically concessive or eclectic (Ruben 2013, 9). On my view, this case is easily tractable. Such a person is not a true successor because ideas that are retrograde with respect to those central to the predecessor cannot constitute advancement. Moreover, one way in which her ideas may be problematically eclectic is in being an unusual mix that is inconsistent with those central to the predecessor. And surely retrograde degenerate and problematic are not terms of praise, unlike true or faithful successor. Contact details: johnwilliams@smu.edu.sg References Lai, Whalen. 1984. Kao Tzu and Mencius on mind: Analyzing a paradigm shift in classical China. Philosophy East and West 34 (2): 147-160. 15

Ruben, David-Hillel. 2013. Traditions and true successors. Social Epistemology 27 (1): 32-46. Ruben, David-Hillel. 2013. Reply to Williams. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 2 (8): 8-9 Williams, John. 2013. David-Hillel Ruben s Traditions and True Successors : A critical reply. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 2 (7): 40-45. Williams, John. 1988. Confucius, Mencius and the notion of true succession. Philosophy East and West 38 (2): 157-71. Zagzebski, Linda. 2000. Précis of virtues of the mind. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60 (1): 169-177. 16