Categorical Imperative by. Kant

Similar documents
Problems of Philosophy

Lecture 12 Deontology. Onora O Neill A Simplified Account of Kant s Ethics

Benjamin Visscher Hole IV Phil 100, Intro to Philosophy

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

Is Morality Rational?

Kantian Deontology - Part Two

(naturalistic fallacy)

Kant's Moral Philosophy

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

[Forthcoming in The International Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Hugh LaFollette. (Oxford: Blackwell), 2012] Imperatives, Categorical and Hypothetical

CMSI Handout 3 Courtesy of Marcello Antosh

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

Deontology: Duty-Based Ethics IMMANUEL KANT

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law

Kant, Deontology, & Respect for Persons

DEONTOLOGICAL ETHICS

Suppose... Kant. The Good Will. Kant Three Propositions

Kant The Grounding of the Metaphysics of Morals (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes. Section IV: What is it worth? Reading IV.2.

Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa

Duty and Categorical Rules. Immanuel Kant Introduction to Ethics, PHIL 118 Professor Douglas Olena

24.02 Moral Problems and the Good Life

Kantianism: Objections and Replies Keith Burgess-Jackson 12 March 2017

Hello again. Today we re gonna continue our discussions of Kant s ethics.

Lecture 6 Kantianism. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

Ethical Theories. A (Very) Brief Introduction

Kant and his Successors

Can Christianity be Reduced to Morality? Ted Di Maria, Philosophy, Gonzaga University Gonzaga Socratic Club, April 18, 2008

Kant. Deontological Ethics

Deontological Ethics. Kant. Rules for Kant. Right Action

7/31/2017. Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God

Peter Bornedal, General Lecture, 203. Copyright (C) by P. Bornedal

In-Class Kant Review Dialogue 1

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

Chapter 2 Determining Moral Behavior

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

Download: Two clips from Star Trek. The needs of the many and The needs of the one found in Course Content Kant folder.

Humanities 4: Lectures Kant s Ethics

An Epistemological Assessment of Moral Worth in Kant s Moral Theory. Immanuel Kant s moral theory outlined in The Grounding for the Metaphysics of

Deontological Ethics

Honors Ethics Oral Presentations: Instructions

-- did you get a message welcoming you to the cours reflector? If not, please correct what s needed.

KANTIAN ETHICS: A CRITIQUE

Duty Based Ethics. Ethics unit 3

Chapter 2 Reasoning about Ethics

Short Answers: Answer the following questions in one paragraph (each is worth 5 points).

38 Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals. [Ak 4:422] [Ak4:421]

A Categorical Imperative. An Introduction to Deontological Ethics

Mill s Utilitarian Theory

Ethics Prof. Vineet Sahu Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology-Kanpur

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Deontology: Duty-Based Ethics IMMANUEL KANT

The fact that some action, A, is part of a valuable and eligible pattern of action, P, is a reason to perform A. 1

In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of

Psychological Aspects of Social Issues

CHAPTER 2 Test Bank MULTIPLE CHOICE

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

FREEDOM AND THE SOURCE OF VALUE: KORSGAARD AND WOOD ON KANT S FORMULA OF HUMANITY CHRISTOPHER ARROYO

Deontology. Marianne Talbot University of Oxford Department for Continuing Education

Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 110W Fall 2013 Russell Marcus

A primer of major ethical theories

Introduction to Ethics

A (Very) Brief Introduction to Epistemology Lecture 2. Palash Sarkar

INTENTIONALITY, NORMATIVITY AND COMMUNALITY IN KANT S REALM OF ENDS

Instrumental reasoning* John Broome

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

Philosophy of Ethics Philosophy of Aesthetics. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

CHAPTER THREE Philosophical Argument

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Development of Soul Through Contemplation and Action Seen from the Viewpoint of lslamic Philosophers and Gnostics

Sidgwick on Practical Reason

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

PROFESSIONAL ETHICS IN SCIENCE AND ENGINEERING

IMMANUEL KANT Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals [Edited and reduced by J. Bulger, Ph.D.]

BOOK REVIEW: CONTEMPORARY MORAL PROBLEMS

Q2) The test of an ethical argument lies in the fact that others need to be able to follow it and come to the same result.

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

To link to this article:

Hume s emotivism. Michael Lacewing

Words and their Meaning

PHILOSOPHY IM 25 SYLLABUS IM SYLLABUS (2019)

DEONTOLOGY AND MORAL RESPONSIBILITY

Happiness and Personal Growth: Dial.

The Pleasure Imperative

FACULTY OF ARTS B.A. Part II Examination,

KANT S EXAMPLES. Robert Paul Wolff. Introduction, David Stewart

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations

Deontology. Immanuel Kant ( ) Founder of Deontology

Philosophy 110W: Introduction to Philosophy Spring 2011 Class 26 - April 29 Kantian Ethics. Hamilton College Russell Marcus

Chapter Summaries: A Christian View of Men and Things by Clark, Chapter 1

Absolute Totality, Causality, and Quantum: The Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason. Kazuhiko Yamamoto, Kyushu University, Japan

Important dates. PSY 3360 / CGS 3325 Historical Perspectives on Psychology Minds and Machines since David Hume ( )

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Dr. Desh Raj Sirswal, Assistant Professor (Philosophy), P.G.Govt. College for Girls, Sector-11, Chandigarh

Chapter Summaries: Introduction to Christian Philosophy by Clark, Chapter 1

Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 110W Spring 2011 Russell Marcus

Ethical non-naturalism

Transcription:

Categorical Imperative by Dr. Desh Raj Sirswal Assistant Professor (Philosophy), P.G.Govt. College for Girls, Sector-11, Chandigarh http://drsirswal.webs.com Kant

Immanuel Kant

Immanuel Kant (1724 1804) is the central figure in modern philosophy. He synthesized early modern rationalism and empiricism, set the terms for much of nineteenth and twentieth century philosophy, and continues to exercise a significant influence today in metaphysics, epistemology, ethics, political philosophy, aesthetics, and other fields. The fundamental idea of Kant's critical philosophy especially in his three Critiques: the Critique of Pure Reason (1781, 1787), the Critique of Practical Reason (1788), and the Critique of the Power of Judgment (1790) is human autonomy. He argues that the human understanding is the source of the general laws of nature that structure all our experience; and that human reason gives itself the moral law, which is o ur basis for belief in God, freedom, and immortality. Therefore, scientific knowledge, morality, and religious belief are mutually consistent and secure because they all rest on the same foundation of human autonomy, which is also the final end of nature according to the teleological worldview of reflecting judgment that Kant introduces to unify the theoretical and practical parts of his philosophical system. The Person

Introduction The categorical imperative is the central philosophical concept in the moral philosophy of Immanuel Kant. Introduced in Kant's Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals, it may be defined as a way of evaluating motivations for action. According to Kant, human beings occupy a special place in creation, and morality can be summed up in one ultimate commandment of reason, or imperative, from which all duties and obligations derive. He defined an imperative as any proposition that declares a certain action (or inaction) to be necessary.

Categorical Imperative The philosophical concept of a categorical imperative is central to the moral philosophy of Immanuel Kant.. In his philosophy, it denotes an absolute, unconditional requirement that allows no exceptions, and is both required and justified as an end in itself, not as a means to some other end; the opposite of a hypothetical imperative. Most famously, he holds that all categorical imperatives can be derived from a single one, which is known as "the" Categorical Imperative; it is upon this Imperative that the article will focus.

In his Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals, Kant formulates the Categorical Imperative in three different ways: The first (Universal Law formulation): "Act only on that maxim through which you can at the same time will that it should become a universal law." The second (Humanity or End in Itself formulation): "Act in such a way that you always treat humanity, whether in your own person or in the person of any other, never simply as a means, but always at the same time as an end." The third (Kingdom of Ends formulation) combines the two: "All maxims as proceeding from our own [hypothetical] making of law ought to harmonise with a possible kingdom of ends. Formulations

Immorality In Kant's view immorality occurs when the categorical imperative is not followed: when a person attempts to set a different standard for themselves then for the rest of humanity. In the Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals, once Kant has derived his categorical imperative he applies it to a number of examples. The second example and probably the most analysed is that of an unfaithful promise. Kant applies his imperative to a person who is short of money who intends to ask for a loan, promising to repay it, but with no intention of doing so. When Kant applies the categorical imperative to this situation he discovers that it leads to a contradiction, for if breaking promises were to become universal then no person would ever agree to a promise and promises would disappear. Kant connects rationality with morality, and sees contradictory behaviour as immoral. Some critics have argued that Kant never asserts the connection between rationality and morality, but most dismiss this and point out that Kant clearly explains how morality must be based upon reason and not upon desires.

Especially important to Kant were the works of Aristotle, which stand in direct oppostion to much of what Kant argues. Before Kant the most important moral theories were based upon Aristotle's Nichomachean which assert that whatever leads to greater eudaimonia, or happiness, is what is moral. Rejection of Aristotle Kant, however, believes that any action taken for a deliberate end, whether it be happiness or some other goal, is morally neutral. Kant rests his rejection of the Aristotelian position on a number of points. He points out that all the imperatives are hypthetical, they are performed merely to attain a certain end. More importantly to Kant, this end is one dictated by desires, implying that the human will is no more than a facilitator of predetermined ends, limiting human freedom.

Criticising Aristotle Kant also challenges the traditional viewpoint using his definition of duty as something that is impossible to learn from observation, and thus can only be deduced rationally. While it is possible to learn imperatives of skill and prudence that are morally neutral through observation, the categorical imperative that allows one to determine what actually is moral is known a priori and can only be properly determined through reason. Any imperative that is hypothetical is not based on reason. You perform a hypothetical imperative only if you want or desire something; they are performed for a certain hoped for end. They are based on desire and hope and not upon the reason upon which ethics should be founded. One important difference between Aristotle and Kant is that in Aristotle's case only the educated and the leisurely class that can indulge in self-examination can be moral. Kant's philosophy is far more egalitarian. Morality cannot be taught or learnt, it must arise spontaneously from within

Equivalence of the formulas? One problem is how Kant can possibly regard the first two formulas as equivalent. The answer may lie in the fundamental motivation for the Categorical Imperative - it is essentially based on a conception of fairness and universalizability. I must realise that there must be a consistent law for everyone - there cannot be one rule for me and another for everyone else. For example, stealing would fail the test, since, to steal, you must deny the existence of property rights. But in so doing, you would be denying ownership of your own property, and the whole act of stealing would become (in Kant's eyes) logically self-defeating. This desire for consistency drives the first formulation - could I consistently will that stealing became a universal law? Of course not. The same goes for killing, lying, and so on - I cannot will that these be universally practiced, since if they were it would be harmful to me. Any such actions I carry out are thus inconsistent with reason. There are also more subtle effects: for example, I cannot decide never to help others out, as I must recognise that I am likely to need help from others at some point. The second formulation can be seen as following from the first - if we are tempted to use other people merely as a means, we must realise that a universal law that allowed this would harm us. So the second formulation can be seen as just an example of a universal law willed under the first formulation. More than this, however, the second formulation is again based on a concept of fairness - although I recognise the importance of myself as an end (that is, a person with hopes, desires, and so on), I must realise that what is special about me as a rational being also makes everyone else special, and they too must be seen as ends-in-themselves. So I must regard all persons as ends-in-themselves, rather than just as means to my ends, which are, after all, no more important than anyone else's. Thus, the first two formulations (and therefore the third, which combines the two) can arguably be seen as closely tied together

Conclusion Here we studied the important conceptions of Kant s ethics. Kantian ethics is also known as Categorical Ethics. References: B.A.IInd Year(Notes), USOL, P.U.Chandigarh, 2012-13 J.N.Sinha, A Manual of Ethics. Wikipedia (the free encyclopedia) S.N.Gupta, Ethics.