Review on Heidegger and Philosophical Atheology

Similar documents
Why There s Nothing You Can Say to Change My Mind: The Principle of Non-Contradiction in Aristotle s Metaphysics

Haecceitas and the Question of Being: Heidegger and Duns Scotus

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

On happiness in Locke s decision-ma Title being )

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Life has become a problem.

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

John Duns Scotus. 1. His Life and Works. Handout 24. called The Subtle Doctor. born in 1265 (or 1266) in Scotland; died in Cologne in 1308

Behavior and Other Minds: A Response to Functionalists

ABSTRACT of the Habilitation Thesis

FOUNDATIONALISM AND ARBITRARINESS

2. Refutations can be stronger or weaker.

Follow this and additional works at: Part of the Philosophy Commons

A CRITIQUE OF THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. A Paper. Presented to. Dr. Douglas Blount. Southwestern Baptist Theological Seminary. In Partial Fulfillment

Analytical Thomism: Traditions in Dialogue

COURSE SYLLABUS PHL 550: BEING AND TIME I

The Ontological Argument

1/5. The Critique of Theology

The Character of Space in Kant s First Critique By Justin Murphy October 16, 2006

IS GOD "SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?''

Discussion of McCool, From Unity to Pluralism

Reality. Abstract. Keywords: reality, meaning, realism, transcendence, context

IDOLATRY AND RELIGIOUS LANGUAGE

The title of this collection of essays is a question that I expect many professional philosophers have

Fabrizio Luciano, Università degli Studi di Padova

Friederike Rass. know is a highly talented physicist who regularly attends claustral retreats. These

Critique of Cosmological Argument

Introduction to Philosophy

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

COURSE SYLLABUS PHL 551: BEING AND TIME II

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to

Heidegger's What is Metaphysics?

The Trinity and the Enhypostasia

Excerpt from J. Garvey, The Twenty Greatest Philosophy Books (Continuum, 2007): Immanuel Kant s Critique of Pure Reason

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

From Being to Energy-Being: An Emerging Metaphysical Macroparadigm Shift in Western Philosophy. Preface

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Death and Discourse: An Inquiry into Meaning and Disruption James R. Goebel California State University, Fullerton

Jacob Martin Rump, PhD Symposium: Contemporary Work in Phenomenology Boston Phenomenology Circle Boston University, 1 April 2016

Charles Hartshorne argues that Kant s criticisms of Anselm s ontological

P. Weingartner, God s existence. Can it be proven? A logical commentary on the five ways of Thomas Aquinas, Ontos, Frankfurt Pp. 116.

The Courage of Dialogue

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

The Kalam Cosmological Argument

Christian Lotz, Commentary, SPEP 2009 Formal Indication and the Problem of Radical Philosophy in Heidegger

C. Exam #1 comments on difficult spots; if you have questions about this, please let me know. D. Discussion of extra credit opportunities

TEILHARD DE CHARDIN: TOWARD A DEVELOPMENTAL AND ORGANIC THEOLOGY

Heidegger Introduction

Imaging God in Our Bodily Lives: What Does Image of God Mean?

Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is

Rorty on Language and Social Practices

Does God exist? The argument from evil

Evaluating Heidegger s Fundamental Mood of Dread: Intentionality and Revealing

What Does Academic Skepticism Presuppose? Arcesilaus, Carneades, and the Argument with Stoic Epistemology

Summer Preparation Work

A Review of Christina M. Gschwandtner s Postmodern Apologetics? Arguments for God in Contemporary Philosophy (New York: Fordham UP, 2013)

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

Happiness and Personal Growth: Dial.

DESCARTES ONTOLOGICAL PROOF: AN INTERPRETATION AND DEFENSE

THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN SCIENCE, RELIGION AND ARISTOTELIAN THEOLOGY TODAY

Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa

A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES

LIBERTY: RETHINKING AN IMPERILED IDEAL. By Glenn Tinder. William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company Pp. xiv, 407. $ ISBN: X.

John Haugeland. Dasein Disclosed: John Haugeland s Heidegger. Edited by Joseph Rouse. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2013.

Time 1867 words Principles of Philosophy God cosmological argument

MODELS CLARIFIED: RESPONDING TO LANGDON GILKEY. by David E. Klemm and William H. Klink

Consciousness might be defined as the perceiver of mental phenomena. We might say that there are no differences between one perceiver and another, as

INVESTIGATING THE PRESUPPOSITIONAL REALM OF BIBLICAL-THEOLOGICAL METHODOLOGY, PART II: CANALE ON REASON

Anselm s Equivocation. By David Johnson. In an interview for The Atheism Tapes, from the BBC, philosopher Colin McGinn briefly

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

What Must There be to Account for Being?

Reflections on the Ontological Status

Lecture 18: Rationalism

The Absolute and the Relative

Descartes Theory of Contingency 1 Chris Gousmett

Man and the Presence of Evil in Christian and Platonic Doctrine by Philip Sherrard

Aristotle and Aquinas

Today s Lecture. Preliminary comments on the Problem of Evil J.L Mackie

Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

In what sense does consciousness provide its own criterion?

c Peter King, 1987; all rights reserved. WILLIAM OF OCKHAM: ORDINATIO 1 d. 2 q. 6

Response to Gregory Floyd s Where Does Hermeneutics Lead? Brad Elliott Stone, Loyola Marymount University ACPA 2017

Does God exist? The argument from evil

THE PHILOSOPHER S. A Compendium of Philosophical Concepts and Methods JULIAN BAGGINI AND PETER S. FOSL SECOND EDITION

Religious Language as Analogy

SOUTHWEST PHILOSOPHY REVIEW Vol. 28, No. 2 July, 2012

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

Forces and causes in Kant s early pre-critical writings

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

Religious Studies A new cosmological argument. Additional services for Religious Studies:

1. FROM ORIENTALISM TO AQUINAS?: APPROACHING ISLAMIC PHILOSOPHY FROM WITHIN THE WESTERN THOUGHT SPACE

On Finitism and the Beginning of the Universe: A Reply to Stephen Puryear. Citation Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 2016, v. 94 n. 3, p.

Reason in Islamic Law

What God Could Have Made

Plato s Euthyphro. G. J. Mattey. Spring, 2017 / Philosophy 1. Our first text will be from Plato and centered around his teacher Socrates ( BC).

What conditions does Plato expect a good definition to meet? Is he right to impose them?

Transcription:

BOOK REVIEW Volume 4, Issue, 1 pp. 3-7 Review on Heidegger and Philosophical Atheology by Peter S. Dillard Josh Harris* Heidegger and Philosophical Atheology is another rigorous and well-researched addition to the impressive array of books in the Continuum Studies in Continental Philosophy series. The author, Peter S. Dillard, is a self-avowed defender of the Scholastic tradition of philosophical theology, and the argument in this book is clearly driven by such an approach from the outset. He defines atheology as the rejection of the notion that the universe is created by a metaphysically independent Creator (1). Thus, insofar as Heidegger s critique of the metaphysical tradition extends to this basic theological commitment, he is an atheologian. The central argument of the book, then, is a Scholastic critique of this Heideggerian atheology. It is Dillard s contention that Heidegger s later philosophy proposes a view of contingency that ultimately leads to a contradiction. * Author Information: Trinity Western University, Vancouver, BC., Canada. Contact: joshualeeharris0@gmail.com Citation: Harris, J. (2014). Review on Heidegger and Philosophical Atheology by Peter S. Dillard. Praxis [Online] (4)1, pp. 3-7. 3

Secular readers should not be tempted to discard Dillard s argument on account of its outright appeal to orthodox Christian theology. It is metaphysics not historical theology that is the subject matter of this book. The first chapter deals primarily with Heidegger s early work on Thomas of Erfurt and John Duns Scotus, highlighting both his critique of psychologism (the idea that subjective judgment has direct ontological implications) and his affirmation of the Scotist concept of being that is common to all things, but prior to any categorical conceptualizations (p. 15). This early Heidegger has not yet imagined the antimetaphysical implications of his later work because he is content to accept the independence of thought from language (p. 21). Next, Dillard delves into the heart of Heidegger s atheology of Appropriation, which will eventually set the stage for Heidegger s view of contingency. Whereas the early Heidegger understands thought and language to be independent realms, the mature Heidegger attempts to bridge this gap towards the goal of a univocal, phenomenologically rich account of being one that does justice to the interrelated nature of thought and being (p. 26). In order to do this, Heidegger keeps the Scholastic transcendentals (truth, goodness, unity), but recasts them as historically disclosed transcendentals that are given by Appropriation [Ereignis] that sends both time and being (p. 36). Dillard then contrasts Heidegger s atheology of Appropriation with the Scotist argument for the existence of God. Scotus uses two traditional Scholastic premises in a modified way: 1. An infinite number of causes cannot exist. 2. That if a First Being exists, it exists necessarily. 4

From [1], it follows that the existence of a necessary First Being is possible. This is because a necessary First Being could be that which solves the infinite regress. Then, from [2], it follows that the First Being is actual. This is because, as necessary, the First Being is either actual or impossible and its impossibility has already been ruled out by premise [1]. Heidegger s atheology responds to this argument by rejecting the idea of a First Being altogether. For him, the existence of a necessary First Being is impossible because it is impossible for the sending of being to be caused (p. 52). In fact, this impossibility is the impetus behind Heidegger s coinage of the concept of Appropriation as an absolutely contingent, non-metaphysical sending of being. For him, the history of being might have happened in another way or not at all (p. 51). It is this final point that Dillard will critique in the final chapters, which come to a climax in his refutation of such a view of Appropriation. Heidegger s atheology is ultimately an account of nothingness as the answer to the question, why are there any things at all? For Heidegger, nothing causes, sends, or explains the history of being. It just happens (p. 88). Dillard s argument is an attempt to show why this view ultimately leads to a contradiction. 1. If it is possible for absolutely nothing to exist, then nothing is possible. 2. If nothing is possible, then the actual history of being is not possible. 3. But the actual history of being is possible because it is actual. 4. Therefore, by reductio ad absurdum, it is not possible to affirm Heidegger s position that it is possible for absolutely nothing to exist. While there is no doubt that Dillard s argument is as highly creative as it is tightly argued, it is difficult to imagine that students of Heidegger will be convinced by such a refutation. After 5

all, any metaphysical critique of a non-metaphysical philosophy must by definition have great difficulty hitting its mark, so to speak. It is also strange that Dillard only seems concerned with the early and later Heidegger, leaving Being and Time (1962) almost completely out of the picture These points notwithstanding, however, there is tremendous value in Dillard s argument insofar as it shows the great extent to which the precision of Scholastic metaphysics is very much relevant in contemporary continental philosophy. It may be, in fact, that this refutation does more to present a convincing apology for Scholastic metaphysics than it does to discredit Heidegger s philosophy. Even if this were the case, though, it would not diminish the significance of Dillard s achievement in this book. References Dillard, P., S., 2008. Heidegger and Philosophical Atheology. Maidenhead: Open University Press. UK: Continuum International Publishing Group Ltd. Heidegger, M., 1962. Being and Time. Translated from German by J. Macquarrie & E. Robinson. Harper Ltd. 6

7