Controversial Ethics as a Foundation for Controversial Political Theory

Similar documents
How should I live? I should do whatever brings about the most pleasure (or, at least, the most good)

24.03: Good Food 2/15/17

Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule

No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships

Notes on Moore and Parker, Chapter 12: Moral, Legal and Aesthetic Reasoning

In Defense of The Wide-Scope Instrumental Principle. Simon Rippon

Suppose... Kant. The Good Will. Kant Three Propositions

A Framework for the Good

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

the negative reason existential fallacy

The Discount Rate of Well-Being

Beyond Objectivism and Subjectivism. Derek Parfit s two volume work On What Matters is, as many philosophers

Kihyun Lee (Department of Philosophy, Seoul National University)

Consequentialism, Incoherence and Choice. Rejoinder to a Rejoinder.

The view that all of our actions are done in self-interest is called psychological egoism.

Criticizing Arguments

Ethical non-naturalism

Attraction, Description, and the Desire-Satisfaction Theory of Welfare

IS ACT-UTILITARIANISM SELF-DEFEATING?

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

Utilitarianism. But what is meant by intrinsically good and instrumentally good?

Lecture 2: What Ethics is Not. Jim Pryor Guidelines on Reading Philosophy Peter Singer What Ethics is Not

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY

Disvalue in nature and intervention *

SATISFICING CONSEQUENTIALISM AND SCALAR CONSEQUENTIALISM

World Hunger and Poverty

What should I believe? Only what I have evidence for.

Most philosophy books, it s fair to say, contain more footnotes than graphs. By this

Chapter 2 Normative Theories of Ethics

Action in Special Contexts

CONSEQUENTIALISM AND THE SELF OTHER ASYMMETRY

Eating Right: The Ethics of Food Choices and Food Policy Philosophy 252 Spring 2010 (Version of January 20)

DOES CONSEQUENTIALISM DEMAND TOO MUCH?

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6

Philosophy Courses Fall 2016

Why economics needs ethical theory

A CONSEQUENTIALIST RESPONSE TO THE DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Nicholas R. Baker, Lee University THE DEMANDS OF ACT CONSEQUENTIALISM

Divine command theory

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

PLEASESURE, DESIRE AND OPPOSITENESS

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

HOW TO BE (AND HOW NOT TO BE) A NORMATIVE REALIST:

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

Conditionals II: no truth conditions?

Introduction. In light of these facts, we will ask, is killing animals for human benefit morally permissible?

Peter Singer, Famine, Affluence, and Morality

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

Setiya on Intention, Rationality and Reasons

Philosophical Ethics. Distinctions and Categories

In his celebrated article Toward a Reconstruction of Utility and Welfare Economics,

Can Christianity be Reduced to Morality? Ted Di Maria, Philosophy, Gonzaga University Gonzaga Socratic Club, April 18, 2008

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

Moral dilemmas. Digital Lingnan University. Lingnan University. Gopal Shyam NAIR

The Simple Desire-Fulfillment Theory

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

James Rachels. Ethical Egoism

INTRODUCTORY HANDOUT PHILOSOPHY 13 FALL, 2004 INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY---ETHICS Professor: Richard Arneson. TAs: Eric Campbell and Adam Streed.

The cosmological argument (continued)

SUNK COSTS. Robert Bass Department of Philosophy Coastal Carolina University Conway, SC


Routledge Lecture, University of Cambridge, March 15, Ideas of the Good in Moral and Political Philosophy. T. M. Scanlon

A Priori Bootstrapping

24.01: Classics of Western Philosophy

Williams The Human Prejudice

THE CASE OF THE MINERS

Full file at

AN OUTLINE OF CRITICAL THINKING

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to

Well-Being, Disability, and the Mere-Difference Thesis. Jennifer Hawkins Duke University

Virtue Ethics. Chapter 7 ETCI Barbara MacKinnon Ethics and Contemporary Issues Professor Douglas Olena

Oxford Scholarship Online

EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES My Answers

Material objects: composition & constitution

Korsgaard and Non-Sentient Life ABSTRACT

CRITIQUE OF PETER SINGER S NOTION OF MARGINAL UTILITY

Day 3: Consciousness and rational belief

CLIMBING THE MOUNTAIN SUMMARY CHAPTER 1 REASONS. 1 Practical Reasons

J. L. Mackie The Subjectivity of Values

Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social

Psychological and Ethical Egoism

Reasons With Rationalism After All MICHAEL SMITH

Correspondence. From Charles Fried Harvard Law School

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

AS Religious Studies. 7061/1 Philosophy of Religion and Ethics Mark scheme June Version: 1.0 Final

CAN WE HAVE MORALITY WITHOUT GOD AND RELIGION?

Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

Let us begin by first locating our fields in relation to other fields that study ethics. Consider the following taxonomy: Kinds of ethical inquiries

The Role of Love in the Thought of Kant and Kierkegaard

The Conflict Between Authority and Autonomy from Robert Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (1970)

The normativity of content and the Frege point

THREE CHALLENGES TO JAMESIAN ETHICS SCOTT F. AIKIN AND ROBERT B. TALISSE

Judith Jarvis Thomson s Normativity

The Non-Identity Problem from Reasons and Persons by Derek Parfit (1984)

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

Transcription:

STUDIES IN EMERGENT ORDER VOL 7 (2014): 299-306 Controversial Ethics as a Foundation for Controversial Political Theory Jason Brennan 1 Gary Chartier s Anarchy and Legal Order is a defense of a left-libertarian anarchist market society and a critique of statism. Few people in the world are more sympathetic to Chartier s conclusions than I. Indeed, for me, the choice between statism and anarchism ultimately comes down to consequences. I think there is a strong moral presumption in favor of anarchist market societies over the alternatives, and the only way to defeat this presumption is to show that the former won t work. That is, statists need to show that anarchism won t deliver sufficiently good consequences or would be a disaster in practice, while some alternative in the latter set will work much better. So, I am very much Chartier s ideological ally. I think his basic conclusions are probably correct. However, in general, I think his main arguments for these conclusions are not successful, and that will be the focus of my critique here. Chartier s book, in my view, suffers from a major methodological flaw. To explain why, note that here are some possible (though not exhaustive) ways of doing political philosophy: 1. Begin with widely accepted premises, and show that these lead to widely accepted conclusions. 2. Begin with widely accepted premises, and show that these lead to controversial conclusions. 3. Begin with controversial premises, and show that these lead to widely accepted conclusions. 4. Begin with controversial premises, and show that these lead to controversial conclusions. There can be cases where each of these four methods can be acceptable or worthwhile. For example, 1 might be useful for showing the coherence of commonsense thought. 2 might be useful for using the good parts of commonsense thought to undermine the bad parts of commonsense thought. 3 might be useful if we need to explain why something everyone takes for

CONTROVERSIAL ETHICS/CONTROVERSIAL POLITICAL THEORY 300 granted really is true, even if the explanation is less obvious than the thing being explained. And 4 might be good for conceptual exploration, for showing how certain ideas link up, especially if those ideas, while controversial, are prominent in some way. (Many papers on the history of philosophy look like 4.) Still, that said, there s a pretty good case to be made that philosophy should mostly be about method 2 and mostly avoid the other methods, especially method 4. Bryan Caplan refers to philosophers who partake in method 3 as crazy rationalizers, i.e., as philosophers who tend to take conventional morality for granted, but who want to try to defend it using premises less obviously true than the conclusion being defended. He considers Rawls a prime example. Caplan refers to philosophers who take method 4 as crazy rationalists, who begin by taking as self-evident some bizarre moral premise, and then use to deduce bizarre conclusions. He (2013, 11-12) thinks Kant and Rothbard are good examples of this. In contrast, take Peter Singer. Peter Singer advocates a form of utilitarianism that hardly anyone accepts; indeed, a form that seems to fall prey to all of basic objections to utilitarianism we raise in introductory ethics classes. Singer also advocates a wide range of controversial moral claims, such as the view that it is wrong to eat meat, that it is okay to euthanize many newborns, and that it is obligatory to give most of one s income away to charity. But Singer is no crazy rationalist, on Caplan s account. Instead, what makes Singer such an excellent philosopher is that he argues for his controversial conclusions not on the basis of his controversial utilitarianism, but on the basis of commonsense moral thinking. Singer doesn t say, Utilitarianism is true, utilitarianism implies veganism, therefore veganism. Rather, he asks, Hey, do you think it s morally permissible to torture a cat for fun? Once you say no, he then shows how your pre-existing moral commitment against cat torture implies that you should also not be eating meat (except in special circumstances, such as humanely raised and slaughtered meat, or found roadkill, etc.) He doesn t say, Utilitarianism implies you should be giving money to charity. Instead, he asks, Would you agree you have a moral obligation to save a kid next to you from drowning, even if doing so ruined your fancy shoes? When you say yes, he then tries to show this implies you should be feeding starving children rather than buying shoes in the first place. Now, I don t think all of Singer s arguments succeed, but most people, I ve found, can t poke a hole in them. At any rate, Singer is in many respects the model, in my view, of how one ought to do philosophy. He tries to derive interesting, novel ideas from widely shared premises.

STUDIES IN EMERGENT ORDER 301 In contrast, Chartier s book is an instance of method 4 of arguing for controversial conclusions on the basis of controversial premises. In Caplan s terminology, he s a crazy rationalist. Chartier bases his argument against the state on a controversial moral theory that hardly anyone accepts. This moral theory isn t just controversial; it s rightfully controversial, as it has bizarre and implausible implications. What I ll do here is explain what some of the problems are with Chartier s moral foundations. Chartier wants to block the following argument for statism, known as the public goods argument. 1. There are certain public goods (roads, national defense) that are vital and which cannot be provided without the state. 2. If 1, then, at least presumptively, we should have a state. 3. Therefore, at least presumptively, we should have a state. Premise 1 contains both normative and empirical claims. It asserts that certain goods are vital that is, that going without them would be quite bad and that the state is needed to prove those goods. Many libertarians reject the public goods argument. They tend to focus on undermining the empirical assumptions built into premise 1. 2 Chartier instead wants to attack the moral assumptions contained within the premise. To attack this argument, Chartier argues that it is impossible to objectively rank one state of affairs as better than another state of affairs; therefore, there is simply no such thing as the optimal or even the right level of public goods provision. If there is no such thing as the optimal or right level of public goods provision, then we cannot say, he claims, that a state is needed to secure the right level of public goods. How does he get to this conclusion, that it is impossible to objectively rank one set of affairs as better than another? Now, one argument for this that seems at least plausible at first glance is that different states of affairs harm some and help others relative to some privileged baseline, and we cannot usually make trade-offs between different people s welfare. So, for instance, a law that redistributes wealth from the top 5% of income earners to the bottom 5% clearly harms the former for the sake of the latter. However, defenders of the public goods argument aren t much impressed by these kinds of concerns. They claim that providing certain public goods is either Pareto superior or Kaldor-Hicks superior, such that it s always possible to provide public goods in a way that makes everyone better off by his or her own lights. So, for instance, putting a highway through a town might harm some people there. But, if the highway is really worth building, it is Kaldor-Hicks superior, which means we can just compensate the people who were harmed in the first instance by the highway, such that they are now better off with it than without. I don t want the state to put a public park on my land,

CONTROVERSIAL ETHICS/CONTROVERSIAL POLITICAL THEORY 302 but if the state paid me $2 million for my land in order to put a park there, I d be delighted. Chartier doesn t try to defeat the public goods argument primarily by claiming we cannot trade one person s welfare for another. Instead, his attack on the public goods argument is much more radical: He claims that there s no objective ranking of states of affairs even for single individuals, because different aspects of well-being the different things that go into our flourishing or failing to flourish are incommensurable. He claims that there is simply no truth of the matter about whether one friendship is more intrinsically valuable than another, or whether a day spent learning guitar better contributes to our well-being than a day spent learning to weave. Chartier does not mean that making such judgments is difficult; rather, he means the more radical claim that there is no literally no truth of the matter about which goods contribute more to our well-being. However, this seems to me rather deeply implausible. It seems rather obvious to me that a day spent marrying the love of my life better contributes to my overall flourishing or well-being than, say, a day spent watching a movie I slightly enjoy. It seems obvious that a prolonged and deep friendship with someone whom I love and with whom I share a mutual understanding better contributes to my well-being than a casual relationship with an office mate. It seems obvious that my guitar playing a skill I have developed great capacity in over 23 years better contributes to my well-being than my ability to play Super Mario Brothers 3 on occasion. It seems obvious that getting a tenuretrack academic job at a prestigious university something I worked hard to get for many years is better than a day spent picking one s nose. On a collective level, it seems obvious that a world in which everyone is both virtuous and happy is better than a world in which everyone is in a pain amplifier. And so on. There are some hard cases, where I m not quite sure which things matter more for my well-being. There are also cases where I make in hindsight stupid mistakes about what contributes to my well-being, such as dating a particular woman whom I won t name here in my freshman year of college, or buying certain goods I ended up not enjoying much. But, that said, it seems there is no difficulty in recognizing at least some things contribute more to our well-being than others. Now, just because something seems obvious, it doesn t mean it is true. Chartier wants to deny what I and most other people and, probably you, the reader find obvious. Philosophy often challenges commonsense ideas. I myself earn by bread and butter by challenging widely held beliefs.

STUDIES IN EMERGENT ORDER 303 So, we need to see if Chartier has a good argument undermining the apparently obvious claim that some things contribute better to our well-being than others. Unfortunately, as far as I can tell, he doesn t. I (Brennan 2013) have levied this criticism against him previously, and here was his response: The [new classical natural law] theorists, whose position on this issue I share, deny that there is some one thing that welfare or value or wellbeing is. Talk about value (or well-being, etc.) is a way of talking about the various particular reasons for action we actually have. To maintain that friendship, say, is an aspect of welfare is not to say that friendship realizes some independently specifiable quantity called welfare (or something else happiness, pleasure, preference-satisfaction, etc.) but simply that one s participation in friendship is one of the ways in which one s life can go well, and that initiating or enriching a friendship or connecting with a friend is thus something it makes sense to do for its own sake. Suppose friendship, or æsthetic experience, or knowledge, or bodily well-being, mattered just, and to the extent that, it produced or embodied some common element say, some sort of happiness or pleasure. In this case, the common element would provide a yardstick that would make comparative measurement possible. By contrast, absent a common element, there s no basis for comparative measurement. We can say that friendship is valuable, or that play is valuable. But in doing so we re just saying that play and friendship give us reasons for action, not that they do so because they produce or realize something else, something that s really valuable. Sensory pleasure seems valuable in its own right; but knowledge isn t valuable because of its contribution to producing or realizing sensory pleasure. (Chartier 2013) So, Chartier s argument seems to be this: 1. There are many different kinds of intrinsic value that form part of well-being. 2. These values cannot be expressed on a common scale. 3. If 1 and 2, then these values are incommensurable. 4. If values are incommensurable, then there is no truth of the matter about what better contributes to our well-being. 5. Therefore, there is no truth of the matter about what better contributes to our well-being.

CONTROVERSIAL ETHICS/CONTROVERSIAL POLITICAL THEORY 304 Chartier s argument, at bottom, is that in order to think that some things better contribute to our well-being than others, you must be committed to saying that all values can be expressed on a common scale. Now, one person s modus ponens is often another person s modus tollens. Chartier s argument, at best, really just sets up a dilemma: We have to choose between two sets of claims: A. All values can be expressed on some common scale. B. A day spent marrying the love of one s life is not better for one s wellbeing than a day spent picking one s nose, a day spent winning a long-sought victory is not better than day spent shopping for new shoelaces, etc. Chartier finds A unattractive. Let s suppose he is right. Suppose A is an unattractive claim, one that we should all wish not to be committed to. So, let s agree we should want to reject A if we can. The problem, though, is that if Chartier s arguments are valid, then he has shown us, at best, that the cost of rejecting A is accepting B. Since A, however unattractive, is far less intuitively implausible and unattractive than B, I just see Chartier s best argument as proving contrary to his intent that all values can indeed be commensurated or expressed on a common scale. In short, I might not want to be committed to the view that all values can be expressed on a common scale, but if Chartier is right that my belief that marrying the love of my life better contributes to wellbeing than eat a slice of cheese so commits me, then so be it. But I think that s really granting Chartier too much credit. Consider the following two items: 1. A pebble from a beach that I kept as a souvenir after a vacation 2. $1 million Item 1, the pebble, might have intrinsic value for me I value it for its own sake, as a memento. (Suppose for the sake of argument this pebble has no instrumental value at all.) Item 2, the million dollars, has no intrinsic value, suppose, but it has massive instrumental value. Here we have two items with very different kinds of value one thing is valuable in itself, and the other is valuable only as an instrument for securing other values. They are in that sense not commensurable. Yet, I would have no difficulty whatsoever in choosing between the two items it s pretty obvious, once again, that the pebble, though intrinsically valuable, is less valuable to me than a million dollars. Now consider two more items: 1. A very minor scribble on a napkin by Picasso. 2. The life of one million strangers. Again, 1 and 2 have very different kinds of value. 1 has minor aesthetic value, while 2 has major intrinsic value. Here, I have no difficulty seeing 2 as more valuable than 1, even if I cannot express the values on some common scale.

STUDIES IN EMERGENT ORDER 305 This doesn t commit me to saying that all value can be expressed in terms of satisfaction, or pleasure, or utility, or whatnot. Rather, it just seems clear that even though there are many different kinds of value, some things of one kind of value are clearly more valuable than some things of another kind of value. Really, to say that something is valuable is just a roundabout way of saying that we have reason to respond to it in certain ways and to act in certain ways toward it. When I say day spent marrying the love of my life is more valuable than a day spent going to the Museum of Natural History which I somewhat enjoy for the twentieth time, I m just saying (in this case) that I have greater reason to do the former than the latter. Let s explore what I think perhaps mistakenly is one further implication of Chartier s claim that there is literally no truth of the matter about which intrinsic goods contribute more to our well-being. Suppose Chartier is right. Now suppose you are a human being looking to flourish. How would you make rational decisions about what things to pursue? It seems all you can do is put things into three categories disvaluable, indifferent, and valuable. If you more than one thing in the latter category and have to choose among them, you will pretty much have to flip a coin or roll the dice. That is, if your goal is to flourish, and you have the choice between spending the day marrying the love of your life or picking your nose for fun, you are in the position of Buridan s ass. There is by Chartier s hypothesis no rational basis for choosing one over another, given your goals. So you might as well flip a coin. Economics tells us that people have no choice but to choose. We are constantly in situations where we must pick one thing over another. When we do, something will be lost there is an opportunity cost. Yet, economics seems to have significant success in explaining how people behave. If Chartier is right, then economics as an explanatory theory seems to work only because people are in the grip of false theories of value. Somehow, they rank things and make choices based on that ranking. But, according to Chartier, no such rankings exist, except beyond the broad rankings of good, indifferent, and bad. Good things are better than indifferent things, which are better than bad things, but no good thing is better (from the standpoint of well-being) than another good thing. That seems wrong. All this could be accepted, I suppose, if Chartier had a really good argument for his background moral theory. But he doesn t. An unfortunate feature of Chartier s book is that it is rather confident and assertive about its controversial premises. As I ve complained before, Chartier has a tendency to use the words obviously or clearly to demarcate claims that are not obvious or clear. He often dismisses commonly held positions that most smart

CONTROVERSIAL ETHICS/CONTROVERSIAL POLITICAL THEORY 306 people find quite sensible. This will not do. Chartier does not give the reader good grounds to accept his background theory in the first place. I note here in closing that I have explored only one troubling aspect of Chartier s foundational moral theory. I think the theory leads to other problems as well. It would be better for Chartier if he could make his argument against the state without using his moral theory, but, as far as I can see, his arguments depend upon it. Unfortunately, this means statists have little to fear from Chartier s anarchist critique. Notes 1 Georgetown University 2 For an excellent treatment of this, see Schmidtz 1991. References Brennan, Jason. 2013. Gary Chartier, Anarchy and Legal Order, Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. http://ndpr.nd.edu/news/38159-anarchy-and-legal-order-law-and-politicsfor-a-stateless-society/. Caplan, Bryan. 2013. Thoughts on Jason Brennan s The Ethics of Voting, Reason Papers 35: 11-16. Chartier, Gary. 2013. Jason Brennan Did Not Like Gary Chartiers Book. http://bleedingheartlibertarians.com/2013/03/jason-brennan-did-not-like-garychartiers-book/. Schmidtz, David. 1991. The Limits of Government: An Essay on the Public Goods Argument. Boulder: Westview Press.