ELEMENTS OF LOGIC. 1.1 What is Logic? Arguments and Propositions

Similar documents
A Primer on Logic Part 1: Preliminaries and Vocabulary. Jason Zarri. 1. An Easy $10.00? a 3 c 2. (i) (ii) (iii) (iv)

Pastor-teacher Don Hargrove Faith Bible Church September 8, 2011

Handout 2 Argument Terminology

Intro Viewed from a certain angle, philosophy is about what, if anything, we ought to believe.

PHILOSOPHY ESSAY ADVICE

Deduction. Of all the modes of reasoning, deductive arguments have the strongest relationship between the premises

A Brief Introduction to Key Terms

Lecture 3 Arguments Jim Pryor What is an Argument? Jim Pryor Vocabulary Describing Arguments

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 2. Background Material for the Exercise on Inference Indicators

Academic argument does not mean conflict or competition; an argument is a set of reasons which support, or lead to, a conclusion.

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 1. Background Material for the Exercise on Validity

Overview of Today s Lecture

Tutorial A02: Validity and Soundness By: Jonathan Chan

Argumentation Module: Philosophy Lesson 7 What do we mean by argument? (Two meanings for the word.) A quarrel or a dispute, expressing a difference

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

A. Problem set #3 it has been posted and is due Tuesday, 15 November

How to Write a Philosophy Paper

Mr Vibrating: Yes I did. Man: You didn t Mr Vibrating: I did! Man: You didn t! Mr Vibrating: I m telling you I did! Man: You did not!!

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE AND META-ETHICS

What we want to know is: why might one adopt this fatalistic attitude in response to reflection on the existence of truths about the future?

Logic Appendix: More detailed instruction in deductive logic

A R G U M E N T S I N A C T I O N

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Basic Concepts and Skills!

CRITICAL THINKING (CT) MODEL PART 1 GENERAL CONCEPTS

C. Problem set #1 due today, now, on the desk. B. More of an art than a science the key things are: 4.

Moore on External Relations

Circularity in ethotic structures

Criticizing Arguments

C. Exam #1 comments on difficult spots; if you have questions about this, please let me know. D. Discussion of extra credit opportunities

Introduction to Philosophy

Kripke on the distinctness of the mind from the body

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information

MCQ IN TRADITIONAL LOGIC. 1. Logic is the science of A) Thought. B) Beauty. C) Mind. D) Goodness

HOW TO ANALYZE AN ARGUMENT

Follow Will of the People. Your leftist h. b. ave often d1sgusted b h

Skim the Article to Find its Conclusion and Get a Sense of its Structure

Lecture 2.1 INTRO TO LOGIC/ ARGUMENTS. Recognize an argument when you see one (in media, articles, people s claims).

Introduction to Philosophy

What is a logical argument? What is deductive reasoning? Fundamentals of Academic Writing

To better understand VALIDITY, we now turn to the topic of logical form.

PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Module 5. Knowledge Representation and Logic (Propositional Logic) Version 2 CSE IIT, Kharagpur

Logic for Computer Science - Week 1 Introduction to Informal Logic

How Gödelian Ontological Arguments Fail

HANDBOOK. IV. Argument Construction Determine the Ultimate Conclusion Construct the Chain of Reasoning Communicate the Argument 13

On A New Cosmological Argument

Chapter 1 - Basic Training

Introduction Symbolic Logic

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Logic & Proofs. Chapter 3 Content. Sentential Logic Semantics. Contents: Studying this chapter will enable you to:

Rawls versus utilitarianism: the subset objection

Genuine dichotomies expressed using either/or statements are always true:

Merricks on the existence of human organisms

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Truth and Modality - can they be reconciled?

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

BASIC CONCEPTS OF LOGIC

A Note on Straight-Thinking

Paradox of Deniability

LOGIC Lesson 10: Univocal, Equivocal, Analogical Terms. 1. A term in logic is the subject or the predicate of a proposition (a declarative sentence).

SHORT ANSWER. Write the word or phrase that best completes each statement or answers the question.

BENEDIKT PAUL GÖCKE. Ruhr-Universität Bochum

The Critical Mind is A Questioning Mind

Logical Omniscience in the Many Agent Case

Phil 435: Philosophy of Language. P. F. Strawson: On Referring

Chapter 1. Introduction. 1.1 Deductive and Plausible Reasoning Strong Syllogism

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

Chapter 8 - Sentential Truth Tables and Argument Forms

What are Truth-Tables and What Are They For?

A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC FOR METAPHYSICIANS

BASIC CONCEPTS OF LOGIC

INDUCTION. All inductive reasoning is based on an assumption called the UNIFORMITY OF NATURE.

! Introduction to the Class! Some Introductory Concepts. Today s Lecture 1/19/10

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

Compatibilism and the Basic Argument

G.E. Moore A Refutation of Skepticism

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

Introduction to Logic

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

Reconstructing Arguments 1. Reconstructing Arguments 3. Reconstructing Arguments 2. HW #4 is due on Thursday Longer than usual (and on ch.

Some Logical Paradoxes from Jean Buridan

National Quali cations

Is the law of excluded middle a law of logic?

How should I live? I should do whatever brings about the most pleasure (or, at least, the most good)

Proofs of Non-existence

Informalizing Formal Logic

THEOLOGICAL METHOD AND INERRANCY: A REPLY TO PROFESSOR HOLMES

PHIL2642 CRITICAL THINKING USYD NOTES PART 1: LECTURE NOTES

John Buridan. Summulae de Dialectica IX Sophismata

Aquinas Cosmological argument in everyday language

Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak.

Instructor s Manual 1

Charles Saunders Peirce ( )

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

2. Refutations can be stronger or weaker.

Externalism and a priori knowledge of the world: Why privileged access is not the issue Maria Lasonen-Aarnio

Since Michael so neatly summarized his objections in the form of three questions, all I need to do now is to answer these questions.

Transcription:

Handout 1 ELEMENTS OF LOGIC 1.1 What is Logic? Arguments and Propositions In our day to day lives, we find ourselves arguing with other people. Sometimes we want someone to do or accept something as true and so we find ourselves citing various reasons for why they ought to do what we want or accept what we think to be the case. Other people are no different. They wish to convince us of something and so they use various tactics to get our assent. Sometimes we find their tactics convincing, other times we are unpersuaded, and other times we are unsure what we should think. Logic is a science that aims to identify principles for good and bad reasoning. In essence, it aims to develop criteria (rules or methods) for the identification of good and bad arguments. Good Arguments Arguments Logic Bad Arguments Figure 1.1 Logic aims to identify good arguments In formulating criteria for good and bad arguments, the focus of logic is on arguments, not on arguing. Arguing and arguments differ in many important ways. Arguing is a broader, more complex phenomena that often, although not always, includes arguments. When we argue, it is often directed at some other person (our friends, family, or strangers), it can involve yelling, the rolling of our eyes in disbelief, or some other gesture. In contrast, an argument is a sequence of sentences (called propositions ) where some proposition (called the conclusion ) is represented as following from another set of propositions (called the premises ).

1.1 What is Logic? Arguments and Propositions 3 Definition Argument An argument is a series of propositions in which a certain proposition (the conclusion) is represented as following from another set of propositions (the premises or assumptions). One way to think about the concept of an argument is that an argument is an abstraction (or selection) from what goes on when people argue. That is, part of what people do (or at least aim to do) when they argue is to utter sentences that support some other sentence. In doing this, they put forward arguments. Arguments abstraction Arguing Figure 1.2 An argument can be understood as an abstraction from the everyday practice of arguing 1.1.1 Propositions The definition of an argument contains a number of terms that need clarification. First, an argument is a series of propositions. What is a proposition? Definition Proposition A proposition is a sentence (or something that is expressed by a sentence) that is capable of being true or false. Example 1: Examples of Propositions 1. John is tall. 2. There are 10,234 trees in State College. 3. Socrates is Mortal. Many types of things do not express propositions. For example: Questions: Is John tall? Exclamations: Woah! Commands: Close the door. Performative Utterances: I do uttered on your wedding day.

4 ELEMENTS OF LOGIC Key Ideas about Propositions 1. Sentence Proposition: While all propositions are expressed by sentences, not all sentences express propositions, e.g. commands, questions, exclamations do not express propositions. 2. Many Sentences Can Express One Proposition: A single proposition can be expressed in a variety of different ways (a) Example 1: John loves Liz vs. Liz is loved by John. (b) Example 2: A single proposition expressed in two different languages 3. One Sentence Can Express Many Propositions: A single sentence does not always express the same proposition, e.g. I ate breakfast 4. Being T or F vs. Knowing T of F: While a proposition must express content that is true or false (or can be true or false), it is not necessary that you know the truth value of a sentence (or know how to confirm the truth value) in order for the sentence to be a proposition, e.g. there are 50,304 trees in State College. Exercise 1: Determine whether the following sentences express propositions. 1. Be a yardstick of quality. 2. Don t make friends with drug dealers. 3. How may I help you? 4. I know that God exists. 5. God does not exist. 1.1.2 Premises and the Conclusion Two other key terms in the definition of an argument are premises and conclusion. The terms premises and conclusion refer to the role certain propositions play in an argument. Intuitively, the premises or the premise of an argument plays a supporting role in that they serve to support or act as evidence or reasons for a conclusion. The conclusion plays the role of proposition that is supported. To illustrate, note that in Argument 1.1 there are three propositions, labeled (P1), (P2), and (C). (P1) and (P2) are the premises and they support (C), the conclusion. 1.1.3 How to Identify Arguments An argument is not a mere list of sentences nor is it a list of propositions. For example, some sets of sentences are not wholly composed of propositions (e.g., a list of questions) and so they are not arguments. In other cases, there are a

1.1 What is Logic? Arguments and Propositions 5 Premises Argument Propositions Conclusion Figure 1.3 Arguments consists of propositions (premises and a conclusion) P1 All women are mortal. Premise P2 Liz is a woman. Premise C Therefore, Liz is mortal. Conclusion Argument 1.1 An argument consisting of three propositions, two premises, and a single conclusion. series of sentences, all of which propositions, but these propositions don t take on the role of premise or conclusion (e.g. a descriptive account of your day is not an argument). Identifying what is and what is not an argument is an art. 1. Look to see if the sentences or words consist of propositions. 2. Identify certain key terms called argument indicators like therefore, in conclusion, since, it follows that that indicate the presence of an argument. 3. Determine whether one proposition (the conclusion) can plausibly be said to logically follow from another set of propositions (the premises or an assumption). For example, suppose three propositions P1, P2, P3, test whether they are an argument by writing P1, P2, therefore P3, then P1, P3, therefore P2. 4. Look for certain conventional practices in how arguments are expressed, e.g. its presentation in a schematic or standard form. Indicators of Premises because..., for, since, for the reason that..., is supported by..., may (or can) be deduced from,... is a reason,... suggests Indicators of Conclusions therefore, hence, in conclusion, so, entails, implies that, indicates, therefore, consequently, we may (can) deduce that, suggests..., it follows that.., Table 1.1 Common Argument Indicators While arguments do not have a single order of presentation, a standard way of presenting arguments is as follows:

6 ELEMENTS OF LOGIC First Second Third Premises/Assumptions Argument Indicator Conclusion Table 1.2 A Diagrammatic Presentation of an Argument Example 1: John told me that David is a bad teacher. Frank also told me that David is a bad teacher. John and Frank are never wrong about who is a good or bad teacher because they have failing grades. Therefore, David must be a bad teacher. P1 John told me that David is a bad teacher. Premise P2 Frank also told me that David is a bad teacher. Premise P3 John and Frank are never wrong about who is a good Premise or bad teacher because they have failing grades. C Therefore, David must be a bad teacher. Conclusion Argument 1.2 argument indicator therefore Exercise 2: Classroom Exercise: Create Your Own Argument! In a small group, create your own argument. Make sure you label the premises, the conclusion, and any terms that be considered argument indicators. 1.2 Evaluating Arguments Recall that logic is a science that aims to separate good arguments from bad arguments. Tagging an argument as good or bad involves evaluating the quality of an argument. What makes an argument good? This partly depends upon the purpose of the argument. If we only expect arguments to entertain us or be thought-provoking, then whether the premises of the argument are true or not might not be of our concern. If we only want arguments to consist of only true propositions, then we might read-off each proposition of the argument and determine whether it is true (or false). That is, we would evaluate the argument independent of the relation between the premises and the conclusion. If, however, we want the argument to be truth-preserving (viz., it is impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion to be false), then our focus is principally on the relationship between the premises and the conclusion. This latter desire is the one pursued in this text. 1.3 Deductive Validity

1.3 Deductive Validity 7 Definition Deductive Validity An argument is deductively valid if and only if it is logically impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion false. Alternatively put, an argument that is deductively valid is one where it is necessarily the case that if the premises are true, then the conclusion is true. So, a valid argument that has all true premises must have a true conclusion. An initial confusion involved in understanding the concept of deductive validity is that people sometimes think that in order for an argument to be deductively valid, the premises and the conclusion must, in fact, be true. This is not the case for when we consider whether an argument is deductively valid, we don t consider the actual truth or falsity of the premises but rather consider whether it is logically impossible for all of the premises to be true and the conclusion false. What this means then is that an argument can be deductively valid where the argument has: 1. true premises and a true conclusion 2. false premises and a true conclusion 3. false premises and a false conclusion What cannot be the case is an argument that has true premises and a false conclusion. In fact, that scenario cannot be possible. To see this more clearly, consider that the propositions in an argument (the premises and the conclusion) can be true or false. Let s represent some of these combinations as follows: Premise True True False True True False Premise True False False True False False Conclusion True True True False False True 1 2 3 4 5 6 Table 1.3 Argument is valid if and only if column 4 is impossible An argument is deductively valid if and only if column (4) is logically impossible. That is, that (4) cannot occur. To illustrate, consider the following argument: P1 P2 C Either Jennifer Lopez or Mario Lopez is the president of the United State of America (USA) Mario Lopez is not the president of USA. Therefore, Jennifer Lopez is the president of USA. Argument 1.3 Notice that premise (P1) is false. It is not the case that either Jennifer Lopez or Mario Lopez is the president of the USA. Nevertheless, if the premises (P1) and (P2) were true, would the conclusion also be true? The answer is a resounding Yes! It is impossible for (P1) and (P2) to be true while (C) is false. That is, it is necessarily the case that if (P1) and (P2) are true, then (C) is true. Thus,

8 ELEMENTS OF LOGIC the argument is deductively valid. 1.3.1 The Imagination Test for Deductive Validity How do we determine which arguments are valid and which are invalid? One answer is this: we determine which arguments are deductively valid (or invalid) by trying to imagine a scenario in which an argument s premises are true and its conclusion is false. If we are unable to imagine such a scenario, then the argument is valid. If we are able to imagine such a scenario, then the argument is invalid. Let s call this method the human-imagination method for determining valid arguments. This method feeds arguments to human subjects and then asks the subjects to imagine whether they can imagine a scenario where the premises are true and the conclusion is false. If they can, then the argument is invalid. If they cannot, the argument is invalid. Valid (Good Arguments) Arguments Human Imagination Invalid (Bad Arguments) Figure 1.4 Human-Imagination Method for Testing Arguments How does the human-imagination method for testing arguments work? First, we consider the question of whether an argument is deductively valid in the following terms Is it possible for all of the premises to be true and the conclusion false? Second, we try to imagine a scenario where the premises of the argument are true and the conclusion is false. Third, if such a scenario is imaginable, then the human-imagination method says the argument is not valid (invalid). If such a scenario is not imaginable, then the human-imagination method says the argument is valid. Let s consider a particular use of the human-imagination method on an argument considered earlier (see Argument 1.4). P1 P2 C Either Jennifer Lopez or Mario Lopez is the president of the United State of America (USA) Mario Lopez is not the president of USA. Therefore, Jennifer Lopez is the president of USA. Argument 1.4 An Argument for Jennifer Lopez as President To determine whether this argument is valid or invalid, we can first ask whether we can imagine a scenario where all of the premises to be true (P1 and P2) and the conclusion is false (C). If we can imagine such a scenario, then the argument is invalid. If we cannot imagine such a scenario, then the argument is valid. Let s consider another example (see Argument 1.5).

1.4 Soundness 9 Is it possible for all of the premises to be true and the conclusion false? Imagination Test: can you imagine a scenario where all of the premises are true and the conclusion is false? Yes No Invalid Valid Figure 1.5 Imagination Test for Valdiity P1 P2 C Some basketball players are millionaires. Some millionaires have fancy cars. Therefore, some basketball players have fancy cars. Argument 1.5 An Argument for Basketball Players Having Fancy Cars QUESTION RESULT (1) Is it possible for all of the premises to be true? Yes! (2) If the answer to (1) is yes, then is it logically possible for Yes! all of the premises to be true and the conclusion false? 3 If the answer to (2) is yes, then the argument is not valid. Not Valid! Table 1.4 Imagination test of Argument 1.5 It is logically possible for all of the premises to be true and the conclusion false because it is possible that basketball players do not have fancy cars, i.e., they may buy large homes and fancy jewelry but own modest cars. 1.4 Soundness Definition Sound An argument is sound if and only if all of the premises are (in fact) true and it is deductively valid. In short, soundness = valid + all true premises. We won t be concerned with soundness in this course, but is important to know that soundness is a stronger

10 ELEMENTS OF LOGIC notion than validity since an argument can be valid without being sound. Exercise 3: Valid or Invalid? 1. All pigs fly. Babe is a pig. Therefore, Babe flies. 2. John eats brains if and only if John is a zombie. John is not a zombie. Therefore, John does not eat brains. 3. John is happy. Therefore, John is happy or hungry. 4. God exists or he doesn t. Well, I see no good reason for thinking God exists. Therefore, God doesn t exist. 1.5 Problems with the Imagination Test Objection 1. Too Many Premises. First, using the imagination method seems relatively straightforward when dealing with arguments that are composed of one or two premises, but what about arguments with nine, ten, fifty, or a hundred premises. In other words, we can imagine feeding P 1, P 2, P 3 to a human subject and it being capable of telling us whether or not it is a good or bad argument. P 1 Good Arguments P 2 Human Subject P 3 Bad Arguments Figure 1.6 Imagination Method for Testing Arguments But, at some point, human beings will struggle with imagining whether it is possible for some large, but finite, number of premises A 1, A 2, A 3... A n is true and the conclusion false. That is, at some point, human beings will become exhausted and no longer be able to tell us whether or not the argument is good or bad. In short, it would be nice if there were some way to evaluate whether or not an argument is good or bad that does not depend upon the finite powers of human beings. Objection 2. Human Bias & Disagreement. A second problem with the human-imagination method is that it is unclear how human subjects are evaluating the arguments they are given. Subjects may evaluate an argument as a good argument or correct reasoning when it is in conflict with the facts simply because they desire the conclusion to be true. In short, it would be nice if there were some way to evaluate arguments using certain criteria that is as independent of human bias. Objection 3. Ambiguity A third problem with the human-imagination method is that human beings evaluate arguments in a natural language that allows for different forms of imprecision. For example, arguments that have ambiguous terms allow for equivocation.

1.5 Problems with the Imagination Test 11 P1 P2 C A pencil is light Light has no weight Therefore, a pencil has no weight. Argument 1.6 Argument for the weightlessness of pencils. In Argument 1.6, light is used in two different ways: (i) not being heavy, and (ii) a kind of electromagnetic radiation that the human eye can see. P1 P2 C Every student in logic did not pass the exam. John is a student in logic. Therefore, John did not pass the exam. Argument 1.7 Argument for the weightlessness of pencils. (P1) is ambiguous. If (P1) means no student in logic passed the exam, then Argument 1.7 is valid. If, however, (P1) means there exists at least one student who didn t pass the logic exam, then Argument 1.7 is invalid. Questions 1. What is logic? 2. What is an argument? 3. What is a proposition? 4. Does the following sentence express a proposition: There are ten thousand atoms in the universe. 5. Does the following sentence express a proposition: Clean your room! 6. Does the following sentence express a proposition: Oh my! 7. Does the following sentence express a proposition: What is the answer to question 5? 8. What types of sentences do not express propositions? 9. How is an argument different from arguing? 10. What does it mean to say that an argument is deductively valid? 11. How can we test arguments to determine if they are deductive valid 12. What are some problems associated with the human-imagination test for validity? 13. What does it mean to say that an argument is sound? 14. Can an argument be sound if it is not valid? 15. Can an argument be sound if it has at least one false premise? 16. Is it possible for an argument to be valid, have true premises and a false conclusion? 17. Is it possible for an argument to be valid yet have false premises? 18. Is it possible for an argument to be valid, have one true premise and one false premise? 19. Assuming that an argument is valid and has true premises, is it possible for that argument to have a false conclusion? 20. Are valid arguments truth-preserving? That is, if the premises of a valid argument are true, does this guarantee the truth of the conclusion?