ARE THE MORAL FIXED POINTS CONCEPTUAL TRUTHS?

Similar documents
THE MORAL FIXED POINTS: REPLY TO CUNEO AND SHAFER-LANDAU

THE UNBELIEVABLE TRUTH ABOUT MORALITY

STILL NO REDUNDANT PROPERTIES: REPLY TO WIELENBERG

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

A Rational Solution to the Problem of Moral Error Theory? Benjamin Scott Harrison

MORAL FIXED POINTS AND CONCEPTUAL DEFICIENCY: REPLY TO INGRAM (2015)

WHY WE REALLY CANNOT BELIEVE THE ERROR THEORY

DO NORMATIVE JUDGEMENTS AIM TO REPRESENT THE WORLD?

AN ACTUAL-SEQUENCE THEORY OF PROMOTION

Review of Erik J. Wielenberg: Robust Ethics: The Metaphysics and Epistemology of Godless Normative Realism

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

Dissolving the Debunker s Puzzle

CAN WE BELIEVE THE ERROR THEORY?

HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ

Epistemic Normativity for Naturalists

HYBRID NON-NATURALISM DOES NOT MEET THE SUPERVENIENCE CHALLENGE. David Faraci

Non-naturalism and Normative Necessities

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Shafer-Landau's defense against Blackburn's supervenience argument

PLEASESURE, DESIRE AND OPPOSITENESS

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

THINKING ANIMALS AND EPISTEMOLOGY

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

SCHROEDER ON THE WRONG KIND OF

The Puzzle of Pure Moral Motivation

EXTERNALISM AND THE CONTENT OF MORAL MOTIVATION

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE AND META-ETHICS

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

PRACTICAL REASONING. Bart Streumer

Hybridizing moral expressivism and moral error theory

Non-naturalism and Normative Necessities

The Tempering of a Defense: Further Critiques Against Error Theory in Light of Russ Shafer- Landau s Ethical Nonnaturalism

REASONS AND ENTAILMENT

Scanlon on Double Effect

Supervenience Arguments and Normative Non-naturalism

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Philosophy in Review XXXI (2011), no. 5

THE METAPHYSICS OF REASONS

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

PHILOSOPHY Metaethics. Course Text: Russ-Shafer-Landau and Terence Cuneo (eds.), Foundations of Ethics: An Anthology, Blackwell Publishing 2007.

Hume s Law Violated? Rik Peels. The Journal of Value Inquiry ISSN J Value Inquiry DOI /s

Faith and Philosophy, April (2006), DE SE KNOWLEDGE AND THE POSSIBILITY OF AN OMNISCIENT BEING Stephan Torre

CONCEPTUALIZING QUEERNESS

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY

Perception and Mind-Dependence: Lecture 2

Miller, Alexander, An Introduction to Contemporary Metaethics, Oxford: Polity Press, 2003, pp.

Well-Being, Time, and Dementia. Jennifer Hawkins. University of Toronto

Externalism and a priori knowledge of the world: Why privileged access is not the issue Maria Lasonen-Aarnio

e grounding argument against non-reductive moral realism

Psychological and Ethical Egoism

DANCY ON ACTING FOR THE RIGHT REASON

2210 Speedway, Stop C3500, WAG 316, Austin, TX (936)

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Philosophical Review.

The New Puzzle of Moral Deference. moral belief solely on the basis of a moral expert s testimony. The fact that this deference is

Postmodal Metaphysics

Smith s Incoherence Argument for Moral Rationalism

David Enoch s Taking Morality Seriously (Oxford University Press 2011) is the latest in

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

NON-COGNITIVISM AND THE PROBLEM OF MORAL-BASED EPISTEMIC REASONS: A SYMPATHETIC REPLY TO CIAN DORR

The Supervenience Challenge to Non-Naturalism

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

REASONS-RESPONSIVENESS AND TIME TRAVEL

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

CONCEPT FORMATION IN ETHICAL THEORIES: DEALING WITH POLAR PREDICATES

David Copp, ed., The Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory, Oxford: Oxford University

Contents. Detailed Chapter Contents Preface to the First Edition (2003) Preface to the Second Edition (2013) xiii

THE CONDITIONS OF MORAL REALISM

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Beyond Objectivism and Subjectivism. Derek Parfit s two volume work On What Matters is, as many philosophers

Non-Realist Cognitivism, Truth and Objectivity

Reply to Robert Koons

The Nature and Explanatory Ambitions of Metaethics. By Tristram McPherson (Ohio State University) and David Plunkett (Dartmouth College)

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

Bart Streumer, Unbelievable Errors, Oxford: Oxford University Press, ISBN

Divine command theory

BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth).

Introduction. The Nature and Explanatory Ambitions of Metaethics

Grounding and Analyticity. David Chalmers

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy.

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

Is God Good By Definition?

ON PROMOTING THE DEAD CERTAIN: A REPLY TO BEHRENDS, DIPAOLO AND SHARADIN

Reactions & Debate. Non-Convergent Truth

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

Ethics (ETHC) JHU-CTY Course Syllabus

Judith Jarvis Thomson s Normativity

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Intro to Ground. 1. The idea of ground. 2. Relata. are facts): F 1. More-or-less equivalent phrases (where F 1. and F 2. depends upon F 2 F 2

SWINBURNE ON THE EUTHYPHRO DILEMMA. CAN SUPERVENIENCE SAVE HIM?

IN DEFENSE OF THE PRIMACY OF THE VIRTUES

* Thanks to Mark Murphy for his very helpful comments on an earlier version of this chapter.

Intuition, Self-evidence, and understanding 1. Philip Stratton-Lake

Why there is no such thing as a motivating reason

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

Transcription:

DISCUSSION NOTE BY DAAN EVERS AND BART STREUMER JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE MARCH 2016 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT DAAN EVERS AND BART STREUMER 2016

Are the Moral Fixed Points Conceptual Truths? T ERENCE CUNEO AND RUSS SHAFER-LANDAU have recently proposed a new version of moral nonnaturalism, according to which there are nonnatural moral concepts and truths but no nonnatural moral facts. 1 This view entails that moral error theorists are conceptually deficient. We explain why moral error theorists are not conceptually deficient. We then argue that this explanation reveals what is wrong with Cuneo and Shafer-Landau s view. 1. Cuneo and Shafer-Landau s New Version of Moral Nonnaturalism Consider the following propositions: (1) It is wrong to engage in the recreational slaughter of a fellow person. 2 (2) It is morally admirable to express gratitude to a benefactor whose gift resulted from substantial sacrifice undertaken from exclusively altruistic motives. (3) There is some moral reason to offer aid to those in distress, if such aid is very easily given and comes at very little expense. According to Cuneo and Shafer-Landau, propositions like (1), (2) and (3) have framework status, fixing the boundaries as to what counts as a type of subject matter : a normative system that fails to incorporate these propositions is not a moral system, but is instead a normative system of some other kind. 3 They therefore take propositions like (1), (2) and (3) to be conceptual truths, which they call the moral fixed points. 4 Cuneo and Shafer-Landau think that conceptual truths are made true by the essences of their constituent concepts. If so, the proposition that (4) Unmarried men are bachelors is made true by the essences of the concepts UNMARRIED MAN and BACHELOR: the essences of these concepts are such that anything that satisfies the concept UNMARRIED MAN thereby satisfies the concept 1 Cuneo and Shafer-Landau (2014). Cuneo and Shafer-Landau argue that nonnaturalists can also say that there are nonnatural moral facts, but they take this to be an optional addition to their version of nonnaturalism. We will ignore this optional addition, since it does not affect our arguments. 2 Like Cuneo and Shafer-Landau, we use the term wrong to mean pro tanto wrong. 3 Cuneo and Shafer-Landau (2014: 407). 4 They also give three other reasons for taking the moral fixed points to be conceptual truths: that if these propositions are true, they are necessarily true; that if they are knowable, they are knowable a priori; and that denying them tends to evoke bewilderment (2014: 407-8). We return to this in n. 9.

BACHELOR. Similarly, Cuneo and Shafer-Landau think, the proposition that (1) It is wrong to engage in the recreational slaughter of a fellow person is made true by the essences of the concepts RECREATIONAL SLAUGHTER OF A FELLOW PERSON and WRONG: the essences of these concepts are such that anything that satisfies the concept RECREATIONAL SLAUGHTER OF A FELLOW PERSON thereby satisfies the concept WRONG. Cuneo and Shafer-Landau take moral concepts like WRONG to be nonnatural concepts, in the sense that these concepts are not equivalent to any natural concept. They therefore think that nonnaturalists need not say that propositions like (1), (2) and (3) are made true by nonnatural facts, but can instead say that such propositions are made true, in part, by nonnatural concepts. (1), (2) and (3) are general moral propositions. What about particular moral propositions? Suppose that Fred is engaging in the recreational slaughter of a fellow person. In that case, Cuneo and Shafer-Landau think, the true proposition that (1) It is wrong to engage in the recreational slaughter of a fellow person and the true proposition that (5) Fred is engaging in the recreational slaughter of a fellow person together make it true that (6) Fred s action is wrong. Since (1) and (5) together make (6) true, Cuneo and Shafer-Landau think that (6) is made true by the essences of (1) s constituent concepts, one of which is a nonnatural concept, together with the natural fact that makes (5) true. They therefore think that nonnaturalists need not say that particular moral propositions like (6) are made true by nonnatural facts either. Almost all philosophers agree that moral concepts like WRONG are nonnatural concepts, in the sense that these concepts are not equivalent to any natural concept. 5 Standard nonnaturalism is controversial not because it says that there are nonnatural moral concepts in this sense, but because it says that there are nonnatural moral facts. Since Cuneo and Shafer-Landau s version of nonnaturalism avoids this controversial commitment, it may seem more attractive than standard nonnaturalism. 5 Though, as Cuneo and Shafer-Landau note, Jackson (1998) denies this. So does Finlay (2014). 2

2. Why the Moral Fixed Points Are Not Conceptual Truths Cuneo and Shafer-Landau s view avoids a commitment to nonnatural facts by taking on a different controversial commitment instead namely, by saying that (1), (2), (3) and the other moral fixed points are conceptual truths. According to Cuneo and Shafer-Landau, anyone who denies these propositions is conceptually deficient : such a person either lacks moral concepts or fails to see that the essences of these concepts make propositions like (1), (2) and (3) true. 6 Since moral error theorists deny that anything is wrong, morally admirable or a moral reason, they deny that (1), (2) and (3) are true. 7 Cuneo and Shafer-Landau s view therefore entails that moral error theorists are conceptually deficient. 8 Are Cuneo and Shafer-Landau right that (1), (2), (3) and the other moral fixed points are conceptual truths? Consider a different concept: the concept GOD. Suppose that a Christian thinks that (7) Benevolence is rewarded by God. This Christian may think that (7) has what Cuneo and Shafer-Landau call framework status : he or she may think that a faith that fails to incorporate (7) is not a form of Christianity, but is instead a faith of some other kind. Just as Cuneo and Shafer-Landau take (1), (2) and (3) s framework status to show that (1), (2) and (3) are conceptual truths, this Christian may take (7) s framework status to show that (7) is a conceptual truth. And if this Christian endorses Cuneo and Shafer-Landau s view that conceptual truths are made true by the essences of their constituent concepts, he or she will think that (7) is made true by the essences of the concepts BENEVOLENCE and REWARDED BY GOD: he or she will think that the essence of these concepts is such that anything that satisfies the concept BENEVOLENCE thereby satisfies the concept REWARDED BY GOD. But, of course, (7) is not a conceptual truth. For it is not a conceptual truth that God exists, and if God does not exist, something that satisfies the concept BENEVOLENCE does not thereby satisfy the concept REWARDED BY GOD. The essences of these concepts therefore do not 6 This person may fail to see this either because he or she has what Cuneo and Shafer- Landau call an inadequate or confused grasp of these concepts, of because he or she fails to appreciate or acknowledge the manifest implications of these concepts (2014: 413). 7 For defenses of a moral error theory, see Mackie (1977), Joyce (2001), Streumer (2013) and Olson (2014). 8 As Ingram (2015) argues, this implication by itself throws doubt on Cuneo and Shafer- Landau s view. One of us has defended an error theory about all normative judgements and has argued that we cannot believe this error theory, which means that he himself does not believe this theory either (Streumer 2013). But since this error theory implies that (1), (2) and (3) are false, Cuneo and Shafer-Landau will presumably say that this theory is conceptually false, and that its defender is therefore conceptually deficient. 3

make (7) conceptually true, but at most make it conceptually true that (7*) If anything is rewarded by God, benevolence is rewarded by God. Similar claims apply to (1), (2) and (3). It is not a conceptual truth that wrongness is instantiated, and if wrongness is not instantiated, something that satisfies the concept RECREATIONAL SLAUGHTER OF A FELLOW PERSON does not thereby satisfy the concept WRONG. The essences of these concepts therefore do not make (1) conceptually true, but at most make it conceptually true that (1*) If anything is wrong, it is wrong to engage in the recreational slaughter of a fellow person. Similarly, the essences of (2) and (3) s constituent concepts do not make (2) and (3) conceptually true, but at most make it conceptually true that and that (2*) If anything is morally admirable, it is morally admirable to express gratitude to a benefactor whose gift resulted from substantial sacrifice undertaken from exclusively altruistic motives, (3*) If anything is a moral reason, there is some moral reason to offer aid to those in distress that is very easily given and comes at very little expense. Cuneo and Shafer-Landau may be right that (1), (2) and (3) have framework status : they may be right that a normative system that fails to incorporate (1), (2) and (3) is not a moral system. But this only shows that it is conceptually true that if anything satisfies the constituent moral concepts of (1), (2) and (3), then (1) (2) and (3) are true. In other words, it only shows that (1*), (2*) and (3*) are conceptually true. Since (1*), (2*) and (3*) do not say or entail that anything is in fact wrong, morally admirable or a moral reason, moral error theorists can accept (1*), (2*) and (3*). 9 If (1*), (2*) and (3*) are conceptual truths, it therefore does not follow that moral error theorists are conceptually deficient. 10 9 Moreover, moral error theorists can also agree with Cuneo and Shafer-Landau that if (1), (2) and (3) are true, they are necessarily true (while denying that (1), (2) and (3) are in fact true); they can agree that if (1), (2) and (3) are knowable, they are knowable a priori (while denying that (1), (2) and (3) are in fact knowable); and they can agree that denying (1), (2) and (3) tends to evoke bewilderment (while saying that such denials tend to evoke bewilderment not because (1), (2) and (3) are conceptual truths, but because a moral error theory is, as Olson (2014: 143), puts it, emotionally difficult to accept ). 10 Cuneo and Shafer-Landau also say that when moral error theorists reject highly evident first-order moral propositions such as that it is wrong to engage in recreational slaughter of a fellow person by appealing to highly controversial metaethical claims such as [the claim that] there are no categorical reasons, they are employing a prob- 4

Cuneo and Shafer-Landau could reply that if (1) has to be revised to (1*) to turn it into a conceptual truth, it is hard to see why the proposition that (4) Unmarried men are bachelors does not similarly have to be revised to (4*) If anything is a bachelor, unmarried men are bachelors to turn it into a conceptual truth. But (4) clearly does not have to be revised to (4*) to turn it into a conceptual truth. So why, Cuneo and Shafer- Landau could ask, should we think that (1) has to be revised to (1*) to turn it into a conceptual truth? The answer is that since the concept BACHELOR is identical to the concept UNMARRIED MAN, the satisfaction of the concept BACHELOR does not require more of the world than the satisfaction of the concept UNMARRIED MAN does. That is why (4) does not have to be revised to (4*) to turn it into a conceptual truth. By contrast, the satisfaction of the concept REWARDED BY GOD requires something of the world that the satisfaction of the concept BENEVOLENCE does not namely, the existence of God. That is why (7) has to be revised to (7*) to turn it into a conceptual truth. Similarly, the satisfaction of the concept WRONG also requires something of the world that the satisfaction of the concept RECREATIONAL SLAUGHTER OF A FELLOW PERSON does not namely, the instantiation of wrongness. That is why (1) also has to be revised to (1*) to turn it into a conceptual truth. Cuneo and Shafer-Landau could reply that, whereas the world has to be a certain way for God to exist, the world does not have to be a certain way for wrongness to be instantiated, at least not over and above containing recreational slaughter or instantiations of other natural properties that make actions satisfy the concept WRONG. If they reject our parallel between (7) and (1) in this way, they can agree that (7) has to be revised to (7*) to turn it into a conceptual truth, but deny that (1) similarly has to be revised to (1*) to turn it into a conceptual truth. But if Cuneo and Shafer-Landau say this, that will make their view much less attractive to their fellow nonnaturalists. For consider an antimoralist who lacks the concept WRONG and instead has the concept WRONG anti. Imagine that this concept plays the same role in this antimoralist s thought and action as the concept WRONG does in ours: the judgment that an action is wrong anti tends to motivate the anti-moralist to avoid this action, the anti-moralist tends to blame people for disregarding wrongness anti and so on. This anti-moralist may take it to be a conceptual lematic methodology (2014: 438). For a response to this charge, see Ingram (2015). 5

truth that (9) It is wrong anti to stop people from engaging in the recreational slaughter of a fellow person. Of course, we want to say that the concept that should guide people s behavior is WRONG rather than WRONG anti. But the anti-moralist can similarly say that the concept that should anti guide people s behavior is WRONG anti rather than WRONG. We may want to accuse the anti-moralist of being irrational. But the anti-moralist can similarly accuse us of being irrational anti and so on for any other normative concept. 11 Standard nonnaturalists think that something breaks this deadlock: they think that concepts like WRONG, SHOULD and IRRATIONAL ascribe properties that are really instantiated, whereas concepts like WRONG anti, SHOULD anti and IRRATIONAL anti ascribe properties that are not really instantiated. 12 They can admit that it is a conceptual truth that (9*) If anything is wrong anti, it is wrong anti to stop people from engaging in the recreational slaughter of a fellow person. But since they think that nothing is wrong anti, they deny that (9) is true. By contrast, if Cuneo and Shafer-Landau say that the world does not have to be a certain way for wrongness to be instantiated over and above containing instantiations of natural properties that make actions satisfy the concept WRONG, it is hard to see how they can avoid admitting that (9) is a conceptual truth. For if all that is required for the instantiation of wrongness is the existence of the concept WRONG and the instantiation of natural properties that make actions satisfy this concept, all that is required for the instantiation of wrongness anti similarly seems to be the existence of the concept WRONG anti and the instantiation of natural properties that make actions satisfy that concept. If Cuneo and Shafer-Landau say this, therefore, their view no longer seems to be a form of realism. That will undermine its attractiveness to their fellow nonnaturalists. 13 11 And also for truth if we accept a deflationary account of the truth of normative propositions. 12 Of course, that standard nonnaturalists think this does not mean that it is true. Error theorists think it is false: they think that concepts like WRONG, SHOULD and IRRATIONAL also ascribe properties that are not instantiated. 13 This point is similar to the objections from shmeasons and counter-reasons that McPherson (2011) and Enoch (2011) make to quietism. That is no coincidence: if Cuneo and Shafer-Landau deny that the world has to be a certain way for wrongness to exist, their view comes close to being a version of quietism. 6

3. Why It Matters Whether the Moral Fixed Points Are Conceptual Truths Cuneo and Shafer-Landau may now agree that (1), (2) and (3) are not conceptual truths and that moral error theorists are therefore not conceptually deficient. But they may say that this does not matter, since they did not aim to refute the moral error theory but merely to convert other realists to their new version of nonnaturalism. But if (1), (2) and (3) are not conceptual truths, this does undermine Cuneo and Shafer-Landau s view. For if it is not a conceptual truth that (1) It is wrong to engage in the recreational slaughter of a fellow person then nonnaturalists cannot say that (1) is made true by the essences of the concepts RECREATIONAL SLAUGHTER OF A FELLOW PERSON and WRONG: they cannot say that the essences of these concepts are such that anything that satisfies the concept RECREATIONAL SLAUGHTER OF A FELLOW PERSON thereby satisfies the concept WRONG. Instead, unless more is said, they will have to say that claims like (1), (2) and (3) are made true by nonnatural moral facts. In other words, they will have to revert to standard nonnaturalism about general moral propositions. And suppose again that Fred is engaging in the recreational slaughter of a fellow person. The true proposition that (1*) If anything is wrong, it is wrong to engage in the recreational slaughter of a fellow person and the true proposition that (5) Fred s action is the recreational slaughter of a fellow person do not together make it true that (6) Fred s action is wrong. This means that if (1) is not a conceptual truth, nonnaturalists cannot say that a particular moral proposition like (6) is made true by the essences of (1) s constituent concepts together with the natural fact that makes (5) true. Instead, unless more is said, they will have to say that (6) is, at least in part, made true by a nonnatural fact: either by a particular nonnatural fact or by a natural fact together with the more general nonnatural fact that makes (1) true. In other words, they will have to revert to standard nonnaturalism about particular moral propositions as well. We therefore conclude that Cuneo and Shafer-Landau s defense of their new version of nonnaturalism fails. Since the moral fixed points are 7

not conceptual truths, moral nonnaturalists cannot avoid being committed to the existence of nonnatural facts in the way Cuneo and Shafer- Landau propose. 14 Daan Evers University of Groningen Faculty of Philosophy h.w.a.evers@rug.nl Bart Streumer University of Groningen Faculty of Philosophy b.streumer@rug.nl 14 We are grateful to Terence Cuneo, Niels van Miltenburg and several anonymous referees for helpful comments. 8

References Cuneo, T. and Shafer-Landau, R. (2014) The Moral Fixed Points: New Directions for Moral Nonnaturalism, Philosophical Studies 171: 399-443. Enoch, D. (2011) Taking Morality Seriously, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Finlay, S. (2014) Confusion of Tongues, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Ingram, S. (2015) The Moral Fixed Points: Reply to Cuneo and Shafer-Landau, Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy. Jackson, F. (1998) From Metaphysics to Ethics, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Joyce, R. (2001) The Myth of Morality, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Mackie, J. L. (1977) Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong, Harmondsworth: Penguin. McPherson, T. (2011) Against Quietist Normative Realism, Philosophical Studies 154: 223-40. Olson, J. (2014) Moral Error Theory, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Streumer, B. (2013) Can We Believe the Error Theory? Journal of Philosophy 110: 194-212. 9