Yuval Dolev, Time and Realism, MIT Press, 2007

Similar documents
Craig on the Experience of Tense

Dolev s Anti-Metaphysical Realism: A Critique. L. Nathan Oaklander

Time travel and the open future

AGENCY AND THE A-SERIES. Roman Altshuler SUNY Stony Brook

Replies to Giuliano Torrengo, Dan Zeman and Vasilis Tsompanidis

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Scope Fallacies and the "Decisive Objection" Against Endurance

Markie, Speckles, and Classical Foundationalism

Presentism/Eternalism and Endurantism/Perdurantism: why the unsubstantiality of the first debate implies that of the second 1

spring 05 topics in philosophy of mind session 1

BEGINNINGLESS PAST AND ENDLESS FUTURE: REPLY TO CRAIG. Wes Morriston. In a recent paper, I claimed that if a familiar line of argument against

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works

Metametaphysics. New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology* Oxford University Press, 2009

Rententionalism vs Extensionalism about Time Consciousness:

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central

PRESENTISM AND PERSISTENCE

Transcendence J. J. Valberg *

Under contract with Oxford University Press Karen Bennett Cornell University

Review of Ontology and the Ambitions of Metaphysics by Thomas Hofweber Billy Dunaway University of Missouri St Louis

A Complex Eternity. One of the central issues in the philosophy of religion is the relationship between

Understanding Belief Reports. David Braun. In this paper, I defend a well-known theory of belief reports from an important objection.

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

PHILOSOPHICAL PERSPECTIVES

The Reality of Tense. that I am sitting right now, for example, or that Queen Ann is dead. So in a clear and obvious

The Burning Fuse Model of Unbecoming in Time.

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

The Burning Fuse Model of Unbecoming in Time. 1

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Names Introduced with the Help of Unsatisfied Sortal Predicates: Reply to Aranyosi

CONCLUSION TO PART I

Tense and Reality. There is a common form of problem, to be found in many areas of philosophy,

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

BENEDIKT PAUL GÖCKE. Ruhr-Universität Bochum

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

Russell s Problems of Philosophy

COULD WE EXPERIENCE THE PASSAGE OF TIME? Simon Prosser

Experience and the Passage of Time

Persistence, Parts, and Presentism * TRENTON MERRICKS. Noûs 33 (1999):

The Kripkenstein Paradox and the Private World. In his paper, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Languages, Kripke expands upon a conclusion

Orthodox truthmaker theory cannot be defended by cost/benefit analysis

Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox

The Kalam Cosmological Argument provides no support for theism

Time and Existence: A Critique of "Degree Presentism"

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

Counterparts and Compositional Nihilism: A Reply to A. J. Cotnoir

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

KYLEY EWING. A thesis submitted to the Department of Philosophy. in conformity with the requirements for. the degree of Master of Arts

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

Heidegger s Unzuhandenheit as a Fourth Mode of Being

Why Four-Dimensionalism Explains Coincidence

5 A Modal Version of the

Metaphysical atomism and the attraction of materialism.

Van Fraassen: Arguments concerning scientific realism

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Wolfgang Spohn Fachbereich Philosophie Universität Konstanz D Konstanz

Andrei Marmor: Social Conventions

Fundamentals of Metaphysics

Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness

From Meaning is Use to the Rejection of Transcendent Truth

1/12. The A Paralogisms

A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel

On Experiencing time : a response to Simon Prosser

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

BonJour Against Materialism. Just an intellectual bandwagon?

George Berkeley. The Principles of Human Knowledge. Review

Horwich and the Liar

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

PHIL 181: METAPHYSICS Fall 2006 M 5:30-8:20 MND-3009 WebCT-Assisted

Perceiving Abstract Objects

Foreknowledge and Freedom

A Logical Approach to Metametaphysics

Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke,

TRUTH-MAKERS AND CONVENTION T

Getting the Measure of Consciousness

spring 05 topics in philosophy of mind session 7

Russell: On Denoting

Why Counterpart Theory and Four-Dimensionalism are Incompatible. Suppose that God creates ex nihilo a bronze statue of a

Varieties of Apriority

Wittgenstein: Meaning and Representation

The Correspondence theory of truth Frank Hofmann

Realism and instrumentalism

Vagueness in sparseness: a study in property ontology

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

What one needs to know to prepare for'spinoza's method is to be found in the treatise, On the Improvement

Nathan Oaklander IS THERE A DIFFERENCE BETWEEN ABSOLUTE AND RELATIVE SPACE?

Anti-Metaphysicalism, Necessity, and Temporal Ontology 1

Negative Facts. Negative Facts Kyle Spoor

Is phenomenal character out there in the world?

REVIEW THE DOOR TO SELLARS

Andrea Westlund, in Selflessness and Responsibility for Self, argues

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

Thinking About Consciousness

A Critique of Compound Presentism

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

Nagel, Naturalism and Theism. Todd Moody. (Saint Joseph s University, Philadelphia)

Caspar Hare March 2010 Forthcoming in Philosophy Compass. Realism About Tense and Perspective

Transcription:

[In Humana.Mente, 8 (2009)] Yuval Dolev, Time and Realism, MIT Press, 2007 Andrea Borghini College of the Holy Cross (Mass., U.S.A.) Time and Realism is a courageous book. With a clear prose and neatly woven arguments, Dolev takes the reader through two different, although related endeavors. The first (Chapters 1 4) is an assessment of the two major conceptions of time the so called tensed and tenseless views; the finale of this part avers that both views, in their different versions, play against serious challenges. The second and more ambitious endeavor (Chapters 5 and 6) argues that these challenges can be transcended (to use Dolev s own expression) and, hence, that philosophy can be liberated from old burdens such as explaining time s passage, or what time is, or why the future appears as open. In this review I will first point out two desirable theoretical distinctions that are missing throughout the volume and from which I believe Dolev s study would have substantially benefited. I will then discuss two aspects of the second, more inventive endeavor. It should be stressed, however, that the first four chapters contain original sections too, such as 3.2, a rather meticulous discussion of Dummett s antirealist conception of tensed propositions, and 4.3, a discussion of Mellor s tenseless view. Time and Realism looks into lasting philosophical conundrums that arise when we ponder the nature of time. At the core of the investigation lies the distinction between a tensed and a tenseless view of time distinction which is, eventually, rejected by Dolev. Roughly, tensed theorists maintain that any vindication of what there is is given within a certain temporal perspective, which breaks away time in a past, a present, and a future; thus, our world is such that Napoleon was exiled in St Helena between October 1815 and

May 1821. Tenseless theorists, on the other hand, assert that the ultimate description of reality is a temporal: whether a subject regards a certain event as being say past is not constitutive of what the event is; thus, our world is such that Napoleon is exiled in St Helena between October 1815 and May 1821 (where is has to be read a temporally, as when we say that The set of equilateral triangles is the set of equiangular triangles ). The opposition between the tensed and the tenseless view is essentially a semantic opposition: it interests the way in which a statement has to be true whether it is true a temporally or relatively to a certain time. Still, when it comes to the metaphysics of time, there are at least two more distinctions that typically play a relevant theoretical role. One involves so called three and four dimensionalism. Roughly, the first holds that a material object is wholly present at each instant at which it exists. So, for example, on October 20, 1815, at 11:34am Napoleon is wholly present. Four dimensionalists, on the other hand, maintain that a material object is only partially present at each instant at which it exists: on October 20, 1815, at 11:34am a temporal slice of Napoleon is present, not the whole Napoleon. Three and fourdimensionalism, thus, aim at providing a metaphysical account of the persistence of material objects through time. (There are other theoretical options, such as the so called stage view, that I am here omitting for the sake of space.) Contenders in the other distinction are the so called presentists and eternalists. Those defending the first view claim that only present entities exist; so, literally speaking, the exile of Napoleon is an empty description, although there may be at present entities whose existence is explained also in terms of such a description. On the other side of the spectrum, eternalists claim that past, present, and future entities all exist; thus, the exile of Napoleon is real as much as the fact that you are reading this words right now. (I m omitting

here, again for the sake of space, other intermediate positions, such as the so called growing universe view, according to which only the past and the present exist, but not the future.) Time and Realism does not make use of the three vs four dimensionalist nor of the presentist vs eternalist oppositions; no mention is made of the first one, while the second is quoted on p.6, where it is regarded as equivalent to the tensed vs tenseless opposition. This absence renders the conceptual articulation of the book wanting in a number of places. For example, much of the discussion in Chapter 4 on the emergence of a ontology of time would benefit from the introduction of both distinctions (especially the discussion of Mellor s view, 4.3); or, the examination of Dummett s position ( 3.2) would be more transparent, if Dummett were more explicitly characterized as a presentist. More generally, the sole use of a semantic distinction (tensed vs tenseless) throughout the volume strikes as peculiar, considering that the book deals with ontological accounts of time. Let us now move to consider Chapters 5 and 6, where Dolev lays out his most original material. It is here that he purports to show that the major ontological issues on the nature of time can be transcended. With this expression Dolev expresses an attitude, proper also of the late Wittgenstein, according to which the philosophical conundrums that arise when we peruse for longer than usual our ordinary worldview can be dissolved; and the role of the philosopher is precisely to show how this can be done. Thus, the key to transcend the ontological issues on the nature of time lies in realizing that tense cannot be cast in ontological terms. (p. 114) This conviction is arrived at after a meticulous examination of the tensed and tenseless views, both of which it is argued cannot provide a satisfactory explanation of time s passage (among other issues). Whether Dolev s assessment of these views is accurate I shall leave open. What strikes as particularly challenging is his tentative of dissolution of the ontological issues on the nature of time. Having to select some portions of it, I will concentrate, in order, on his

alleged dissolution of two problems: of the duration of the present moment ( 5.1) and of the presence of experience ( 5.2). Other problems for which he tries to account are: the fact that remembered experiences appear as past ( 5.3); the flow of time ( 5.4); the tensed character of first person experience ( 5.5); the apparent openness of the future ( 5.6); and the implications of Relativity Theory on our conception of time ( 5.7). How long is the present moment? On his way to reply this question, Dolev at first notices that there is a striking discrepancy between the philosopher s vanishing present and the apparent temporal voluminousness of present events and states of affairs. (p. 118) Building on this remark, he then argues that this old and vexed question becomes problematic only once we start presuming (as the typical philosopher does) that there has to be one specific duration which constitutes the answer to such question. It is unclear, however, whether Dolev provides sufficient ground upon which to rest his argument. He brings forward two points that are, allegedly, in his favor; but neither of them seems tenable. The first is an appeal to the reader s intuitions: it seems evident to me that there is nothing wrong with speaking, say, of the hockey game as opposed to some instantaneous parts of the game as present event. (p. 118) With this I might agree, if it were not for the fact that it is also evident to me that there is nothing wrong with speaking, say, of the hockey game as being partially gone and partially yet to be done, thus implying that only a tiny fraction of it is present; this strikes me as the way in which most players, the coach and many spectators probably conceive of the game in order to make the most of it. Thus, which conception one ought to favor is unclear and it seems that one could contemplate both at once. The second point hinges on an analogy between the adverbs here and now : It is evident that here is not pointlike, that by asserting that she is here, in New York, Dana does not mean that the whole of New York is somehow

here, inside her room. But then why would anyone have thought that by asserting that the game is now in progress, one might have meant that the entire game, all three periods of it, are being played now, at this very instant? (p. 120) The analogy between space and time, is, however, not always a fitting one. At least phenomenically, the reasons why here differs from now are readily pointed out: while we are able to perceive extended regions of space, we are not able to perceive extended (or, at least: comparatively extended) regions of time; we may conceive of the latter and thus speak of them, and perhaps we may use our adverbs as referring to what we are conceiving; but, in their most crudely acquaintance related character, here and now differ substantially. Thus, Dolev s argument aiming at dissolving the problem of the duration of the present is found wanting. The suspicion is that, in order to pin down a solution to it, one would have to revert to some kind of ontological explanation the one that Dolev is trying to avoid. Let us now move to consider the problem of the presence of experience. In order to dissolve it, Dolev brings in an analogy with 50 and 279 of Wittgenstein s Philosophical Investigations (see pp. 132 136). There Wittgenstein argues that an entity cannot be the measure of itself; thus, for example, of the standard meter which is in Paris one cannot say that it is or that it is not a meter long. Along the same lines, for Dolev, an experience s presence is like S s meterhood: it is a ghost of a phenomenon, not something in relation to which the idea of an explanation, or an account, can be given in any sense. (p. 136) That an experience is present works as a standard for sorting out what is past, what is co present, and what is future; but, of the experience itself, it does not make sense to say that it is or that it is not present. Indeed, we certainly do not establish that e is present by comparing its temporal location with that of some other event. (p. 137) Dolev s point is well taken only if to establish what is present in one s experience turns out to be just a business of setting a standard, like when we have to measure the

length of an object. However, one could argue that the presence of experience is deeply rooted in a self conscious realization of being alive (as, for example, authors such as Sartre or Heidegger maintained). It is not accidental, one could note, that we speak of the presence of experience but not of the length of experience (with reference to the portion of space one is experiencing); indeed, the former is a concept which is constitutive of being a person, while the latter is not. Thus, when Mary says of her experience that it is present, she is saying something meaningful: roughly, that through such an experience she realizes that she is alive. And, if this is the case, then the analogy with Wittgenstein s line of argument is dispersed, and with it the alleged dissolution of the problem of the presence of experience.