Argument Mapping. Table of Contents. By James Wallace Gray 2/13/2012

Similar documents
Skim the Article to Find its Conclusion and Get a Sense of its Structure

ARGUMENTS. Arguments. arguments

Handout 2 Argument Terminology

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 1. Background Material for the Exercise on Validity

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Philosophy 1100: Ethics

2. Refutations can be stronger or weaker.

Replies to Hasker and Zimmerman. Trenton Merricks. Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, I.

PHI 244. Environmental Ethics. Introduction. Argument Worksheet. Argument Worksheet. Welcome to PHI 244, Environmental Ethics. About Stephen.

C. Exam #1 comments on difficult spots; if you have questions about this, please let me know. D. Discussion of extra credit opportunities

Overview: Application: What to Avoid:

Example Arguments ID1050 Quantitative & Qualitative Reasoning

1/19/2011. Concept. Analysis

Introduction to Philosophy

Argumentation Module: Philosophy Lesson 7 What do we mean by argument? (Two meanings for the word.) A quarrel or a dispute, expressing a difference

FOLLOWING CHRIST IN THE WORLD

PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy

Pastor-teacher Don Hargrove Faith Bible Church September 8, 2011

The Cosmological Argument for the Existence of God

2016 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions

Ethics and Science. Obstacles to search for truth. Ethics: Basic Concepts 1

Review of Nathan M. Nobis s Truth in Ethics and Epistemology

PHIL-176: DEATH. Lecture 15 - The Nature of Death (cont.); Believing You Will Die [March 6, 2007]

Searle vs. Chalmers Debate, 8/2005 with Death Monkey (Kevin Dolan)

In Defense of The Wide-Scope Instrumental Principle. Simon Rippon

Logic, Truth & Epistemology. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

Hume. Hume the Empiricist. Judgments about the World. Impressions as Content of the Mind. The Problem of Induction & Knowledge of the External World

Introduction to Philosophy

INTERMEDIATE LOGIC Glossary of key terms

Logic Appendix: More detailed instruction in deductive logic

Either God wants to abolish evil and cannot, or he can but does not want to, or he cannot and does not want to, or lastly he can and wants to.

Exposition of Symbolic Logic with Kalish-Montague derivations

Lecture 3 Arguments Jim Pryor What is an Argument? Jim Pryor Vocabulary Describing Arguments

Chapter 2: Two Types of Reasoning

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 2. Background Material for the Exercise on Inference Indicators

What is Debate? Debating vs. Arguing. Formal Debate vs. Informal Debate

Do we have knowledge of the external world?

The Relationship between the Truth Value of Premises and the Truth Value of Conclusions in Deductive Arguments

Recall. Validity: If the premises are true the conclusion must be true. Soundness. Valid; and. Premises are true

A Primer on Logic Part 1: Preliminaries and Vocabulary. Jason Zarri. 1. An Easy $10.00? a 3 c 2. (i) (ii) (iii) (iv)

Elements of Science (cont.); Conditional Statements. Phil 12: Logic and Decision Making Fall 2010 UC San Diego 9/29/2010

Introduction to Analyzing and Evaluating Arguments

By submitting this essay, I attest that it is my own work, completed in accordance with University regulations. Minh Alexander Nguyen

Notes on Business Ethics James W. Gray

PHLA10F 2. PHLA10F What is Philosophy?

Portfolio Project. Phil 251A Logic Fall Due: Friday, December 7

Critical Thinking. The Four Big Steps. First example. I. Recognizing Arguments. The Nature of Basics

Arguments. 1. using good premises (ones you have good reason to believe are both true and relevant to the issue at hand),

Relativism and the Nature of Truth

1.5. Argument Forms: Proving Invalidity

Chapter 2 Reasoning about Ethics

CRITICAL THINKING (CT) MODEL PART 1 GENERAL CONCEPTS

Module 9- Inductive and Deductive Reasoning

Moore on External Relations

Session Two. The Critical Thinker s Toolkit

Chapter 6. Fate. (F) Fatalism is the belief that whatever happens is unavoidable. (55)

Handout Two: Argument Construction in Impromptu Speaking

Notes on Business Ethics James W. Gray

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

Argumentative Writing. 9th Grade - English Language Arts Ms. Weaver - Qrtr 3/4

Inductive Logic. Induction is the process of drawing a general conclusion from incomplete evidence.

Philosophical Arguments

Mr Vibrating: Yes I did. Man: You didn t Mr Vibrating: I did! Man: You didn t! Mr Vibrating: I m telling you I did! Man: You did not!!

In general, the simplest of argument maps will take the form of something like this:

TOK FALLACIES Group 1: Clark Godwin, Kaleigh Rudge, David Fitzgerald, Maren Dorne, Thanh Pham

Philosophy Introduction to Philosophy Jeff Speaks What is philosophy?

Argumentation. 2. What should we consider when making (or testing) an argument?

Academic argument does not mean conflict or competition; an argument is a set of reasons which support, or lead to, a conclusion.

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

This document consists of 10 printed pages.

DOWNLOAD OR READ : WHY GOOD ARGUMENTS OFTEN FAIL MAKING A MORE PERSUASIVE CASE FOR CHRIST PDF EBOOK EPUB MOBI

!Validity!Soundness. Today s Lecture 1//21/10

Introduction Symbolic Logic

Does Morality Require God? 2010 James Gray

Suppressed premises in real life. Philosophy and Logic Section 4.3 & Some Exercises

Adapted from The Academic Essay: A Brief Anatomy, for the Writing Center at Harvard University by Gordon Harvey. Counter-Argument

The Kalam Cosmological Argument provides no support for theism

Validity & Soundness LECTURE 3! Critical Thinking. Summary: In this week s lectures, we will learn! (1) What it is for an argument to be valid.

PHILOSOPHY 5340 EPISTEMOLOGY

The Problem of Evil Chapters 14, 15. B. C. Johnson & John Hick Introduction to Philosophy Professor Doug Olena

Today we are going to look at... it was actually prompted yesterday while I was working on the yard I was also listening to a preacher on the radio.

I. What is an Argument?

Learning from Mistakes Karl Popper and Thomas Kuhn

EXERCISES: (from

A Solution to the Gettier Problem Keota Fields. the three traditional conditions for knowledge, have been discussed extensively in the

Huemer s Problem of Memory Knowledge

Chapter 3: Basic Propositional Logic. Based on Harry Gensler s book For CS2209A/B By Dr. Charles Ling;

Proofs of Non-existence

b) The meaning of "child" would need to be taken in the sense of age, as most people would find the idea of a young child going to jail as wrong.

Since Michael so neatly summarized his objections in the form of three questions, all I need to do now is to answer these questions.

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

It Ain t What You Prove, It s the Way That You Prove It. a play by Chris Binge

Deduction by Daniel Bonevac. Chapter 1 Basic Concepts of Logic

Relevance. Premises are relevant to the conclusion when the truth of the premises provide some evidence that the conclusion is true

Introducing Our New Faculty

IDHEF Chapter 2 Why Should Anyone Believe Anything At All?

Ethics. The study of right or correct behavior

9.1 Intro to Predicate Logic Practice with symbolizations. Today s Lecture 3/30/10

How to Generate a Thesis Statement if the Topic is Not Assigned.

Transcription:

Argument Mapping By James Wallace Gray 2/13/2012 Table of Contents Argument Mapping...1 Introduction...2 Chapter 1: Examples of argument maps...2 Chapter 2: The difference between multiple arguments and multiple premises...6 Chapter 3: The difference between supporting arguments and objections...7 Chapter 4: The difference between objections to conclusions, premises, and arguments...9

Introduction Argument mapping (also known as persuasion mapping or reasoning mapping) is a visual representation of arguments. They can help clarify arguments and help us make important distinctions. I will give examples of argument maps and use them to illustrate the difference between premises and conclusions; multiple arguments and multiple premises; supporting arguments and objections; and objections against conclusions, premises, and arguments. Chapter 1: Examples of argument maps Consider the argument: 1. All men are mortal. 2. Therefore, Socrates is a mortal. An argument map can illustrate this argument in the following way: The map clarifies which statement is a premise and which statement is a conclusion. It illustrates that the premise supports the conclusion by coloring the premise blue and having an arrow point to the conclusion. Although this argument could be persuasive as shown here, it is actually not a complete argument because it's not clear how the fact that all men are mortal relates to the fact that Socrates is mortal. If Socrates is a vampire or god, then the conclusion would seem to be false.

Consider the improved argument: 1. All men are mortal. 2. Socrates is a man. 3. Therefore, Socrates is mortal. This improved argument can be illustrated using the following argument map: This time two premises combine to form a single argument to support the conclusion. There is a line connecting both premises to show that they combine to form a singe argument. This argument is complete because the premises are sufficient to prove the conclusion. If the premises are true, then the conclusion must also be true. Although the two above argument maps make it perfectly clear what the conclusion is, we should keep in mind that premises can be used as conclusions because we often need to justify our premises. Consider that someone might doubt that all men are mortal. In that case we might want to justify the fact that all men are mortal. How can we know such a thing? We could argue the following: 1. If not all men are mortal, then we probably would have found an immortal one by now. 2. We haven't found an immortal one by now. 3. Therefore, all men are probably mortal. Yet, once again we could be asked to justify one of our premises. How do we know that we haven't found an immortal man yet? We could then present the following argument:

1. If we found an immortal man, then it would probably be in the historical record. 2. There are no immortal men in the historical record. 3. Therefore, We probably haven't found an immortal man yet. And again we can provide a justification for one of the premises. How do we know that the historical record would probably mention the existence of an immortal man? We could then present the following argument: 1. People are very interested in immortality. 2. People put things that are very interesting to them in history books. 3. Therefore, if we found an immortal man, then it would probably be in the historical record. All of these arguments can be shown in a single argument map:

This argument map makes it clear what premise is justified by further argumentation. Each of those premises are both premises and conclusions. Keep in mind that (almost all) premises can be further justified and it's not always clear at what point we should stop justifying our premises. At some point we might have to admit that our premises are assumptions that will not be proven by argumentation. That is often satisfactory in a debate when the assumption is shared we need not prove anything in a debate when everyone already agrees with it. Chapter 2: The difference between multiple arguments and multiple premises. Many people give a series of simple arguments rather than a series of premises, and we should keep in mind the difference between the two. Consider the following: 1. Sometimes we find out criminals are innocent after we kill them. 2. Human life has value. 3. Therefore, the United States shouldn't use the death penalty. In this case the two premises are two separate arguments two different and somewhat unrelated reasons used to support the conclusion as is illustrated by this argument map: We should make sure to differentiate two supporting arguments from arguments with multiple premises, such as the following:

1. Sometimes we find out criminals are innocent after killing them. 2. It's better to save a single innocent life from an unjust death penalty than to kill several guilty criminals. 3. Therefore, the United States shouldn't use the death penalty. The argument map for this argument looks like the following: This argument map makes it clear that both premises combine to form a single argument. They are not separate and unrelated reasons to accept the conclusion. They both must be true for us to prove the conclusion is true. Chapter 3: The difference between supporting arguments and objections. Supporting arguments are shown on argument maps in blue and the word support is used to distinguish them from objections. Objections are arguments, just like supporting arguments. Objections are also known as challenges, refutations, or counter arguments. When someone presents us with an assertion, conclusion, or argument; we might disagree with it and provide an argument of our own against it. Objections can be used to show beliefs to be in need of further justification, irrational, counterintuitive, or known to be false. Objections can also be used to show arguments to be logically invalid or unsound.

Consider the following objection: 1. Kicking people can hurt them. 2. Therefore, we should reject the belief that it's never wrong to kick people. An example of an argument map of an objection is the following: This argument map illustrates an argument against a belief. Someone is said to conclude or believe that it's never wrong to kick people and the objection against that belief is that kicking people can hurt them. The objection is shown in pink and the word opposes is used to distinguish it from supporting arguments. However, we aren't justified to reject the belief based on the single premise shown above, which is an incomplete argument. We can expand the objection as the following: 1. People sometimes kick others to hurt them. 2. Sometimes it's wrong to do something to try to hurt people. 3. Therefore, we should reject to belief that kicking people is never wrong. We can represent this argument using the following argument map:

This time two premises are combined to form a single argument against the belief. Chapter 4: The difference between objections to conclusions, premises, and arguments. I've already given an example of an objection to a belief. Objections to conclusions are the same as objections to beliefs. Those are arguments that give us a reason to reject a certain belief. However, we still need to know what objections are that are given to premises and other arguments. Objections to beliefs and conclusions Another example of an objection to a belief is the following: 1. Someone argues that kicking people can hurt them. 2. However, kicking people while sparring in kung fu class is not wrong. 3. Therefore, we should reject the belief that it's always wrong to kick people. This argument can be illustrated by the following argument map:

In this case there is both an argument for and against a conclusion. Objections are generally only considered to be objections when someone actually believes and argues for the belief we object to. Objections to premises One potential shortcoming with objections to beliefs is that other people might have arguments for those beliefs. If we are stuck with an argument for and an argument against a belief, then we still need to know which argument is better. Otherwise it won't be clear if we should accept the belief or not. In that case it is necessary to provide an argument against a relevant premise or argument. If we want to prove a belief to be unjustified, then we not only need an argument against the belief; but we also need to show why the arguments in support of the belief are unjustified. For example, consider someone who argues that Socrates is a mortal because he is a dog. This argument should be rejected, but that does not give us a good reason to reject the conclusion. We need an additional reason to reject the conclusion. Even so, arguments against premises are essentially the same as arguments against conclusions and beliefs. The main difference is simply that a premise of an argument is opposed by an objection. An example of an objection to a premise is the following: 1. Someone argues that it's always wrong to kick people because it's always wrong to hurt people and kicking people hurts them. 2. However, it's not wrong to hurt people when you need to do so to protect yourself. 3. Therefore, we should reject the premise that states that it's always wrong to hurt people.

This objection can be illustrated with the following argument map: Objections to arguments There are two main ways to object to arguments without objecting to a premise. One, we can argue that the opposing argument is logically invalid. Two, we can argue that the premises are not appropriate sufficient to support the conclusion for some other reason. An example of an invalid argument is the following: 1. If Socrates is a man, then he is mortal. 2. Socrates is mortal. 3. Therefore, Socrates is a man.

Am example of an argument map of an objection to this argument is the following:

I will not explain this argument map in detail because I will discuss logical validity in detail later on. However, it should be noted that the objection is further supported by another argument, which is in blue rather than pink. Arguments that support objections are in blue instead of pink, even though they could be considered to be part of the relevant objection. Another example of an objection to an argument without objecting to a specific premise in particular is the following: 1. Someone argues that there is life on another planet in the galaxy; there is no life on another planet in the galaxy; therefore there are other stars in the galaxy. 2. However, it's impossible for contradictions to exist. 3. Moreover, the two premises form a contradiction. 4. Therefore, at least one of the premises must be false. The argument map for this objection looks like the following:

The conclusion of the first argument is true, but that's not good enough. The problem is the argument itself is flawed. We don't know which premise is false, but we don't have to. We know that at least one of the premises has to be false.