Death and Discourse: An Inquiry into Meaning and Disruption James R. Goebel California State University, Fullerton

Similar documents
Heidegger Introduction

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

Published Citation Sealey, Kris. (2011). Desire as Disruption, Journal for Cultural and Religious Theory, Vol. 11(3), Fall 2011, pp

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

CHAPTER I INTRODUCTION. A. Research Background. being as opposed to society as a one organism (Macquarrie, 1973). Existentialism mainly finds

In its ultimate version, McCraw proposes that H epistemically trusts S for some proposition, p, iff:

Our presentation of Lévinas

METAPHYSICS IN DERRIDA AND LEVINAS

J. Aaron Simmons and Bruce Ellis Benson, The New Phenomenology: A Philosophical Introduction (New York: Bloomsbury, 2013)

Review on Heidegger and Philosophical Atheology

Thinking the Abyss of History: Heidegger s Critique of Hegelian Metaphysics

Heidegger and Levinas: Metaphysics, Ontology and the Horizon of the Other

From Phenomenology to Theology: You Spin Me Round *

The Supplement of Copula

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Jacob Martin Rump, PhD Symposium: Contemporary Work in Phenomenology Boston Phenomenology Circle Boston University, 1 April 2016

Follow this and additional works at: Part of the Philosophy Commons

SIMONE DE BEAUVOIR: ARE WOMEN COMPLICIT IN THEIR OWN SUBJUGATION, IF SO HOW?

borderlands e-journal

PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT FALL SEMESTER 2009 COURSE OFFERINGS

DEONTOLOGY AND MORAL RESPONSIBILITY

Divisibility, Logic, Radical Empiricism, and Metaphysics

Phil 311: Phenomenology and Existentialism Fall 2007 Syllabus

In Search of a Political Ethics of Intersubjectivity: Between Hannah Arendt, Emmanuel Levinas and the Judaic

Heidegger's What is Metaphysics?

EXAM PREP (Semester 2: 2018) Jules Khomo. Linguistic analysis is concerned with the following question:

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

Christian Lotz, Commentary, SPEP 2009 Formal Indication and the Problem of Radical Philosophy in Heidegger

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

Response to Gregory Floyd s Where Does Hermeneutics Lead? Brad Elliott Stone, Loyola Marymount University ACPA 2017

John Haugeland. Dasein Disclosed: John Haugeland s Heidegger. Edited by Joseph Rouse. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2013.

Levinas, Meaning, and Philosophy of Social Science: From Ethical Metaphysics to Ontology and Epistemology

THE CRISIS OF THE SCmNCES AS EXPRESSION OF THE RADICAL LIFE-CRISIS OF EUROPEAN HUMANITY

The Character of Space in Kant s First Critique By Justin Murphy October 16, 2006

The Sea-Fight Tomorrow by Aristotle

Undergraduate Calendar Content

EXISTENTIALISM AND FILM. LECTURE NOTES:

Affirmative Judgments: The Sabbath of Deconstruction

Week 4: God and Existence

RUNNING HEAD: Philosophy and Theology 1. Christine Orsini RELS 111 Professor Fletcher March 21, 2012 Short Writing Assignment 2

To Provoke or to Encourage? - Combining Both within the Same Methodology

Response to The Problem of the Question About Animal Ethics by Michal Piekarski

Fabrizio Luciano, Università degli Studi di Padova

3 Supplement. Robert Bernasconi

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

Reply to Robert Koons

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

A Philosophical Study of Nonmetaphysical Approach towards Human Existence

TEILHARD DE CHARDIN, A. N. WHITEHEAD AND A METAPHYSICS OF INTERSUBJECTIVITY

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

Who is Able to Tell the Truth? A Review of Fearless Speech by Michel Foucault. Los Angeles, CA: Semiotext(e), 2001.

Introduction. 1 Bertrand Russell, The Problems of Philosophy (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, n.d.), 7.

MODELS CLARIFIED: RESPONDING TO LANGDON GILKEY. by David E. Klemm and William H. Klink

At the Frontiers of Reality

Phenomenology and Metaphysical Realism 1. Robert D. Stolorow. Abstract: This article examines the relationship between totalitarianism and the

SPINOZA, SUBSTANCE, AND SUBJECTIVITY IN HEGEL S LECTURES ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION

The Other Half of Hegel s Halfwayness: A response to Dr. Morelli s Meeting Hegel Halfway. Ben Suriano

Postmodern Religious Thought IDSEM-UG.1672 Gallatin School of Individualized Study New York University Spring 2012

Review of This Is Not Sufficient: An Essay on Animality and Human Nature in Derrida. Leonard Lawlor Columbia University Press pp.

BRANKO KLUN. University of Ljubljana. Horizon, Transcendence, and Correlation: Some Phenomenological Considerations 1

World View, Metaphysics, and Epistemology

Introduction to the Issue

François Laruelle and the Non-Philosophical Tradition

Week 3: Negative Theology and its Problems

History 1324: French Social Thought From Durkheim to Foucault Prof. Peter E. Gordon Department of History Harvard University

Craig on the Experience of Tense

Existentialism Philosophy 303 (12070) Fall 2011 TR 9:30-10:45 Kinard 312

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

Heidegger s Unzuhandenheit as a Fourth Mode of Being

PROFESSOR FULTON'S VIEW OF PHENOMENOLOGY

Haecceitas and the Question of Being: Heidegger and Duns Scotus

HEIDEGGER AND DERRIDA ON DEATH A THESIS SUBMITTED TO THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF SOCIAL SCIENCES OF MIDDLE EAST TECHNICAL UNIVERSITY

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things:

Perspectival Methods in Metaphysics

Weekend Retreat and Workshop, Heidegger, Being and Time Graduate Seminar, Lotz Nov 21-Nov 23, 2008 Seminarpage

THE FICHTEAN IDEA OF THE SCIENCE OF KNOWLEDGE. by Jean Hyppolite*

Tatyana P. Lifintseva, Professor at the School of Philosophy, NRU HSE Staraya Basmannaya ul., 21/4, office

Reality. Abstract. Keywords: reality, meaning, realism, transcendence, context

Iowa Journal of Cultural Studies

Saying, Showing, and Sharing

BOOK REVIEWS. The arguments of the Parmenides, though they do not refute the Theory of Forms, do expose certain problems, ambiguities and

The Subject after Humanism: Towards an open subjectivity for education

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

11/23/2010 EXISTENTIALISM I EXISTENTIALISM. Existentialism is primarily interested in the following:

PART TWO EXISTENCE AND THE EXISTENT. D. The Existent

Introducing Levinas to Undergraduate Philosophers

Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins

A phenomenological interpretation of religion via pre-socratic thinking. University of Notre Dame Australia

THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN SCIENCE, RELIGION AND ARISTOTELIAN THEOLOGY TODAY

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Ethics and the Primacy of the Other: A Levinasian Foundation for Phenomenological Research

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable

The Singularity of the Self

FAITH & REASON THE JOURNAL OF CHRISTENDOM COLLEGE

Hannah Arendt and the fragility of human dignity

Existentialism Philosophy 303 (CRN 12245) Fall 2013

Life, Automata and the Mind-Body Problem

The Paradox of Sense, or On the Event of Thought in Gilles Deleuze s Philosophy. Sanja Dejanovic


Transcription:

Death and Discourse: An Inquiry into Meaning and Disruption James R. Goebel California State University, Fullerton Abstract: In Being and Nothingness, Jean-Paul Sartre vehemently argues that we must assume the world with the proud consciousness of being its authors, as it is only in and through our projects that the world has Meaning. I explore Martin Heidegger s The Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics to develop a brief analysis of language that locates Meaning in the speaking human subject. I argue that while language does provide a pre-reflective foundation of Meaning onto the world, there are events that have the potential to severely disrupt that Meaning and, therefore, the potential to challenge Sartre s existential-phenomenological framework. In Being and Nothingness, Jean-Paul Sartre vehemently argues that we must assume the world with the proud consciousness of being its authors, as it is only in and through our projects that the world has Meaning (Sartre 1943, p. 707). Among a heritage of phenomenological thinkers such as Hegel, Husserl and Heidegger, Sartre argues that substance, or the world-as-phenomena, appears as substance only for consciousness. Meaning, as a force of signification that is placed onto the world, therefore, presents and sustains itself within the human subject (Sartre 1943, p. 239). The purpose of this paper is to explore the limitations of Meaning as it is conceptualized in Sartre s existential-phenomenological framework. That said, it would not be enough to ask, How is it that we come into Meaning? or How do we give Meaning to the world? Such questions inquire into the sociological and psychological mechanics of how the human subject relates to Meanings provided by cultural and familial contexts while Meaningas-such finds itself already presupposed and, moreover, uninterrogated. The guiding thread of our inquiry, if we wish to have any insight into Meaning, should then be fashioned in such a way that Meaning is put at great risk. We must ask in a preliminary In The California Undergraduate Philosophy Review, vol. 1, pp. 117-124. Fresno, CA: California State University, Fresno.

118 James R. Goebel sense: Are there non- or extra-human events that resist the jurisdiction of existential-phenomenological Meaning? Before we answer this question, however, we must detour in order to provide a deeper understanding of the way in which the human subject occupies the locus of Meaning. In the following section, I explore Martin Heidegger s interpretation of various Greek terms in order to develop a brief analysis of language that lends itself to the existential-phenomenological framework. The key point that emerges from this development is a representation of substance, or the material/natural world, as purely semiotic. That is, because Meaning is located solely within the speaking human subject, a limited directional pattern is assumed in which semiotics always determine the meaning of world, and never world that determines the meaning of semiotics. 1 This position has, since the rise of poststructuralist thought, been a source of great debate. I will argue that while language does provide a pre-reflective foundation of Meaning onto the world, there are events that have the potential to severely disrupt that Meaning and, therefore, the potential to challenge the Sartrean thesis. 1.!"#$% [lógos] and Tearing From Concealment: Metaphysics, Truth and Presuppositions In The Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics, we find Martin Heidegger conducting an inquiry into the Greek term µ!"# "# $%&'(# [metá tá phúsiká], an early expression of the word metaphysics that served to designate philosophy. 2 He begins by breaking down the last-mentioned term, $%&'(# [phúsiká], to $%&') [phusis], a term customarily translated as nature, which itself comes from the Latin natura: to be born, to arise, to grow. Heidegger writes, We here take growth and growing in the primal experience of man as [an] occurring in the midst of, and permeated by, the changing of the seasons the alternation of day and night the wandering stars, of storms and weather and the raging of the elements. Growing is all this taken together as one. (1929, p. 25) Heidegger pushes us into this understanding of growing so that $%&') can be interpreted, not in the literal sense of growth, but rather as the self-forming prevailing of beings as a whole (1929, p. 25). The processes of procreation, birth, childhood, maturing, aging and death, are, therefore, understood not as strictly biological 1 Patrick McGann (2002, p. 83 makes a similar argument in relation to the body. 2 All Greek translations are Martin Heidegger, (1929, pp. 25-26).

Death and Discourse 119 processes of nature, but as the general prevailing of beings, which comprehends within itself human fate and its history [that which man] does not have power over, but which precisely prevails through and around him (1929, p. 25). *%&') appears to have an ontological status in Heidegger s interpretation and, in fact, this appears more so in his analysis of the Greek term +,-.), which literally translates as word or speech. He writes, Man, insofar as he exists as man, has always already spoken out about $%&'), about the prevailing whole to which he himself belongs (1929, p. 25). This speaking out of $%&'), of prevailing beings and their order and constitution, provides a deeper understanding than the literal translation of +,-.) because whatever is spoken out, for Heidegger, is already necessarily grounded within $%&'), otherwise it could not be spoken out of it (1929, p. 25). To further explore the function of +,-.) in Heidegger, we must introduce two more Greek terms he uses:!"#$%& [légeín], which Heidegger translates to bringing out of concealment and into word, and its antithesis, (/%!"!'0 [krupteín], or keeping concealed and in concealment. For Heidegger, the fundamental function of!"#$%& is to reveal, or take out of concealment, that which conceals itself in $%&'). He writes, Revealing is that happening which occurs in the +,-.). In the +,-.) the prevailing of beings [$%&')] becomes revealed, becomes manifest (1929, p. 27). Let us analyze the statement, the ball is round. The simple analysis tells us that what I have done is connected an object in the world, i.e. the ball, to a predicate, i.e. round. Yet, what further inquiry discloses is that I have revealed or brought out of concealment several truths about the world: that there is an I and some notion of reality that makes my utterance possible, that there are objects and predicates in this reality, and that there are relationships among these objects and predicates. The objection could be made that the statement has done nothing to reveal truth. Heidegger writes, Yet, what is at issue is by no means the claim that this speaking out should be true, that statements about $%&') should be true and not false. It is rather a matter of comprehending what truth means here, and how the truth of $%&') is understood in this commencement. (1929, pp. 28-29) The Greek term, 1+23!41 [alétheia], does not readily translate into the German Warheit, or truth. However, Heidegger interprets 1+23!41 to mean, that which is not concealed, or that which has been unconcealed. He writes, The Greeks thus implicitly understand something negative in the innermost essence of truth In truth

120 James R. Goebel beings are torn from concealment Truth is innermost confrontation of the essence of man with the whole of beings themselves (1929, p. 29). The prevailing of beings, $%&'), as Heidegger understands it, their order and constitution and the law of beings themselves as grounded in $%&') is that towards which +,-.) addresses and forms itself (1929, p. 26). The function of language, thus far, is twofold: (1) it tears from concealment and brings to light the 1+23!41 of $%&'). Insofar as this is its function, to speak about and concern itself with the order and constitution of beings, language appears to be deeply metaphysical. (2) It expresses a confrontation and relationship between the speaker and that which speaking addresses, $%&'), in the name of 1+23!41 and, therefore, lays claim to truth as it is understood in the commencement of speaking. What remains to be addressed is the presuppositional nature of language. I refer here to an earlier observation that $%&') appears to be the ontological grounding toward which +,-.) addresses and forms itself in Heidegger s interpretation. However, I would suggest that this thesis could be traced to Nietzsche s The Twilight of the Idols in which he writes, I fear indeed that we shall never rid ourselves of God, since we still believe in grammar. 3 Michel Foucault provides one of the most insightful analyses into this dictum. He writes, God is perhaps not so much a region beyond knowledge as something prior to the sentences we speak; and if Western man is inseparable from him, it is not because of some invincible propensity to go beyond the frontiers of experience, but because his language ceaselessly foments him in the shadow of his laws. (1966, p. 298) What Nietzsche, Heidegger, and Foucault all seem to understand is the presupposed onto-axiomatic foundation on which language rests. Speaking does not begin with the vocal utterance of a sentence but with the onto-metaphysical presuppositions that make that sentence possible. II. The preliminary formulation of our guiding question can now be reformulated: Are there events in which &'()% resists *"#$%, and therefore resists being brought to +*,-./+? This brief analysis of language clearly lends itself to the Sartrean framework as Meaning is localized within the speaking human subject. The moment at which substance, or world, appears is the 3 Quoted in Foucault (1966, p. 130) from Friedrich Nietzsche, The Twilight of the Idols (First German ed. 1889; French trans. 1911).

Death and Discourse 121 moment at which +,-.), the word, tears it from concealment and brings it into 1+23!41, truth or understanding. The round ball of our earlier example, therefore, remains concealed from knowledge and Meaning until I have spoken about it and have brought it under the jurisdiction of +,-.). Once again, Sartre s words return to us. He writes, for the very worst disadvantages or the worst threats which can endanger my person have meaning only in and through my project; and it is on the ground of the engagement which I am that they appear (Sartre 1943, p. 708). And again, while discussing an existential-phenomenological epistemology, Sartre writes, While the relation of the for-itself to the in-itself is originally constitutive of the very being which is put into the relation, we should not understand that this relation is constitutive of the initself but rather of the for-itself. It is in the for-itself alone that we must look for the key to that relation to being which we call knowing. (1943, p. 239) This is the point at which controversy arises because, while Meaning is located solely within the human subject, a limited directional pattern is assumed in which the world is always the object of our Meaning and never our Meaning that is subject to the world. Our analysis of language, as brief as it may be, and the function of +,-.), in relation to the onto-axiomatic foundation on which Meaning rests, provide the Sartrean position with substantial weight. Yet, exposing the foundations on which the existentialphenomenological framework rests helps to illuminate its vulnerabilities. If the goal of our investigation is to disrupt Meaning, and if that Meaning rests upon presupposed, metaphysical claims to truth, then it is precisely these foundations that must be called into question. I want to suggest that the event of disruption, then, presents itself at least in the event of Death. III. In Being and Time, Heidegger writes, Death is the possibility of the absolute impossibility of Dasein. 4 What does this mean? Death as the incalculable arrival of the Other. In Totality and Infinity, Emmanuel Levinas argues that the whole of Western philosophy has been an attempt to reduce the Other to the Same by interposition of a middle and neutral term that ensures the comprehension of being (1961, p. 43). Traditionally, the Other 4 Heidegger (1927, p. 294).

122 James R. Goebel does not fall within the gaze of philosophical comprehension until it has first been turned into an object available for analysis, dissection, argumentation, refutation, etc. This process, according to Levinas, is a dispossession of the Other as outside of or beyond me and, as he writes, it is hence not a relation with the Other as such but the reduction of the Other to the Same (1961, p. 46). The brief analysis of language that we have provided elucidates this reductive process. As I speak about the round ball, there is a moment of objectification in which the ball becomes readily available for my analysis: What is its shape? Its color? Its weight? Thematization and conceptualization, what brings the object under the understanding of my onto-axiomatic foundations, are, for Levinas, forms in which a philosophy of power oppresses the Other (1961, p. 46). It should be no surprise then that traditional philosophy has turned Death into an object. In the publicness with which we are with one another in our everyday manner, Heidegger writes, death is known as a mishap which is constantly occurring as a case of death (1927, p. 296). The question for Levinas, however, which appears to be, prima facie, analogous to the guiding thread of our inquiry, is, How can the Same enter into relationship with an Other without immediately divesting it of its alterity? What is the nature of this relationship? (1961, p. 38). Levinas interests lie specifically in relations of inter-human subjectivity. The Other that traditional philosophy has reduced, and for whom Levinas seeks to restore a divine respect for, is the human Other. However, Levinas is faced with a difficult task: he must answer why that which is infinitely outside of and beyond me must meet certain preconditions to be recognized as Other than me. It appears that Levinas has undercut his own project: in order to first recognize the Other he or she must first be reduced to something like me. Despite this blunder, the Levinasian project should not be abandoned as he does provide an intriguing and useful phenomenological description of the Other and, using the more inclusive logic of Jacques Derrida, the Other can move beyond relations of purely inter-human subjectivity and into the realm of the free, the incalculable, the unforeseeable, the undecidable, the event, the arrival what comes (2004, p. 51). Within the parameters of these conditions, of how the Other presents itself to me, we can now speak of Death without simultaneously divesting it of its radical alterity its status as infinitely outside of and beyond me and can now attempt to appropriately assess Heidegger s claim

Death and Discourse 123 that Death is the possibility of the absolute impossibility of Dasein (1927, p. 294). Heidegger argues, Death reveals itself as that possibility which is one s ownmost, which is non-relational, and which is not to be outstripped (1927, p. 294). Death becomes something I must face on my own accord as nobody can die in my place. Yet, Heidegger does acknowledge that while my Death may be my ownmost possibility, I nonetheless experience the event and presence of Death in Others. As Dasein I am possibility, and Death, as the possibility of my impossibility, and as it presents itself to me through Others, manifests as radically Other than me; it is an event that is distinctively impending but has not yet come to me (1927, p. 294). For both Levinas and Derrida, the Other contains within itself the idea of Infinity. Levinas writes, The idea of Infinity is the overflowing of an adequate idea. If totality can not be constituted it is because Infinity does not permit itself to be integrated (1961, p. 80). Thus, any attempt to thematize or conceptualize in whole the event or presence of Death will be problematic because Death, as Infinitely outside of and beyond me, and in fact the negation of me, is Infinitely separate from me. It is this Infinite separation in the presence of Death that pushes me into ambiguity: how do I, or more appropriately, how can I understand or speak about Death without first divesting it of its radical alterity? As Derrida writes, There is no horizon for the Other it can fall upon me, or surprise me by coming at my back, from behind or below and in such a way that I don t see it coming (2004, p. 52). IV. The severe disruption of Meaning as the calling into question of Freedom. The role of language, as we have briefly attempted to understand it, is to objectify that which is Other than the speaker: as I bring the world into myself, I bring it within the understanding of my ontoaxiomatic foundations and reduce its ambiguities. Such is the definition of freedom, Levinas writes, to maintain oneself against the Other (1961, p. 46). The guiding motivation of our inquiry has been to find at least one event in which the unidirectional flow of Meaning, as presented within the Sartrean framework, is severely disrupted. Death, as the radical Other, as that which is outside of and beyond me calls into question the naïve right of my powers, my glorious spontaneity as a living being (1961, p. 84). If Freedom is defined as the ability to reduce the world to the onto-axiomatic foundations of semiotics, then the event of severe disruption must call into question my

124 James R. Goebel Freedom; Meaning must shudder before the immense ambiguities of the world. This, Levinas argues, is precisely how the Other presents itself, as him over whom I cannot have power, whom I cannot kill (1961, p. 84). I began this paper with the suggestion that if we wish to have any insight into Meaning, our inquiry must, in its task, put Meaning at great risk. The conception of the speaking human subject as the locus of Meaning carries with it a portrait: an existential human placed at the center of the universe furnished with the power of signification that somehow extends beyond itself and on to the world. As I have attempted to demonstrate, however, Death is at least one means by which Meaning can be displaced and severely disrupted. In the case of Death, there is something of the world that cannot be spoken of or, at least, not without returning back onto itself with acquired tensions and problematics. The implications of this displacement are to be further explored: Does the speaking human subject merely fumble onto the world? Or is this particular to the event of Death? If it turns out that Meaning is revealed to be boorish and clumsy, should not the existential value given to the speaking human subject be reconsidered or, perhaps, abandoned? In fact, are we not forced to come back onto ourselves? To question, not the object that falls under philosophical inquiry, but the philosophical inquiry itself? REFERENCES Derrida, J. and Roudinesco, E. (2004) For What Tomorrow : a Dialogue. Translated by J. Fort. Palo Alto, CA: Stanford University Press. Foucault, M. (1966/1994) The Order of Things: An Archaeology of the Human Science. New York, NY: Vintage Books. Heidegger, M. (1929/1995). The Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics: World, Finitude, Solitude. Translated by W. McNeill and N. Walker. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press. Heidegger, M. (1927/1962). Being and Time. Translated by J. Macquarrie and E. Robinson. San Francisco, CA: Harper Press. Levinas, E. (1961/1969) Totality and Infinity. Translated by A. Lingis. Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press. McGann, P. (2002). Eating Muscle. In N. Tuana, W. Cowling, M. Hamington, G. Johnson and T. MacMullan (eds.), Revealing Male Bodies, pp. 83-99. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press. Sartre, J. (1943/1992) Being and Nothingness. New York, NY: Washington Square Press.