A Response to My Critics Adam Potkay Hume Studies Volume XXVII, Number 1 (April, 2001)

Similar documents
Hume on Promises and Their Obligation. Hume Studies Volume XIV, Number 1 (April, 1988) Antony E. Pitson

A Hobbist Tory: Johnson on Hume Paul Russell Hume Studies Volume XVI, Number 1 (April, 1990)




5AANA005 Ethics II: History of Ethical Philosophy 2014/15. BA Syllabus


Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.



Robert Kiely Office Hours: Monday 4:15 6:00; Wednesday 1-3; Thursday 2-3

HUME AND HIS CRITICS: Reid and Kames

'Things' for 'Actions': Locke's Mistake in 'Of Power' Locke Studies 10 (2010):85-94 Julie Walsh

Christian Johnson and Pagan Hume William R. Connolly Hume Studies Volume XXVII, Number 1 (April, 2001)

HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD

World-Wide Ethics. Chapter One. Individual Subjectivism

Robert Kiely Office Hours: Tuesday 1-3, Wednesday 1-3, and by appointment

Hume's Treatise of Human Nature

Inconsistency within a Reconciling Project Antony Flew Hume Studies Volume IV, Number 1 (April, 1978), 1-6.

1/12. The A Paralogisms

THE EMOTIONAL AND INTELLECTUAL VIRTUE OF FAITH

Symposium: Stoicism Reconsidered. Choose the Hyundai. Reason Papers Vol. 40, no. 1. Jennifer Baker College of Charleston

On happiness in Locke s decision-ma Title being )

David O Connor. Hume on Religion H. O. Mounce Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 2 (November, 2002)

Edinburgh Research Explorer

Wed, 1:30-4:00 Office hours: Mon, 1:30-3:30 Packard Conference Room Packard Hall 109

Hume s An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding

Two Approaches to Natural Law;Note

Commentary on Professor Tweyman's 'Hume on Evil' Pheroze S. Wadia Hume Studies Volume XIII, Number 1 (April, 1987)

Introduction to Ethics Part 2: History of Ethics. SMSU Spring 2005 Professor Douglas F. Olena

Philosophical Review.

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Virtue Ethics. A Basic Introductory Essay, by Dr. Garrett. Latest minor modification November 28, 2005

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Reason Papers Vol. 36, no. 1

Hume s Refutation of Wollaston? Oliver A. Johnson Hume Studies Volume XII, Number 2 (November, 1986)

Kant s Misrepresentations of Hume s Philosophy of Mathematics in the Prolegomena

Hume s Law Violated? Rik Peels. The Journal of Value Inquiry ISSN J Value Inquiry DOI /s

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Judith Jarvis Thomson s Normativity

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6

Dumitrescu Bogdan Andrei - The incompatibility of analytic statements with Quine s universal revisability

Hume's Functionalism About Mental Kinds

Hoong Juan Ru. St Joseph s Institution International. Candidate Number Date: April 25, Theory of Knowledge Essay

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 110, No. 3. (Jul., 2001), pp

Hume is a strict empiricist, i.e. he holds that knowledge of the world and ourselves ultimately comes from (inner and outer) experience.

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 100, No. 3. (Jul., 1991), pp

HUME S EPISTEMOLOGICAL COMPATIBILISM

What Does Academic Skepticism Presuppose? Arcesilaus, Carneades, and the Argument with Stoic Epistemology

Anne Jaap Jacobson, ed. Feminist Interpretations of David Hume Michelle Mason Hume Studies Volume XXVII, Number 1 (April, 2001)

BOOK REVIEWS. Duke University. The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVII, No. 1 (January 1988)

CHAPTER 2. The Classical School

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

Certainty, Necessity, and Knowledge in Hume s Treatise

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

Duty and Categorical Rules. Immanuel Kant Introduction to Ethics, PHIL 118 Professor Douglas Olena

The dangers of the sovereign being the judge of rationality

ELEONORE STUMP PENELHUM ON SKEPTICS AND FIDEISTS

UNCORRECTED PROOF GOD AND TIME. The University of Mississippi

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

RECENT WORK THE MINIMAL DEFINITION AND METHODOLOGY OF COMPARATIVE PHILOSOPHY: A REPORT FROM A CONFERENCE STEPHEN C. ANGLE

Hume on the Pre-Social State

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

Imprint CURIOUS VIRTUES IN HUME S EPISTEMOLOGY. Karl Schafer. volume 14, no. 1 january University of Pittsburgh.

Aquinas on Spiritual Change. In "Is an Aristotelian Philosophy of Mind Still Credible? (A draft)," Myles

The Development of Laws of Formal Logic of Aristotle

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

A Vindication. Hume Studies Volume XVII, Number 2 (November, 1991) Wim Klever 212.

Florida State University Libraries

Objectivism and Education: A Response to David Elkind s The Problem with Constructivism

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

UNITED NATIONS EDUCATIONAL, SCIENTIFIC AND CULTURAL ORGANIZATION. Address by Mr Federico Mayor

Charles Hartshorne argues that Kant s criticisms of Anselm s ontological

Intro to Ground. 1. The idea of ground. 2. Relata. are facts): F 1. More-or-less equivalent phrases (where F 1. and F 2. depends upon F 2 F 2

Faith and Philosophy, April (2006), DE SE KNOWLEDGE AND THE POSSIBILITY OF AN OMNISCIENT BEING Stephan Torre

Tamás Demeter, David Hume and the Culture of Scottish Newtonianism: Methodology and Ideology in Enlightenment Inquiry, Boston: Brill, 2016, 221 pp.

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Primary and Secondary Qualities. John Locke s distinction between primary and secondary qualities of bodies has

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

An Alternate Possibility for the Compatibility of Divine. Foreknowledge and Free Will. Alex Cavender. Ringstad Paper Junior/Senior Division

How to Live a More Authentic Life in Both Markets and Morals

Bart Streumer, Unbelievable Errors, Oxford: Oxford University Press, ISBN

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have

Philosophy Courses-1

Spring CAS Department of Philosophy Graduate Courses

The hallmark of a good moral theory is that it agrees with and improves

narrow segment of life with a short-lived feeling ( I m happy with my latest pay raise ). One

A New Argument Against Compatibilism

PROFESSIONAL ETHICS IN SCIENCE AND ENGINEERING

History of Political Thought I: Justice, Virtue, and the Soul

THE FREGE-GEACH PROBLEM AND KALDERON S MORAL FICTIONALISM. Matti Eklund Cornell University

Comments on Ontological Anti-Realism

Hume Against Spinoza and Aristotle. Hume Studies Volume XVII, Number 2 (November, 1991) Frank J. Leavitt 208.

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

The Ontological Argument

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

Transcription:

A Response to My Critics Adam Potkay Hume Studies Volume XXVII, Number 1 (April, 2001) 173-180. Your use of the HUME STUDIES archive indicates your acceptance of HUME STUDIES Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.humesociety.org/hs/about/terms.html. HUME STUDIES Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the HUME STUDIES archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Each copy of any part of a HUME STUDIES transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. For more information on HUME STUDIES contact humestudies-info@humesociety.org http://www.humesociety.org/hs/

HUME STUDIES Volume 27, Number 1, April 2001, pp. 173-179 A Symposium on Adam Potkay, The Passion for Happiness: Samuel Johnson and David Hume A Response to My Critics ADAM POTKAY In The Passion for Happiness, I attempt to situate Johnson alongside Hume within a common Enlightenment culture and, in so doing, to give us a better idea of what that culture is, or may be said to be. I am concerned in the book to analyze what I see as their shared debts to classical eudaimonism, particularly as it is presented in the philosophical dialogues of Cicero. In this regard, my book builds upon Peter Jones s Hume s Sentiments: Their Ciceronian and French Contexts (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1982); I am also deeply indebted to some recent re-interpreters of Hellenistic ethics, especially to Martha Nussbaum, Julia Annas, and Lawrence Becker. A third of my book, however, is devoted to a discussion of Johnson and Hume s roughly parallel-and, I think, mutually illuminating-careers as political writers and commentators, including the political and moral casts of their historiographical writings. The titles of chapters 7 through 9- The Passions and Patterns of History, Enthusiasm and Empire, Constancy -suggest at least my hopes that The Passion for Happiness might be of some interest to intellectual and political historians. My commentators, however, are both philosophers, and as such have chosen to focus on the first half of my book, chiefly chapters 2 to 6. Within this restricted purview, William Connolly offers what I in general find to be a judicious, even a generous, assessment of my arguments. Yet while I acknowledge that it s the religious differences between Johnson and Hume that constitute the greatest obstacle to any rapprochement between them (Connolly 158), I would still want to emphasize, as I do in my book, that Johnson and Adam Potkay is Professor of English, The College of William and Mary, Williamsburg, VA 23187, USA. e-mail: aspotk@wm.edu

174 Adam Potkay Hume each tend to write as enlightened moralists in a Ciceronian mode. This mode tends to make Hume sound, at crucial moments in both his epistemological and historical writings, a bit more religious than he in all probability was, while it makes Johnson sound, at similar moments in his writing, a lot less religious than he almost certainly was. I can t stress enough that my primary object of inquiry is Johnson s own substantial body of writings and not the work which is, alas, much better known-boswell s entertaining but very tendentious Life of Johnson. And yet the almost insuperable temptation to rely on Boswell, or to equate Boswell s Johnson with Johnson, tout court, is evidenced in the first part of William Connolly s comments on The Passion for Happiness. This temptation is completely indulged in Peter Lopston s otherwise very useful book, Theories of Human Nature (Peterborough, Ontario: Broadview Press, 1995). Here, Professor Lopston deems Johnson the prototypical conservative individualist chiefly on the basis of several glum quips extracted from the Life offohnson (92-5); Johnson is deemed the typical Tory Christian without any supporting evidence whatsoever. According to Lopston, Tory Christians think of themselves as living in Babylon, part of a beleaguered minority in dark times growing darker (SO). And yet, as I show in my book, Johnson thought of himself as living in, and contributing to, an enlightened age -indeed, the enlightened age. Our age, Johnson claimed, is enlightened beyond any former time (PFH 6-7). I bring up Professor Lopston s earlier characterization of Johnson because I suspect that it continues to animate his sense of who Johnson is, and of why he and Hume must, therefore, be somehow incommensurable entities. Lopston continues to think of Johnson as dark -as he asserts in his concluding remarks on my book, Johnson remains a dark, glowering... Christian of a man (Loptson 171)- but has yet to support this characterization with evidence, or to engage with the considerable body of contrary evidence that I provide in my book. Indeed, Lopston is concerned less with characterizing my book than with engaging its claims or assumptions on three interrelated points of more general philosophic concern. Let me start with Lopston s second concern, the proper distinctions between types of compatibilism, simply because I can address it with the least ado. Lopston makes, I think, a very convincing case that Johnson was not a compatibilist in the way that Hume was. I ve learned a good deal from this section of Professor Lopston s paper, and I thank him for the instruction. Professor Lopston s remaining claims require more comment. First, he argues, in objection to one of my book s claims, that neither Cicero nor Hume had any signal debts to Stoic ethics. Second, against what he finds to be an HUME STUDIES

Response to Critics 175 assumption of my book, Lopston argues that Hume (unlike Johnson) is not a moral objectivist, labeling him instead a moral positivist (Loptson 169). Can Hume be related back to Stoicism of a Roman variety? Indeed, is there Stoicism of a Roman variety? With all due respect to Professor Lopston s objections, I would still answer yes to both questions. First, Professor Lopston asserts that as for happiness as a human telos... it is an explicit and primary model for Aristotelianism and Epicureanism, not Stoicism (Loptson 165). Of course, Stoicism is, like the other Hellenistic schools, a eudaimonistic philosophy. Roman Stoicism is, historically, an amalgam of Aristotelian and Stoic roots. E. Vernon Arnold aptly notes, the triumph won by Panaetius [in introducing Stoicism to Rome]... was purchased by the sacrifice not only of its physics, but very largely of its ethics also; and the success of the new system might not unfairly be described as a victory of literature over logic, of reasonableness over reason, and of compromise over consistency. However this may be, Panaetius undoubtedly succeeded in presenting Greek philosophy to his Roman friends in a form in which it recommended itself alike to their reasoning powers and to their moral sense. 2 One of my arguments in The Passion for Happiness is that it is this peculiarly Roman Stoicism, as it was elaborated in several of Cicero s dialogues, which had a significant influence on Hume and Johnson alike. We needn t call Cicero himself a Stoic in order to acknowledge the presence of modified Stoic doctrine in his works. It s what we find in De Finibus Book 3-the great discourse on Stoic ethics that Cicero puts in the mouth of Marcus Cato; it s also what we find in De Officiis, which largely relies on a lost work by Panaetius. In addressing Hume scholars, I scarcely need emphasize the importance of De 0fl lciis to Hume s ethics. But I should briefly suggest-a suggestion upon which I elaborate in my book-that the modified Stoic doctrine that we find in De Finibus 3 is the only type of Stoicism that makes sense of Hume s essay The Stoic, and thus what Hume thinks a proper Stoic is. (Elsewhere in his writings, when Hume seeks to censure what he sees as the excesses, or the consolatory deficiencies, of Stoicism, the name he introduces is always Epictetus; even Epictetus, however, garners praise for his magnanimity in Enquiry concerning the Principles of Morals, section 7.) Hume s essay The Stoic is, I argue, key to an understanding of Hume s ethic^.^ Through The Stoic, it is possible to trace a line of influence from De Finibus 3 to many of Hume s-and Johnson s-ethical themes and concerns. For the sake of brevity, simply let me list some of these baldly, with minimal adornment from Hume s essay: Volume 27, Number 1, April 2001

176 a a 0 0 a a Adam Potkay We naturally possess radiating benevolence (as opposed to universal benevolence). In some way, free will and necessity-or are compatible. virtue and fortune - The philosopher must defend the (motivating force of the) socia1 passions, and seek simply to moderate the passions and enlighten the reason. Reason needs particular enlightening to attain to the artificial virtue of justice. Special praise is due to magnanimity, generously sacrificing ourselves for the interests of our country. The love of fame is a deterrent against the fear of death. The great end of all human industry is the attainment of happin ess. The main difference between Johnson and Hume-as I point out in my book, and as William Connolly rightly underlines in his paper-is that Johnson would not concede the penultimate point here: for him, the fear of death will, at least upon the deathbed, trump all other passions. Indeed, it s in writing about death, and pretty much only in writing about death, that Johnson the writer reveals the porch or portico view of human life that Hume scripted for Demea, and that he, personally, rejected. I cannot fully reply to Professor Lopston s third and final claim, concerning moral objectivism, because it turns, in the course of an ostensible comment on my book, into the germ of an independent and not uninteresting article, and a proper response would require at least another article in turn. Let me, however, make a few remarks as a prologomenon to any future article (it s one that I, by the way, won t be writing). The term moral objectivism is Lopston s substitute for moral realism, the term he used in his oral remarks on my book at the 27th Hume Conference; the new term is no doubt intended to avoid the definitional quandaries that attend moral realism, but I m not sure that it does so. Moral realism, I can say from my experience at the 27 h Hume Conference, is a term upon whose meaning a roomful of Humeans cannot agree. Part of the problem, of course, is that it s a term Hume never used. My own preferred definition of moral realism, according to which Hume can be viewed as one, was offered by Dorothy Coleman: for Hume moral distinctions are real in the sense of being non-reductive, not reducible to a radical motive such as self-interest. HUME STUDIES

Response to Critics 17 7 The moral realism or objectivism that, according to Lopston, Hume opposes is the position that there are things which are good, bad, right, wrong, obligatory, and permissible, morally (168). Prima facie, Hume hardly seems opposed to such a position: he begins his second Enquiry by dismissing those who have denied the reality of moral distinctions as disingenuous disputants, adding Let a man s insensibility be ever so great, he must often be touched with images of Right and Wr~ng. ~ In the Dialogue that always accompanies the Enquiry, Hume reiterates that there are universal, established principles of morals adhered to by all but those who perversely affect artificial lives and manners -such as Diogenes, the most celebrated model of extravagant philosophy, and, much the worse, Pascal, a slave to the illusions of religious superstition. Pascal made constant profession of humility and abasement, of the contempt and hatred of himself; and endeavoured to attain these supposed virtues, as far as they are attainable. The austerities of the Greek [Diogenes] were in order to inure himself to hardships, and prevent his ever suffering; Those of the Frenchman were embraced merely for their own sake, and in order to suffer as much as possible.... When men depart from the maxims of common reason, and affect these artificial lives... no one can answer for what will please or displease them. 5 Pascal possesses what Hume elsewhere in the Enquiry calls-contemptuously-the monkish virtues (section 9, part 1); readers of Hume will also recall the sustained critique of these unreal virtues in the second half of The Natural History of Religion and in the medieval volumes of The History of England. Such passages remind us that Hume is not simply or even primarily a social scientist of moral-judgment making, as Lopston avers, but a moralist, one who intends to convince his readers to abide by natural morals and to reject their perversions by religious superstition and enthusiasm. Lopston misses this point when he quotes from my book a snippet of Hume s 1739 letter to Hutcheson, responding to a criticism Hutcheson had made about the still unpublished Book 111 of the Treatise. Hume proceeds in this letter to say that he intends, in the future, to supply that want of Warmth in the cause of Virtue Hutcheson had remarked in the Treatise: I intend to make a new Tryal, if it be possible to make the Moralist & Metaphysician agree a little better. j I surmise that Hume s new Tryal ultimately resulted in his Enquiry concerning the Principles of Morals, and that it is the work s reconciliation of moral painting with moral anatomy that made it, as Hume opined in My Own Life, of all my writings, historical, philosophical, or literary, incomparably the best. At his self-perceived best, Hume seldom sounds like a social scientist, but rather appears as a classical moralist whose aim is human happiness: Volume 27, Number 1, April 2001

178 Adam Potkay But what philosophical truths can be more advantageous to society, than those here delivered, which represent virtue with all her genuine and most engaging charms, and make us approach her with ease, familiarity, and affection? The dismal dress falls off, with which many divines, and some philosophers, have covered her; and nothing appears but gentleness, humanity, benevolence, affability; nay, even at proper intervals, play, frolic, and gaiety. She talks not of useless austerities and rigours, suffering and self-denial. She declares that her sole purpose is to make her votaries and all mankind, during every instant of their existence, if possible, cheerful and happy; nor does she ever willingly part with any pleasures but in hopes of ample compensation in some other period of their lives. The sole trouble which she demands, is that of just calculation, and a steady preference of the greater happiness. (EPM 279) Hume seeks to dissuade his readers from moral values that are wrong (or, at least, universally and uniformly detrimental to self and society), and to inculcate those that are true (or, at least, universally and uniformly beneficial to self and society). What s at stake in the difference between a vocabulary of right and wrong and my parenthetical translations of these terms into a relational idiom? Lopston is shrewd in drawing our attention to the distinction-and it may well be more than merely verbal-between Johnson s tendency to talk about morality in simple predicates ( what is of most use is of most value ) and Hume s characteristic appeal to our determinations about morality ( in all determinations of morality, this circumstance of public utility is ever principally in view ). Yet I would leave Professor Lopston with two related questions. First, what does determination mean in Hume s sentence? As William Walker has argued, the word determination is, from Sextus Empiricus onwards, an ambiguous one, able to refer either to discerning or to stipulating something about reality.* Can we be sure that Hume, in the sentence quoted above, clearly means determination to mean some kind of stipulative, legislative act-as Lopston, if I m reading him correctly, seems to think it does? The possibility that we can t leads to my second question: does a humanly discerned (as opposed to posited) good necessarily differ in kind from a good that is held to exist prior to human discernment? Hume, as far as I know, doesn t address this question. But here I m touching upon matters that lie outside the purview of The Passion for Happiness and beyond my professional competence; I humbly leave them, if they re of interest, for philosophers to decide. HUME STUDIES

Response to Critics 179 NOTES 1 This paper is a reply to William R. Connolly, Christian Johnson and Pagan Hume, Hume Studies 27 (2001): 149-59, and Peter Loptson, Hellenism, Freedom, and Morality in Hume and Johnson, Hume Studies 27 (2001): 161-72. References to Connolly and Loptson, and to my book The Passion for Happiness: Samuel Johnson anddavid Hume- PFH -(Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2000) will be provided parenthetically in the text. 2 Roman Stoicism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1911), 103. 3 That Hume expresses his own view of human excellence in The Stoic has also been argued by Donald Livingston in Philosophical Melancholy and Delirium (Chicago, 1998), 138-41. It is, I think, rather too hasty to dismiss the essay, as Isabel Rivers does, as a parody of Shaftesbury s rhapsodic mode (Reason, Grace, and Sentiment: A Study of the Language of Religion and Ethics in England, 1660-1780, volume 2, Shaftesbury to Hume [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 20001, 241). 4. Enquiries concerning Human Understanding and concerning the Principles of Morals, ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge, 3rd ed., revised by P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975), 169-70. Subsequent references to the Enquiry concerning the Principles of Morals (EPM) will be provided in the text. 5. A Dialogue, in Enquiries, 342, 343. 6. The Letters of David Hume, ed. J. Y. T. Grieg, 2 vols. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1932), 1: 32-3. 7. Essays: Moral, Political, and Literary, ed. Eugene F. Miller (Indianapolis: LibertyClassics, 1985), xxxvi. 8. The Determination of Locke, Hume, and Fielding, Eighteenth-Century Life 20 (1996): 70-93. Volume 27, Number 1, April 2001