Edmund Husserl s Transcendental Phenomenology by Wendell Allan A. Marinay

Similar documents
1.0 OBJECTIVES. Contents. 1.0 Objectives

THE CRISIS OF THE SCmNCES AS EXPRESSION OF THE RADICAL LIFE-CRISIS OF EUROPEAN HUMANITY

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

PROFESSOR FULTON'S VIEW OF PHENOMENOLOGY

Ontology and Phenomenology

For example brain science can tell what is happening in one s brain when one is falling in love

Descartes, Husserl, and Derrida on Cogito

A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES

Summary of Sensorama: A Phenomenalist Analysis of Spacetime and Its Contents

Subjectivity, Objectivity, Intersubjectivity: Phenomenology and Analytical Philosophy 1

The Making of Phenomenology as an Autonomous Discipline

THE FICHTEAN IDEA OF THE SCIENCE OF KNOWLEDGE. by Jean Hyppolite*

Man and the Presence of Evil in Christian and Platonic Doctrine by Philip Sherrard

Philosophy of Consciousness

Structure and essence: The keys to integrating spirituality and science

Chapter 25. Hegel s Absolute Idealism and the Phenomenology of Spirit

Perspectival Methods in Metaphysics

Solipsistic and lntersubjecuve Phenomenology I

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

INTENTIONALITY IN HUSSERL AND HEIDEGGER

Denis Seron. Review of: K. Mulligan, Wittgenstein et la philosophie austro-allemande (Paris: Vrin, 2012). Dialectica

Canadian Society for Continental Philosophy

Heidegger's What is Metaphysics?

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Christian Lotz, Commentary, SPEP 2009 Formal Indication and the Problem of Radical Philosophy in Heidegger

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things:

KNOWLEDGE OF SELF AND THE WORLD

Jacob Martin Rump, PhD Symposium: Contemporary Work in Phenomenology Boston Phenomenology Circle Boston University, 1 April 2016

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

William Meehan Essay on Spinoza s psychology.

MODELS CLARIFIED: RESPONDING TO LANGDON GILKEY. by David E. Klemm and William H. Klink

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

1/12. The A Paralogisms

1/9. The Second Analogy (1)

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

INVESTIGATING THE PRESUPPOSITIONAL REALM OF BIBLICAL-THEOLOGICAL METHODOLOGY, PART II: CANALE ON REASON

Department of Philosophy, UOH. Course code: PH701. Class: M. Phil. Semester: I. Number of credits 4. Method of evaluation:

Heidegger Introduction

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE

Resolutio of Idealism into Atheism in Fichte

Habermas and Critical Thinking

Kant and his Successors

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism

A Philosophical Study of Nonmetaphysical Approach towards Human Existence

Ibuanyidanda (Complementary Reflection), African Philosophy and General Issues in Philosophy

PHILOSOPHY IAS MAINS: QUESTIONS TREND ANALYSIS

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

At the Frontiers of Reality

The Copernican Shift and Theory of Knowledge in Immanuel Kant and Edmund Husserl.

K.V. LAURIKAINEN EXTENDING THE LIMITS OF SCIENCE

Phenomenology. Edmund Husserl ( )

Markie, Speckles, and Classical Foundationalism

1/5. The Critique of Theology

Craig on the Experience of Tense

Response to Gregory Floyd s Where Does Hermeneutics Lead? Brad Elliott Stone, Loyola Marymount University ACPA 2017

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

A RESPONSE TO "THE MEANING AND CHARACTERISTICS OF AN AMERICAN THEOLOGY"

Phenomenology and the Rehabilitation of Philosophy

The Character of Space in Kant s First Critique By Justin Murphy October 16, 2006

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Facticity and Transcendence Across the Disciplines: Phenomenology and the Promise

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Chapter 24. Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel: The Concepts of Being, Non-being and Becoming

Deconstruction and the Transformation of Husserlian Phenomenology

LOOKING FOR INTENTIONALITY WITH HEIDEGGER

Dave Elder-Vass Of Babies and Bathwater. A Review of Tuukka Kaidesoja Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

The Nature of Belief and the Method of Its Justification in Husserl s Philosophy

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 110, No. 3. (Jul., 2001), pp

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins

Important dates. PSY 3360 / CGS 3325 Historical Perspectives on Psychology Minds and Machines since David Hume ( )

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

METAPHYSICS IN DERRIDA AND LEVINAS

1/8. The Schematism. schema of empirical concepts, the schema of sensible concepts and the

EDMUND HUSSERL. Meditations. Cartesian MARTINUS NIJHOFF PUBLISHERS AN INTRODUCTION TO PHENOMENOLOGY DORION CAIRNS. Translated by

The Boundaries of Hegel s Criticism of Kant s Concept of the Noumenal

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

0.1 G. W. F. Hegel, from Phenomenology of Mind

Transcendental Knowledge

Tuesday, September 2, Idealism

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

Title<Aufsätze> Is Philosophy Regional o. Citation Phenomenology (2007), 4:

ABSTRACT of the Habilitation Thesis

Rationalist-Irrationalist Dialectic in Buddhism:

Religious Studies. Name: Institution: Course: Date:

Kierkegaard: A Phenomenologist?

Barry SMITH. (Manchester) THE ONTOLOGY OF EPISTEMOLOGY *

Excerpt from J. Garvey, The Twenty Greatest Philosophy Books (Continuum, 2007): Immanuel Kant s Critique of Pure Reason

Thursday, November 30, 17. Hegel s Idealism

Read, Write, Laugh and Learn: A Student's Perspective

Four Phenomenological Philosophers

The Creation of the World in Time According to Fakhr al-razi

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

Transcription:

Edmund Husserl s Transcendental Phenomenology by Wendell Allan A. Marinay We remember Edmund Husserl as a philosopher who had a great influence on known phenomenologists like Max Scheler, Edith Stein, Martin Heidegger, among others. These abovementioned followers acknowledged their indebtedness to Husserl despite their being unrecognized by Husserl himself. In fact, Stein, as Husserl s secretary, was treated like a slave. Husserl considered Scheler s phenomenology as fool s gold. And not only that, Scheler and Heidegger were referred to as antipodes. Husserl created an opening to Continental philosophy. This opening is called phenomenology a work that would eventually take philosophy beyond the older, tired alternatives of psychologism and formalism, realism and idealism, objectivism and subjectivism. 1 In this paper, I shall attempt to critically expose Husserl s transcendental phenomenology and explore some implications to real-life situations. Phenomenology For Husserl, phenomenology is foundational for all philosophy (i.e. pre - philosophical ). It is a reflexive act that cuts across the normal flow of consciousness to reveal and delineate its eidetic, or essential, structures, i.e. its intentional nature, as the subjective condition for the possibility of all thinking whatsoever, especially science. 2 The phenomenological method is necessarily connected to the fundamental idea of (Kantian) transcendental philosophy that all objects are in principle accessible to consciousness. 3 This goes to say that in phenomenology, consciousness is always consciousness of. All conscious awarenesses are intentional awarenesses; all consciousness is consciousness-of-something. 4 Phenomenology is the special method of the eidetic reduction by means of which the phenomena are described. Through the method of imaginative variation (examples of instantiation and comparative examination), the invariant or eidetic aspects of a particular phenomenon are explicated. 5 In here, we realize that everything is under the domain of consciousness. In other words, nothing can get away from consciousness so that all are subject to its activity. But such consciousness is not operating for its own end. Its function is rather tied to 1 The Essential Husserl: Basic Writings in Transcendental Phenomenology, ed. Donn Welton (Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indianan University Press, 1999), ix. Hereafter Welton. 2 In his introduction, Kenneth Stikkers indicates the differences between Schelerian and Husserlian phenomenology. Cf. Max Scheler, Problems of a Sociology of Knowledge trans. Manfred Frings (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1980), 9. Hereafter Frings. 3 Wolfgang Stegmuller. Main Currents in Contemporary German, British, and American Philosophy (Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company, 1969), 128. Hereafter Stegmuller. For some hints on Hussert s influence from Kant, see also Hebert Spielgelberg. The Phenomenological Movement: A Historical Introduction (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1976), 230. Hereafter Spielgelberg. 4 5 Ibid.

2 something outside of it. For instance, we do not simply think out of nothing and for nothing. Otherwise, we are simply fantasizing or daydreaming or becoming insane. We normally think on something other than our thought. We think of the things before us, that which appear to us, especially those significant to us. Indeed, thinking presupposes something. Husserl s primary concern was the phenomenological investigation of the transcendental ego or the ontological question of Being. His preoccupation is on the questions of method; 6 his entire understanding of Being moves within the contrast between and the complementarity of transcendent entities and the Being of transcendent consciousness. In other words, phenomenology is the rigorous science of all conceivable transcendental phenomena. In itself, it is investigation of horizons. 7 We understand here that phenomenology become an important tool of analysis to knowing the essential characteristics of the things around us. In phenomenology, we know things not just what they are but how they are appearing to us and how we live through them. In phenomenology, we are not doing abstraction. Neither do we come up with abstract realities. Phenomenology gets us involved into the lived-world a world of experience that is within our reach. The real world is the point of departure for our investigation into a deeper reality. True enough, I cannot know what is beyond my capacity to know. My knowledge is no less what I can know. The transcendent and the transcendental Since the distinction between the transcendent and the transcendental is the ultimate conceptual framework for Husserl, the most elemental set of categories in his thought, 8 we should therefore present here their being essentially together. As Caputo points out, the transcendencies are always constituted in and for transcendental consciousness; they rise up for and are given shape in the transcendental. The transcendental, on the other hand, is what it is only in the exercise of the life of the transcendental synthesis by which it constitutes the world of transcendencies. 9 He elaborates, The transcendent is that which transcends our consciousness. It is the plenum which, being other than consciousness, never gives itself up to consciousness; an inexhaustible otherness and fullness which consciousness apprehends now this way, now that; is what always manages to escape consciousness, to overflow it, to be too much for it at any one time. Transcendencies are mundane, empirical realities which give themselves to subjectivity in a complex of presence and absence, of partly filled and partly empty intentions. 6 Frings and Funk present this contention by contrasting Scheler s phenomenology to Husserl s. Cf. Max Scheler, Formalism in Ethics and Non-Formal Ethics of Values: A New Attempt toward the Foundation of an Ethical Personalism trans. Manfred Frings & Roger Funk (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1973), xiv. Hereafter Frings and Funk. 7 Caputo, 206. 8 Caputo, 206. 9 Ibid.

3 Meanwhile, the transcendental does not belong to the world at all. It is not mundane [ ] or empirical, but instead transcends the world; does not transcend the world in a manner of metaphysics, in the sense of belonging to a second, totally other, nonempirical world; is prior to the world, providing the ultimate subjectivity before which the world rises up as a phenomenon; it is in the face of which all objectivity takes shape; is not anything in the world, not anything above the world, but the condition of possibility prior to the world which lets the world be; the center around which the world groups itself, the subject for which the world is object. 10 We are presented here with a complex reality that our limited mind is confronting with. Nonetheless, phenomenology facilitates in understanding the complexity of this reality. The reality may not be that easy to understand, but through phenomenology we are in turn made aware of the process that we are going through. This speaks of the vastness of life. Sometimes, we are at a lost despite our efforts to know what we should do. Yet we continue on searching for the truth; we trust the process that one day, we will arrive to the goal we are desiring. Transcendental-phenomenological reduction Phenomenology, as philosophic discipline, describes its objects instead of constructing explanations. It begins only after the transcendental-phenomenological reduction. 11 Descriptions not preceded by this reduction are not phenomenological. This goes to say that understanding the Husserlian transcendental phenomenology and employing the phenomenological method is to first understand and practice the transcendental-phenomenological reduction. 12 Ricoeur asserts that the phenomenological reduction is presented as the explication of the method practiced in the description of phenomena and simultaneously as the elaboration of a transcendental philosophy implying a genuine metaphysical decision concerning the ontological status of these phenomena and is ultimately concerning the reference of a consciousness to a transcendence. 13 Further, the transcendental reduction entails the eidetic reduction, beginning from the point where consciousness is treated as the field for a seeing, for an 10 Caputo, 205-206. 11 There are different ways of approaching this reduction, in either way, one is led to the question of what had previously seemed self-evident: may follow the Cartesian road of total doubt (wherein we are led to question all presuppositions of human experience) or, may examine one of the traditional philosophic disciplines of logic (by which the presuppositions of judging, of validity and truth become questionable. Cf. Richard Schmitt, Husserl s Transcendental- Phenomenological Reduction in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, vol20, no2, 1959, 238-245 accessed in http://www.jstor.org/discover/10.2307/2104360?uid=3738824&uid=2129&uid=2&uid=70&uid= 4&sid=21102570933167. Hereafter Schmitt. 12 Ibid. 13 Ricoeur, 9.

4 intuitive experiencing. If the transcendental can be looked at, seen, and described, then this intuiting must grasp the transcendental fact in essence. This is why it brings the fiction into play, causes the datum of consciousness to vary imaginatively, and develops experiences in the mode of as if. The fiction is the path from the fact to the eidos of the experienced reality, and it permits our grasping a consciouness as an a priori possibility. 14 This means that we are not putting reality into a box like confining it, classifying it, or putting it under an all-encompassing category. Description is different from definition. This is just like telling our own stories. We normally do the describing of our life rather than defining it. This is so because we are unable to completely remember past events and perfectly picture out what had actually happened. However, when we tell stories in a new way, it does mean we fabricate it (unless we intentionally do so). For an honest to goodness storytelling, it is still the same story but we present it anew. Epoché and reduction proper The phenomenological reduction consists in these two moments of epoché and reduction proper. The moments are internal logical moments and do not refer to two steps that one might take to conclude the procedure as one might do, for example, in waxing a floor: where the first step is to strip off the old wax and the second step is to apply the new wax; steps imply a temporal individuation that is not true of the moments of the phenomenological reduction. Husserl s term, epoché, the negative move whereby we bracket the world, is not a step that we do first in an effort to prepare ourselves for the later step, reduction proper; rather, the bracketing and the move whereby we drive the self back upon itself, the reduction proper, occur together. Taken together, the epoché and the reduction proper comprise the phenomenological reduction since these two moments cannot occur independently. 15 Caputo contends that Husserl introduces transcendental consciousness by means of the epoché or parenthesizing of the objective world. Stated from the side of the object, the epoché means that the actuality of the world is bracketed and we are left only with a world which claims to be real, claims to be objective and actual, but which in fact has been reduced, for the phenomenologist, to a phenomenon. Stated from the side of the subject, epoché means that our belief in the reality of the world is suspended. We abstain from this belief, no longer participate in it. The effect of the epoché is in one sense nothing and in another everything. In one sense, nothing is changed. The world continues to appear precisely as before, and our belief in the world remains in the manner of an act which can be investigated. 16 By epoche, we mean trying to do away our own biases and prejudices about the world around us. This method has something to do with our objective consideration to things themselves. Normally, our knowledge of things clouds our new experiences. For example, if I happen to meet a person from Mindanao, my bias would bring me to a conclusion that the person is a Muslim. But then, it does not necessarily follow. If I would not allow myself to talk to the person and know the facts about him or her, then I 14 Ricoeur, 91. 15 http://www.iep.utm.edu/phen-red/#sh5a. 16 Caputo, 206-207.

5 might only be getting an impression about him or her, a false reality about the person. In effect, I will be missing the truth of his or her person. Meanwhile, who it is that is doing the abstaining directly concerns the moment of the reduction proper. If the epoché is the name for whatever method we use to free ourselves from the captivity of the unquestioned acceptance of the everyday world, then the reduction is the recognition of that acceptance as an acceptance. It is the seeing of the acceptance as an acceptance that is the indication of having achieved a transcendental insight; it is transcendental precisely because it is an insight from outside the acceptedness that is holding us captive. Seeing refers not a knowing that we live in captivation-in-an-acceptedness, but is rather more like the kind of seeing that occurs when one discovers that the mud on the carpet was put there by oneself and not by another, as was first suspected. 17 In connection to the example given above, we realize here that the person is from Mindanao but may not be a Muslim. We acknowledge here that not all those from Mindanao are Muslims, although they can also be. At least, we are certain that we are not sure about the person s religious affiliation. We are able here to distinguish prudently that the person is from Mindanao and maybe or probably be a Muslim. As is quite clear, Husserlian phenomenology, particularly the transcendental phenomenology, constitutes the following characteristics: In phenomenology, consciousness is always consciousness of. All conscious awarenesses are intentional awarenesses; all consciousness is consciousness-of-something. 18 Phenomenology is the special method of the eidetic reduction by means of which the phenomena are described. Through the method of imaginative variation (examples of instantiation and comparative examination), the invariant or eidetic aspects of a particular phenomenon are explicated. 19 For this reason, a direct contact of the knower to the things themselves is essential but not sufficient in itself. 20 Transcendence and transcendental belong essentially together. Transcendencies are always constituted in and for transcendental consciousness; they rise up for and are given shape in the transcendental. 21 On the one hand, the transcendent is that which transcends our consciousness. It is an inexhaustible otherness and fullness which consciousness apprehends now this way, now that. It is what always manages to escape consciousness, to overflow it, to be too much for it at any one time. Transcendencies are mundane, empirical realities which give themselves to subjectivity in a complex of presence and absence, of partly filled and partly empty intentions. On the other, the transcendental does not belong to the world at all. It is not mundane or 17 http://www.iep.utm.edu/phen-red/#sh5a. 18 19 Ibid. 20 Florentino Hornedo, Phenomenology; Knowing with the Whole Self 21 John D. Caputo, Transcendence and the Transcendental in Husserl s Phenomenology in Philosophy Today, Fall, 1979, 206. Hereafter, Caputo.

6 empirical, but instead transcends the world. It is prior to the world, providing the ultimate subjectivity before which the world rises up as a phenomenon; it is in the face of which all objectivity takes shape. The transcendental is not anything in the world, not anything above the world, but the condition of possibility prior to the world which lets the world be. It is the center around which the world groups itself, the subject for which the world is object. 22 Phenomenology is the rigorous science of all conceivable transcendental phenomena. All knowledge should be based on absolutely certain insights. But the rigor of the method of phenomenology is interpreted philosophically rather than in terms of any elaborate, objective procedures of the physical and natural sciences. 23 The natural sciences start from a complex set of presuppositions, frameworks and perspectives of knowledge, but these are not questioned by the sciences themselves. For Husserl, phenomenology is a rigorous, human science precisely because it investigates the way that knowledge comes into being and clarifies the assumptions upon which all human understandings are grounded. 24 Phenomenology begins only after the transcendental phenomenological reduction. Phenomenology, as philosophic discipline, describes its objects instead of constructing explanations. Descriptions not preceded by this reduction are not phenomenological. This goes to say that understanding the Husserlian transcendental phenomenology and employing the phenomenological method is to first understand and practice the transcendental-phenomenological reduction. 25 Transcendental phenomenological reduction is ultimately concerning the reference of a consciousness to a transcendence. Transcendental phenomenological reduction is the process that leads me back to, and enables me to see, my stream of consciousness as transcendental, and the world as a transcendental phenomenon. 26 The phenomenological reduction is presented as the explication of the method practiced in the description of phenomena and 22 Caputo, 205-206. 23 Similarly, Edward Ballad, in the translator s foreword, contends of a more critical awareness of the presupposition of the finality of the scientific ideal of rigor and objectivity. Cf. Paul Ricoeur s Husserl: An Analysis of His Phenomenology (Illinois: Northwestern University Press, 1967), xx. Hereafter Ricoeur. 24 25 Richard Schmitt, Husserl s Transcendental-Phenomenological Reduction in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, vol20, no2, 1959, 238-245 accessed in http://www.jstor.org/discover/10.2307/2104360?uid=3738824&uid=2129&uid=2&uid=70&uid= 4&sid=21102570933167. 26 A History of Philosophical Systems ed. Vergilius Ferm (New York: The Philosophical Library, Inc., 1950), 360.

7 simultaneously as the elaboration of a transcendental philosophy implying a genuine metaphysical decision concerning the ontological status of these phenomena. 27 Further, the transcendental reduction entails the eidetic reduction, beginning from the point where consciousness is treated as the field for a seeing, for an intuitive experiencing. If the transcendental can be looked at, seen, and described, then this intuiting must grasp the transcendental fact in essence. This is why it brings the fiction into play, causes the datum of consciousness to vary imaginatively, and develops experiences in the mode of as if. The fiction is the path from the fact to the eidos of the experienced reality, and it permits our grasping a consciousness as an a priori possibility. 28 The phenomenological reduction consists two moments of epoché and reduction proper. Husserl introduces transcendental consciousness by means of the epoché or parenthesizing of the objective world. Stated from the side of the object, the epoché means that the actuality of the world is bracketed and we are left only with a world which claims to be real, claims to be objective and actual, but which in fact has been reduced, for the phenomenologist, to a phenomenon. Stated from the side of the subject, epoché means that our belief in the reality of the world is suspended. We abstain from this belief, no longer participate in it. The effect of the epoché is in one sense nothing and in another everything. In one sense, nothing is changed. The world continues to appear precisely as before, and our belief in the world remains in the manner of an act which can be investigated. 29 Meanwhile, if the epoché is the name for whatever method we use to free ourselves from the captivity of the unquestioned acceptance of the everyday world, then the reduction is the recognition of that acceptance as an acceptance. It is the seeing of the acceptance as an acceptance that is the indication of having achieved a transcendental insight; it is transcendental precisely because it is an insight from outside the acceptedness that is holding us captive. 30 Transcendental phenomenology is reflexive act as well as philosophically reflective act. While phenomenology is reflexive act that cuts across the normal flow of consciousness to reveal and delineate its eidetic, or essential structures, i.e. its intentional nature, as the subjective condition for the possibility of all thinking whatsoever, especially science, 31 it is also a reflective observational analysis of transcendental consciousness, particularly with respect to its intentionality and its intentional objects, e.g., the transcendental phenomenon. 32 With this idea of reflection, we realize that epoché is not enough. We are introduced into a kind of egology, presenting a two-tiered 27 Ricoeur, 9. 28 Ricoeur, 91. 29 Caputo, 206-207. 30 http://www.iep.utm.edu/phen-red/#sh5a. 31 In his introduction, Kenneth Stikkers indicates the differences between Schelerian and Husserlian phenomenology. Cf. Max Scheler, Problems of a Sociology of Knowledge trans. Manfred Frings (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1980), 9. Hereafter Frings. 32 A History of Philosophical Systems ed. Vergilius Ferm (New York: The Philosophical Library, Inc., 1950), 361.

8 ego, i.e., only one ego which is capable of two different kinds of acts: one is empirical and the other is transcendental. The former is portrayed as always living in belief while the other is portrayed as extricating itself from belief, as withdrawing itself from the life which the empirical ego lives. This phenomenologically reflective act sets up the ego which reflects, i.e., ego which performs the epoché or the reflecting ego, on a higher or transcendental level than the ego reflected upon, i.e., ego which does not perform the epoché or the pre-reflective ego. If the sphere of transcendental consciousness is attained by epoché, the transcendental sphere is attained only in reflection. 33 Conclusion Husserl is not so much concerned of defining things themselves. His phenomenology, as a method, proceeds by describing reality in its fullest sense. The descriptive manner of phenomenological analysis provides us a notion of the a priori, the givenness of things, their essence a general characteristic of phenomenology. This rigor that is evidently involved in the phenomenological project serves well in its purpose to decipher what lies beneath, behind, beyond the realities of things themselves. True enough, from what rests on the surface one is led into the depths. 34 In this approach, we are embarking on a modest position in our inquiry or investigation towards things. We are not too ambitious to really arrive at the very core of what lies beyond our capabilities. Contrary to scientific obsessive tendency to objectify and ascertain and defining things, Husserl described phenomenology as the rigorous science of all conceivable transcendental phenomena. All knowledge should be based on absolutely certain insights. But the rigor of the method of phenomenology is interpreted philosophically rather than in terms of any elaborate, objective procedures of the physical and natural sciences. The natural sciences start from a complex set of presuppositions, frameworks and perspectives of knowledge, but these are not questioned by the sciences themselves. For Husserl, phenomenology is a rigorous, human science precisely because it investigates the way that knowledge comes into being and clarifies the assumptions upon which all human understandings are grounded. 35 Paul Ricoeur would also assert that the transcendental phenomenology is a radicalization of the Cartesian discovery on doubt and cogito as well as the continuation of the struggle against objectivism. 36 This is also affirmed by Edward Ballad who, in the translator s foreword, contends of a more critical awareness of the presupposition of the finality of the scientific ideal of rigor and objectivity. 37 The phenomenological method assumes a nobler purpose of combating the arrogance of scientific inquiry. Even in the olden times, we are already given a hint 33 Caputo, 207. 34 Edmund Husserl, The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology: An Introduction to Phenomenological Philosophy trans. David Carr (Evanston, III.: Northwestern University Press, 1970, p.355. Hereafter Husserl. 35 36 Ricoeur, 161. 37 Ricoeur, xx.

that science and its framework failed. We remember the earth-centered universe which later on was proven to be false. 9