Your use of the HUME STUDIES archive indicates your acceptance of HUME STUDIES Terms and Conditions of Use, available at

Similar documents
Commentary on Professor Tweyman's 'Hume on Evil' Pheroze S. Wadia Hume Studies Volume XIII, Number 1 (April, 1987)



By J. Alexander Rutherford. Part one sets the roles, relationships, and begins the discussion with a consideration

A Threat Then and Now: Hume, Moral Psychology, and Religion s Moral Failings

Critique of Cosmological Argument



The Riddle of Epicurus

A Hobbist Tory: Johnson on Hume Paul Russell Hume Studies Volume XVI, Number 1 (April, 1990)

Atheism: A Christian Response

David O Connor. Hume on Religion H. O. Mounce Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 2 (November, 2002)

QUESTION 69. The Beatitudes


Inconsistency within a Reconciling Project Antony Flew Hume Studies Volume IV, Number 1 (April, 1978), 1-6.

Living a Spiritual Life: 9. Reading

A Rejection of Skeptical Theism

Going beyond good and evil

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

Today s Lecture. Preliminary comments on the Problem of Evil J.L Mackie

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Table of x III. Modern Modal Ontological Arguments Norman Malcolm s argument Charles Hartshorne s argument A fly in the ointment? 86

Your use of the HUME STUDIES archive indicates your acceptance of HUME STUDIES Terms and Conditions of Use, available at

What God Could Have Made

THE CHICAGO STATEMENT ON BIBLICAL INERRANCY A Summarization written by Dr. Murray Baker

7/31/2017. Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God

Chapter 2--How Do I Know Whether God Exists?

The Quality of Mercy is Not Strained: Justice and Mercy in Proslogion 9-11

Making Biblical Decisions

Philosophy of Religion: Hume on Natural Religion. Phil 255 Dr Christian Coseru Wednesday, April 12

The Chicago Statement on Biblical Inerrancy

Outline of the Apology 1. I. Prologue: knowledge is very valuable, though sometimes esteemed too highly. F, 319

Evidential arguments from evil

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

The Age of Exploration led people to believe that truth had yet to be discovered The Scientific Revolution questioned accepted beliefs and witnessed

Pain, Suffering, and a Benevolent God. Topic: The Problem of Good and Evil


J. L. Mackie The Subjectivity of Values

The Goodness of God in the Judaeo-Christian Tradition

This handout discusses common types of philosophy assignments and strategies and resources that will help you write your philosophy papers.


I John Intro. Purpose Author Date Key Verse Outline

OUR SPIRITUAL GUIDE: The Seven Steps of Inner Silence Leading to Sanctification. by Blessed Luigi Novarese

Camino Santa Maria, St. Mary s University, San Antonio, TX 78228, USA;

Matthew 10: As Jesus prepares His disciples to be His witnesses in the world, He warns them especially of coming persecution.

Lumen Gentium Part I: Mystery and Communion/Session III

Examination of Conscience base on the Theological Virtues

JURISPRUDENCE AND LEGAL THEORY II STUDY NOTES

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

THE ROAD TO HELL by Alastair Norcross 1. Introduction: The Doctrine of the Double Effect.

HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD

WORD MEANING HOW IT INFLUENCES A CHRISTIAN Christians believe that God is:

Correspondence. From Charles Fried Harvard Law School

Living a Spiritual Life: 7. Six Essential Requisites for Spiritual Growth

VERIFICATION AND METAPHYSICS

Rational Answers to Ideological Commitments. Jaafar Sheikh Idris. website

God, Natural Evil and the Best Possible World

Faith and Philosophy, April (2006), DE SE KNOWLEDGE AND THE POSSIBILITY OF AN OMNISCIENT BEING Stephan Torre

DORE CLEMENT DO THEISTS NEED TO SOLVE THE PROBLEM OF EVIL?

Anthony Bosman, PhD 1. Do we need to win arguments to win souls? 2. Can we be certain that God exists? 3. Has science replaced the need for faith? 4.

Defending A Dogma: Between Grice, Strawson and Quine

Sophia Perennis. by Frithjof Schuon

Skepticism is True. Abraham Meidan

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling

Altruism, blood donation and public policy:

Do you have a self? Who (what) are you? PHL 221, York College Revised, Spring 2014

sang a few years back, the Perfect Ten. [Play SRM /22/2014

Argument from Design. Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion. David Hume

Teleological: telos ( end, goal ) What is the telos of human action? What s wrong with living for pleasure? For power and public reputation?

Health Care A Catholic Perspective

JOHNNIE COLEMON THEOLOGICAL SEMINARY. Title KEYS TO THE KINGDOM

Warnings and Encouragement Sermons From Pastoral Rule, Book 3 July 17, 2016

Plato: Phaedo (Selections)

Whence Evil? M. Andorf. Presented to the Fermi Society of Philosophy. December

CATHOLIC KNOWLEDGE BOWL QUESTIONS Topic: Catechism of the Catholic Church by Sr. Francis Cabrini Janvier, IWBS, Incarnate Word Convent, Victoria, TX

For the first cause argument to work god has to be external and eternal. Why? What does causation mean?

This handout follows the handout on The nature of the sceptic s challenge. You should read that handout first.

A Study of Order: Lessons for Historiography and Theology

PART 2: REVELATION GENERAL REVELATION. In the great summery of faith, found in the eleventh chapter of Hebrews, the

Atheism. Objectives. References. Scriptural Verses

The Spirituality Wheel 4

Philosophy of Religion. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Pihlström, Sami Johannes.

The New Being by Paul Tillich

QUESTION 113. The Guardianship of the Good Angels

LIFE BEYOND THE GRAVE

A STUDY ON PRINCIPLES OF TRUE RELIGION, LEO TOLSTOY

AMERICA'S CHRISTIAN HERITAGE 8/6/2017. II Chronicles 7:12-15

2. A Roman Catholic Commentary

Hume on Liberty, Necessity and Verbal Disputes

NON-RELIGIOUS PHILOSOPHIES OF LIFE AND THE WORLD Support Materials - GMGY

Hume on Promises and Their Obligation. Hume Studies Volume XIV, Number 1 (April, 1988) Antony E. Pitson

HOW TO OVERCOME SIN. by Charles G. Finney

the absence of good and the impulse to seek our own desires at the expense of the good of others which often results in suffering.

Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke,

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

Evidence and Transcendence

John D. Caputo s book is one in a new series from Penguin called Philosophy in

Quas Primas - Pope Pius XI

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Transcription:

Streminger: Religion a Threat to Morality Joseph Ellin Hume Studies Volume XV Number 2(November 1989) 295-300. Your use of the HUME STUDIES archive indicates your acceptance of HUME STUDIES Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.humesociety.org/hs/about/terms.html HUME STUDIES Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the HUME STUDIES archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Each copy of any part of a HUME STUDIES transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. For more information on HUME STUDIES contact humestudies-info@humesociety.org or visit: http://www.humestudies.org

Volume XV Number 2 295 Streminger: Religion a Threat to Morality Joseph Ell in The question posed by Gerhard Streminger is, What did Hume think of the effect of religion on morality? Professor Streminger makes an important contribution to our understanding of Hume s views. Streminger demonstrates that, in addition to his critique of the rational basis ofreligion, and his perhaps less well-known critique of the origins of religion in what we may call the dark side of human nature, Hume strongly objected to religion on moral grounds. Religion is a threat to morality, Hume thinks. There is no doubt that this is Hume s view; in fact, as I shall show, Hume s opposition to religion is even more far-reaching than Streminger acknowledges. Though Hume did not write systematically on the subject, Streminger has ingeniously brought some order to Hume s views by arranging them under three heads. I shall, in turn, continue this clarification by summarizing Streminger s report of Hume s criticisms into sixteen propositions, as follows: 1. Because fear of the unknown is the origin of religion, clergy have an incentive to limit knowledge. 2. Religious devotion arises from sorrow and terror (terror is the primary principle of religion [D 225-6]), so clergy have an interest in increasing human misery. 3. Clergy are necessarily hypocrites, who sometimes feign more devotion than they possess, and guard against the natural, cheerful sentiments. 4. The God of common religion is no moral authority because, among His other faults, He is malevolent, vengeful and wicked. 5. Due to His omnipotence and omniscience, He is an object of fear, from whom nothing can be hidden. 6. This dominating God evokes flattery and adulation. 7. Because He is the product of human prejudices, God embodies discordant elements. 8. He unjustly inflicts excessive punishments and contradicts our natural human generosity. 9. False religion leads to an unnatural life and threatens our natural moral sentiments, in that superstitious terror evokes the monkish virtues of mortification and humility. 10. Monotheism especially leads to intolerance,

JOSEPH ELLIN 11. and to the suppression of the love of knowledge and liberty. 12. In order to produce amazement and wonder, and to give value to service to the deity by provoking opposition and ridicule, religion deliberately promulgates absurdities. 13. The product of thisis an obstinate, dogmatic spirit, guided by the rule that the greater the absurdity, the more zealous the advocacy. 14. Absurdities are also promulgated to assure that religious acts are done, not for morality, which, since it is natural and rational cannot be done for God, nor be an object of favour in God s eyes, but for God s sake alone. 15. The consequence of this is that superstition, rites and ceremonies, and not morality, are made the essence of religious observance. 16. By encouraging attention to eternal salvation, religion is likely to extinguish the benevolent affections, rendering its devotees untrustworthy. These are the criticisms. They are rather an odd catalogue of horrors, reflecting, no doubt, Hume s deep dislike of conventional religion as well as his unsystematic treatment of the subject. But what exactly are they criticisms of? Streminger thinks that Hume s target is common religion, established churches, religion found in the world, corruption, popular, vulgar beliefs and practices, etc. Hume s target is thus not religion itself, but a certain degenerate or false form of it, not true but false religion. Thus for Hume there is a form of religion, true religion, which escapes the criticisms, Streminger seems to suggest. But this is a distortion of Hume s views, based on a misreading of Hume s text. There is no evidence that for Hume there is any form of religion which can be identified as true religion. What is supposed to be the distinction between true and false religion? Streminger quotes Hume on the proper office of religion, which is to inculcate good moral order. He quotes a passage, ultimately excised from the History of England, but appearing in the Dialogues: The proper ofice of religion is to regulate the heart of men, humanize their conduct, infise thespirit of temperance, order, and obedience; and as its operation is silent, and only enforces the motives of mortality and justice, it is in danger of being overlooked, and confounded with these other motives. Streminger calls this passage Hume s most explicit description of true religion and claims that it states his Uidea of the effect of true religion on morality. However, this passage is not about true religion at all. Worse, in the Dialogues it is not stated by Hume, but by Cleanthes. 296 Hume Studies

STREMINGER "RELIGION A THREAT TO MORALITY" The passage occurs in Dialogue XI, where Cleanthes is defending the view that Religion, howevercorrupted, is still better than no religion at all (D 219). Why? Because it is a security to momls (D 219). When Philo objects that history shows that religion always gives rise to miseries, Cleanthes replies that this occurs because religion departs from its proper ofice, and so becomes a cover to faction and ambition (D 220). To this defence of religion, Philo responds by listing some of the evils Streminger enumerates. Here, Philo is explicit that he is attacking vulgar superstition, that is, false religion, which he must therefore assume is what Cleanthes has defended and to which Cleanthes has made the proper ofice attribution. Unless Philo has misunderstood Cleanthes' point (an implausible hypothesis), it is not the claim of Cleanthes, much less of Hume, that it is true religion which has the oflice described. On the contrary, it is false religion. Evidence that Philo accepts a form of religion called "true" is found in Dialogue XII, where the term "true religion" occurs twice; once Philo says he venerates it (D 2191, and later he says it does not have the pernicious consequences attributable to religion, as it has commonly been found in the world (D 223). He alsorefers once to the philosophical and rational Kind (D 220) of religion. However, in all these passages, it is not clear that Philo means anything by "true religion" other than philosophy itself, and morality: philosophy being whatever reason can tell us about the question of the origin of the universe, and morality being the set of principles ultimately founded on "inclination" and "the natural motives of justice and benevolence." If that is the case, Philo's -readhume's-attackon falsereligionisinfactan attackon religion, since there is no other kind. There are not four things: philosophy, morality, true religion, and false religion; but only three. It appears that anything which we might commonly understand as religion is on Philo's view false religion, and wholly bad, though Philo -read Hume? - disguises this conclusion by occasionally calling the good things - philosophy and morality -by the name "true religion." This conclusion needs some qualifications, at least if one attributes to Hume the theism of Dialogue XII, in whose first part, one will recall, Philo takes the view that the.dispute between sceptic and theist is wholly verbal, since both agree on the creation of the world by a Divine Being(theexistence0fa DEITYisplainlywcertained by reason [D 2171) and disagree only on whether to call it a "mind" or not. This cautious and limited theism is for Philo the philosophical part of true religion. But what is its relation to the other part, morality? Certainly we should say that for Philo-Hume, sceptical theism supports morality by cleansing the mind of zeal and fervour, thus encouraging open-mindedness and tolerance; and this in contrast with Cleanthes, for whom it is false Volume XV Number 2 297

JOSEPH ELLIN religion which supports morality by imposing on its believers powerful, though misguided, hopes and fears. Beyond this, there is evidently a spiritual element in Philo's religion: he professes that no one pays more profound adomtion to the divine Being (D 214) than himself. Perhaps it is this spirituality which accounts for the title "true religion." Though the first, theistic, part of Dialogue XI1 suggests that "true religion" is so-called because it is founded on true propositions, perhaps one could make the case that "true religion" is called "true" because it is the name of the sentiments of the truly religious person, who has no doctrine. It is not clear what is the extent of the term "superstition" in Hume's usage; certainly standard theological conundrums and the catalogue of natural irnpossibilities he regards as superstitious, but perhaps he would so classify any theological doctrine whatever. If so, the term "Infinite Mind"might best be taken as an invocation of an attitude rather than as a meaningful designator. It may well be Philo'sview that thephilosophical and rational kind (D 220) of religion simply is, not the moral emotions, but the rather different emotions of awe, wonder, adoration, reverence and the like induced by reflecting on the ultimate incomprehensibility of. the universe. Such religion would support morality, for Hume would indeed hold that the truly religious attitude would be proof against the intolerance and enthusiasm he found so appalling among the conventionally religious. Nonetheless, with respect to other parts of morality, Hume might suppose the contrary, for might he not note that reverential contemplation of the Infinite Mind could give rise to attitudes not especially commendable, for example, to an inward-focused selfcentredness and indifference towards others? If so, religion of the philosophical and spiritualizing kind might actually weaken the natural moral sentiments of justice and benevolence. To this point, I have argued that Hume is criticizing religion, and not merely some degenerate, if common, form of it. But just what is it about religion that he is attacking? And is his criticism based on conceptual grounds, that is, on the nature of religion itself, or on inevitable weaknesses of human nature, or is it largely historical? If Hume's account is essentially about the origins of popular religion, it loses much of its apparent generality as a critique. How do we know that religion will not outgrow these origins? Perhaps we are to attribute the moral defects from which popular religion sufferstosome inevitable weaknesses in human nature. But why inevitable? One could say that the very growth ofknowledge which Hume so fervently accusedreligion of opposing, has weakened the grip of terror on the popular mind, and with it the opportunity for crafty priests to prey on superstitious incredulity. Perhaps thisliberation process will continue. Since Hume's 298 Hume Studies

Volume XV Number 2 299 STREMINGER RELIGION A THREAT TO MORALITY critique is directed at organized religion - churches, rites, doctrines -one would like to know whether Hume holds that any organization of worship and conscience is doomed to moral disaster. What evidence might he have for such a claim, if indeed Hume is tempted to make it? One might ask whether there is not contrary evidence that churches, perhaps prompted by Hume-like critiques, can purify themselves from their defects, and help overcome, or at least mitigate, the weaknesses in human nature from which these defects spring? Only if the critique is based on conceptual points can it attain impressive generality, but conceptual points seem to play a small or negligiblerolein Hume s writingson religion. Perhapsit is a conceptual point that beliefin the all-powerful God must induce fear, flattery and the monkish virtues: if you don t cultivate these virtues, you simply don t believe in the Omni-present, no matter what you may think you believe. What we would like from Hume is some conceptual analysis of religion designed to show that anything which we might plausibly call by that name is likely to suffer from the defects he finds in historical religions. We would also like a clearer account of just what it is about religion which, in Hume s view, constitutes the =threat to morality. There is a legitimate question as to just what aspect of religion is Hume s real target. Is it superstitious incredulity? he organization of worship? Priests? Doctrine? Monotheism? Or perhaps the unhappy misalliance of superstition, meaningless ritual, crarty and dishonest clergy, and dogmatically held doctrine, which, it can be argued, has characterized much of Judeo-Christian history? Clearly, any final assessment of Hume s views about religion s relation to morality must be more precise than Streminger s on points such as these. Finally, with respect to the justness of Hume s criticisms, one wants to ask most fundamentally how good a grasp of religion Hume actually possessed. bligion was not an institution for which Hume had much use. He failed to foresee its ability to make peace with the growth of scientific knowledge, exaggerated its reliance on superstition, fear and terror, tendentiously accusedit of trading in ignorance and conniving at the suppression of liberty, and underestimated its ability to purify itself on the moral failings he attributed to it. He missed the significance of its communal function as a source of social unity, and seems only dimly to have grasped its spiritual message. To say this is not to deny that Hume s critique is caustic, brilliant, savage and, for its time, daring. Perhaps the human race would have been better off if religion had never existed; and perhaps we will be better off when its slow death agony finally comes to an end. (I should say parenthetically that I am no longer convinced as I once was, that this is indeed what is occurring.) Yet religion can be an uplifting, moderating, humanizing

Hume Studies JOSEPH ELLIN force. In failing to acknowledge this, Hume s critique, it seems to me, falls short of a balanced or fair accounting. Western Michigan University 1. DavidHume, Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, ed. Norman Kemp Smith (Indianapolis, 1947), 220. Further references ( D ) will be given in parentheses within the body of the text.