An Empiricist Theory of Knowledge Bruce Aune

Similar documents
Revised 3/11/09. Bruce Aune

An Empiricist Theory of Knowledge

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

Cory Juhl, Eric Loomis, Analyticity (New York: Routledge, 2010).

PHIL 3140: Epistemology

5AANA009 Epistemology II 2014 to 2015

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

PH 1000 Introduction to Philosophy, or PH 1001 Practical Reasoning

PHILOSOPHY EPISTEMOLOGY ESSAY TOPICS AND INSTRUCTIONS

Overview. Is there a priori knowledge? No: Mill, Quine. Is there synthetic a priori knowledge? Yes: faculty of a priori intuition (Rationalism, Kant)

Contemporary Epistemology

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology

Lecture 1 The Concept of Inductive Probability

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem?

Positive Philosophy, Freedom and Democracy. Roger Bishop Jones

Positive Philosophy, Freedom and Democracy. Roger Bishop Jones

Varieties of Apriority

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Constructing the World

145 Philosophy of Science

Epistemology Naturalized

Comments on Scott Soames, Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, volume I

Metametaphysics. New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology* Oxford University Press, 2009

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

APRIORITY AND MEANING: A CASE OF THE EPISTEMIC TWO-DIMENSIONAL SEMANTICS

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

THE UNIVERSITY OF WESTERN ONTARIO DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY Undergraduate Course Outline PHIL3501G: Epistemology

LENT 2018 THEORY OF MEANING DR MAARTEN STEENHAGEN

Dumitrescu Bogdan Andrei - The incompatibility of analytic statements with Quine s universal revisability

Philosophy A465: Introduction to Analytic Philosophy Loyola University of New Orleans Ben Bayer Spring 2011

TWO CONCEPTIONS OF THE SYNTHETIC A PRIORI. Marian David Notre Dame University

Against Coherence: Truth, Probability, and Justification. Erik J. Olsson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xiii, 232.

INTRODUCTION: EPISTEMIC COHERENTISM

From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Skepticism is True. Abraham Meidan

STEWART COHEN AND THE CONTEXTUALIST THEORY OF JUSTIFICATION

WHAT IS HUME S FORK? Certainty does not exist in science.

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

HPS 1653 / PHIL 1610 Revision Guide (all topics)

Realism and the success of science argument. Leplin:

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE

Review of David J. Chalmers Constructing the World (OUP 2012) David Chalmers burst onto the philosophical scene in the mid-1990s with his work on

On Quine, Grice and Strawson, and the Analytic-Synthetic Distinction. by Christian Green

PHI2391: Logical Empiricism I 8.0

PHILOSOPHY EPISTEMOLOGY

Conventionalism and the linguistic doctrine of logical truth

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use

PHILOSOPHY 3340 EPISTEMOLOGY

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke,

Quine on the analytic/synthetic distinction

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 7 : E P I S T E M O L O G Y - K A N T

Précis of Empiricism and Experience. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

Naturalism and is Opponents

Epistemology: A Contemporary Introduction to The Theory of Knowledge, by Robert Audi. New York: Routledge, 2011.

Empiricism, Natural Regularity, and Necessity

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

Why Naturalized Epistemology Is Normative. Lindsay Beyerstein

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Who Has the Burden of Proof? Must the Christian Provide Adequate Reasons for Christian Beliefs?

Apriority in Naturalized Epistemology: Investigation into a Modern Defense

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

Philosophy 427 Intuitions and Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2011

NOTES ON A PRIORI KNOWLEDGE 10/6/03

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

Biola University: An Ontology of Knowledge Course Points discussed 5/27/97

PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

REVIEW THE DOOR TO SELLARS

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Classical Theory of Concepts

4AANB007 - Epistemology I Syllabus Academic year 2014/15

Phil/Ling 375: Meaning and Mind [Handout #10]

Huemer s Clarkeanism

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

DOUBT, CIRCULARITY AND THE MOOREAN RESPONSE TO THE SCEPTIC. Jessica Brown University of Bristol

Preserving Normativity in Epistemology: Quine s Thesis Revisited

Putnam and the Contextually A Priori Gary Ebbs University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign

UNIVERSITY OF ALBERTA MATHEMATICS AS MAKE-BELIEVE: A CONSTRUCTIVE EMPIRICIST ACCOUNT SARAH HOFFMAN

THE IDEA OF A PRIORI REVISITED* SANJIT CHAKRABORTY

Logic, Truth & Epistemology. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 110, No. 3. (Jul., 2001), pp

Van Fraassen: Arguments concerning scientific realism

Foundationalism Vs. Skepticism: The Greater Philosophical Ideology

PHILOSOPHICAL RAMIFICATIONS: THEORY, EXPERIMENT, & EMPIRICAL TRUTH

Analyticity, Reductionism, and Semantic Holism. The verification theory is an empirical theory of meaning which asserts that the meaning of a

Immanuel Kant, Analytic and Synthetic. Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics Preface and Preamble

RESPECTING THE EVIDENCE. Richard Feldman University of Rochester

PL 399: Knowledge, Truth, and Skepticism Spring, 2011, Juniata College

Philosophy of Science PHIL 241, MW 12:00-1:15

Linguistic Modal Conventionalism in the Real World

Gary Ebbs, Carnap, Quine, and Putnam on Methods of Inquiry, Cambridge. University Press, 2017, 278pp., $99.99 (hbk), ISBN

The Positive Argument for Constructive Empiricism and Inference to the Best

Transcription:

An Empiricist Theory of Knowledge Bruce Aune Copyright 2008 Bruce Aune

To Anne

ii CONTENTS PREFACE iv Chapter One: WHAT IS KNOWLEDGE? Conceptions of Knowing 1 Epistemic Contextualism 4 Lewis s Contextualism 6 A Dual Analysis of Knowledge 11 Problems for Two Senses of Knows 14 Avoiding Gettier Counterexamples 15 Concluding Remarks 19 Chapter Two: THE CLAIMS OF RATIONALISM 23 The A Priori, Universality, and Necessity 23 Axioms and Primitive Rules of Inference 26 General Doubts about Intuitive Knowledge 28 Logical Truths and Rules of Inference 32 Alleged Self-evident Factual Truths 36 Three Final Examples, Two Old and One New 40 An Indirect Argument for Rationalism 43 Chapter Three: EMPIRICISM AND THE A PRIORI 47 Quine s Criticism of Analyticity 47 Quine s Later View of Analytic Truth 50 Analyticity, Logic, and Everyday Language 52 Analyticity Extended 57 Some Examples and Arguments by Kripke 63 Beliefs, Propositions, and Analyticity 64 Chapter Four: PROPERTIES AND CONCEPTS 71 What are Properties? 71 Problems with A-theories and T-theories 73 Predication 76 Advantages of F-theories 78 What are Concepts? 80 Some Problems about DSTs 83 More about Concepts 85 Concepts, Predicates, and the World 87 Meaning, Intending, and Content Clauses 88 Concluding Remarks 93

Contents iii Chapter Five: OBSERVATIONAL KNOWLEDGE 95 A Problem about Observation 95 Evaluating Observational Beliefs 97 Does Knowledge Need a Foundation? 99 Alternatives to Foundationalism 102 Knowledge and the World: Some Problems 104 Semantic Externalism 107 Criticism of Semantic Externalism 110 A Skeptical Problem Restated 114 Chapter Six: MEMORY AND A POSTERIORI KNOWLEDGE 115 Memory as a Source of Knowledge 115 What is Induction? 122 Induction: Arguments Pro and Con 124 Induction and Laws 126 Inference to the Best Explanation 128 Inferences Based on Bayes Theorem 130 Ascertaining Prior Probabilities 133 Basic Prior Probabilities 136 The BIV Hypothesis Again 138 Concluding Remarks 142144 APPENDICES 145 1. Armstrong s New Hypothesis About Universals 145 2. Boghossian and Field on Basic Logical Principles 146 3. Stipulation, Proper Definitions, and Truth 149 4. What is Said and Propositions 152 5. Chisholm s Defense of the Principle CP 155 6. Analytic Probability Principles 156 REFERENCES 159

iv Preface When I began to teach philosophy, almost every responsible analytic philosopher was an acknowledged empiricist. Today, many analytic philosophers repudiate central tenets of the position, rejecting at least an analytic/synthetic distinction and often pursuing metaphysical questions that mainline empiricists set aside decades ago. I regard this development as unfortunate, a backward step in philosophy that needs to be corrected. Bas van Fraassen and Anil Gupta have recently taken important steps in the right direction. I try to do my part in this book, attacking well-known criticisms of empiricist doctrine and defending the sort of empiricist theory that I consider acceptable. There is no essence to empiricism: different positions have been defended under the name empiricism, and the practice will no doubt continue. 1 The empiricism I learned as a student was called logical empiricism, the qualifier marking the importance of formal logic to this version of the theory. One of my teachers, Herbert Feigl, discussed the distinctive claims of an earlier form of this empiricism in a programmatic article called Logical Empiricism, which was regarded as something of a manifesto in its day. The adjective Feigl attached to empiricism was chiefly owing to the logical and semantical work of Rudolf Carnap, another of my teachers, 2 who was the dominant figure among the empiricists whose views Feigl was promoting. Carnap s epistemological views changed significantly over his long philosophical career, and his later views represent a development of empiricism that deserves to be better known by today s critics of the doctrine. The objections to empiricism that W. V. Quine formulated in Two Dogmas of Empiricism (1951) are still widely regarded as successful. The supposed dogmas in question are, Quine said, a belief in a fundamental cleavage between analytic and synthetic truths, on the one hand, and reductionism, the belief that each meaningful statement is equivalent to some logical construct upon terms referring to immediate experience, on the other. As it happens, logical empiricists did not hold the second dogma when Quine s paper was published. Feigl explicitly denounced it in Logical Empiricism (first published in 1943) and Carnap left it behind in the middle thirties. 3 The first dogma assumption is really a better word here was indeed accepted, at least as an ideal, by logical empiricists, and I shall therefore discuss Quine s objections to it carefully and at length. Although Quine has long been one of my philosophical heroes, I have to say that his objections to analyticity fail to undermine the position Carnap defended in his later years. Carnap was right to set them aside as unsuccessful. Quine s criticism was not the only cause of empiricism s decline; another was the rise of epistemological rationalism. The cause of this phenomenon is complex; no doubt it had something to do with the revival of interest in metaphysics that resulted from Kripke s revolutionary ideas on identity, necessity, and essential properties. But whatever the actual cause may be, the most influential exponent of the new analytical rationalism turned out to be R. M. Chisholm. As Alvin Plantinga remarked in 1990, Chisholm s thought has [in fact] dominated American epistemology for more than thirty years ; 4 if this is an exaggeration, as I believe it is, it is nevertheless not very far from the truth. To defend a version of empiricism at the present time it is therefore not sufficient to overcome the criticism of Quine; 1 See van Fraassen (2002), Appendix B, A History of the Name Empiricism. 2 As a graduate student, I spent a year at UCLA, where he was then teaching. 3 He rejected it in Carnap (1936). 4 Plantinga (1990), p. 366.

5 one should also criticize the arguments supporting the alternative position that Chisholm was instrumental in initiating. Criticizing an alternative position is unfortunately an awkward task. There is always more than one version of such a position and always more than one advocate to confront. Alvin Plantinga, George Bealer, Laurence BonJour, Christopher Peacock, and Robert Audi have defended well-considered versions of epistemological rationalism, but I cannot examine all of them in a book like this. Instead of focusing attention on particular versions of the doctrine, I shall for the most part attend to what I regard as the most important arguments rationalists offer for synthetic a priori truths. These arguments feature a number of examples that are cited again and again; in 2005 Laurence BonJour offered the examples that Chisholm gave as early as 1966. 5 I therefore attend to them closely. My positive arguments against epistemological rationalism depend not on the peculiarities of different rationalist theories but on structural weaknesses common to them all. The propositions they take to be intuitively decidable synthetic truths are actually warranted, if they are actually true, by facts that are far too discursive and stipulative to be a confirming element in any rationalist theory. In the past twenty years or so academic philosophy has become highly specialized, with the result that philosophers working in epistemology often do not have well-considered views in related subjects such as metaphysics, formal semantics, and philosophy of science. Topics in these related subjects are nevertheless crucially important for basic epistemological disputes. As far as a priori knowledge is concerned, the pertinent topics belong mainly to metaphysics and formal semantics. Specific issues concern the reality and nature of properties and propositions, which rationalists typically regard as providing the foundation for synthetic a priori knowledge. Because recent work in metaphysics and formal semantics puts older views of these supposed objects into serious doubt, I devote part of one chapter to propositions and a whole chapter to properties. Writing this material has reinforced my belief that it is absolutely essential for a responsible treatment of a priori knowledge. Although critics of empiricism have typically concentrated on an analytic/synthetic distinction, a satisfactory empiricist philosophy must provide an acceptable account of a posteriori knowledge. In my final chapters I therefore discuss problems with the sources of empirical knowledge that empiricists almost always accept: observation, memory, and what Hume called experimental inference. I open chapter five with a consideration of some of these problems, but I soon address the doctrine of semantic externalism that Hilary Putnam developed in criticizing his well-known brains in a vat version of a perennial skeptical hypothesis. Although Putnam evidently considered his externalism to be opposed to traditional views of meaning and reference, I argue that it is in fact quite close to the verificationism that was espoused by logical positivists, and I reject it for reasons that apply to that once popular doctrine. As I see it, the empiricists historical repudiation of empirical entities that cannot possibly be observed is something that an acceptable empiricism must leave behind. In chapter six I am mainly concerned with inductive or a posteriori inference, which has been seriously neglected by main-line epistemologists with rationalist sympathies. (Chisholm had almost nothing to say about this kind of inference in the last edition of his influential Theory of Knowledge.) Since inductive methods raise more problems than most philosophers seem to realize, I provide a critical overview of the standard alternatives. My assessment of these methods is 5 See Chisholm (1989) and BonJour (2005). Chisholm used the same examples in earlier editions of his Theory of Knowledge; the first was published in 1966.

6 generally negative even for the current favorite, Inference to the Best Explanation. Arguing that the problems familiar methods are supposed to solve can be disposed of only by relying on Bayes theorem of probability theory, I end up discussing this theorem and its relation to what can be called evidential probability. This kind of probability is often viewed as a measure of subjective belief, but I argue that it must be understood differently if well-known problems are to be avoided. I view it as a measure of certainty and evidential support, a position I do my best to justify. Although some epistemologists are very knowledgeable about probability theory, the subject is evidently daunting to many philosophers. Believing this, I took special pains to make my discussion understandable to those entirely new to the subject. Sophisticated readers can simply skip the explanatory passages I include here and there. To deal with certain side issues that are highly significant for some philosophers but of minimal interest to many, I followed the example of Fogelin (1994) and van Fraassen (2002) and included a number of appendices. These appendices are generally too long to be footnotes but they are well suited to the end of the book where readers who recognize their importance can consult them. With one exception, a proof that was awkward to place in the text, each appendix is concerned with matters that, in my experience, always eventually arise when philosophical rivals debate epistemological issues. I therefore felt compelled to include them. A number of friends contributed to the manuscript in one way or another. Joe LaPorte, Steve Braude, Jeffrey Sicha, and Lynne Baker made helpful comments on the chapters they read. LaPorte was particularly helpful with chapters one and six, and Sicha subjected the whole manuscript to very careful scrutiny, doing the sort of thing he did many years ago when I was writing my first book. I am greatly indebted to his good judgment and critical acuity. The late Gregory Fitch offered illuminating remarks on some questions I had with Kripke s footnote about the necessity of origins ; he was not himself critical of the argument Kripke seemed to give, but his remarks were instrumental in leading me to the criticism I formulate in chapter three. My wonderful wife, Anne, to whom I dedicate this book, was helpful from start to finish. She read every version of the manuscript and always discovered errors that I had somehow missed. This is my fourth book on epistemology. The first was principally indebted to the work of Wilfrid Sellars, whose influence is discernible here mainly in chapters four and five. The logical empiricist doctrines that I absorbed from Herbert Feigl, Rudolf Carnap, and Grover Maxwell are evident in chapters two and three, and the logical and semantic theory I learned from Donald Kalish and Richard Montague is also apparent there. Montague introduced me to the logical foundations of probability, but my views on that subject are more strongly indebted to the writing of my one-time students Roger Rosenkrantz and Brian Skyrms. The fact that these people, and certain writers whom I have not mentioned, do not agree on all philosophical matters may help to explain the independence of my own philosophical thinking, such as it is. I have had no single path to follow.