Word, World, and a Postmodern Theology of Law

Similar documents
Process Thought and Bridge Building: A Response to Stephen K. White. Kevin Schilbrack

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Phil 2303 Intro to Worldviews Philosophy Department Dallas Baptist University Dr. David Naugle

Postmodernism. Issue Christianity Post-Modernism. Theology Trinitarian Atheism. Philosophy Supernaturalism Anti-Realism

Evidence and Transcendence

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information

The Human Science Debate: Positivist, Anti-Positivist, and Postpositivist Inquiry. By Rebecca Joy Norlander. November 20, 2007

Some Notes Toward a Genealogy of Existential Philosophy Robert Burch

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

RUNNING HEAD: Philosophy and Theology 1. Christine Orsini RELS 111 Professor Fletcher March 21, 2012 Short Writing Assignment 2

PART FOUR: CATHOLIC HERMENEUTICS

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

Post Pluralism Through the Lens of Post Modernity By Aimee Upjohn Light

ARE YOU READY? Lecture 2 Loss of Truth

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Friederike Rass. know is a highly talented physicist who regularly attends claustral retreats. These

A Multitude of Selves: Contrasting the Cartesian and Nietzschean views of selfhood

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

BENJAMIN R. BARBER. Radical Excess & Post-Modernism Presentation By Benedetta Barnabo Cachola

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Luce Irigaray. To Be Born. Genesis of a New Human Being

Ideas Have Consequences

The CopernicanRevolution

A Review of Norm Geisler's Prolegomena

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Rationalist-Irrationalist Dialectic in Buddhism:

EVIL, SIN, FALSITY AND THE DYNAMICS OF FAITH. Masao Abe

Philosophy of Ethics Philosophy of Aesthetics. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge

Freedom and servitude: the master and slave dialectic in Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit

DALLAS BAPTIST UNIVERSITY THE ILLOGIC OF FAITH: FEAR AND TREMBLING IN LIGHT OF MODERNISM SUBMITTED TO THE GENTLE READER FOR SPRING CONFERENCE

Habermas and Critical Thinking

EUTHYPHRO, GOD S NATURE, AND THE QUESTION OF DIVINE ATTRIBUTES. An Analysis of the Very Complicated Doctrine of Divine Simplicity.

Comments on Scott Soames, Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, volume I

THEOLOGY IN THE FLESH

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

Essays in Systematic Theology 45: The Structure of Systematic Theology 1

The British Empiricism

Kant and his Successors

CHAPTER THREE ON SEEING GOD THROUGH HIS IMAGE IMPRINTED IN OUR NATURAL POWERS

1/5. The Critique of Theology

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

The Ethics of Self Realization: A Radical Subjectivism, Bounded by Realism. An Honors Thesis (HONR 499) Kevin Mager. Thesis Advisor Jason Powell

Well-Being, Disability, and the Mere-Difference Thesis. Jennifer Hawkins Duke University

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations

Wisdom in Aristotle and Aquinas From Metaphysics to Mysticism Edmond Eh University of Saint Joseph, Macau

Building Systematic Theology

ON JESUS, DERRIDA, AND DAWKINS: REJOINDER TO JOSHUA HARRIS

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

MARK KAPLAN AND LAWRENCE SKLAR. Received 2 February, 1976) Surely an aim of science is the discovery of the truth. Truth may not be the

THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN SCIENCE, RELIGION AND ARISTOTELIAN THEOLOGY TODAY

ETHICS AND THE FUTURE OF HUMANKIND, REALITY OF THE HUMAN EXISTENCE

To link to this article:

True and Reasonable Faith Theistic Proofs

Sufficient Reason and Infinite Regress: Causal Consistency in Descartes and Spinoza. Ryan Steed

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp.

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

Reading Engineer s Concept of Justice in Islam: The Real Power of Hermeneutical Consciousness (A Gadamer s Philosophical Hermeneutics)

How Trustworthy is the Bible? (1) Written by Cornelis Pronk

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Final Paper. May 13, 2015

VERIFICATION AND METAPHYSICS

TEILHARD DE CHARDIN: TOWARD A DEVELOPMENTAL AND ORGANIC THEOLOGY

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins

Reading/Study Guide: Rorty and his Critics. Richard Rorty s Universality and Truth. I. The Political Context: Truth and Democratic Politics (1-4)

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Insider and Outsider Scholarship in Bahá í Studies

MDiv Expectations/Competencies ATS Standard

Andrea Westlund, in Selflessness and Responsibility for Self, argues

Presuppositional Apologetics

15 Does God have a Nature?

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

History of Education Society

Church Emerging. from the cracks. a church IN, but not OF the world. Johann-Albrecht Meylahn. About the author

THE PERSONAL UNITY OF GLORY AND POVERTY IN FREEDOM AS LOVE *

The Emerging Consciousness of a new Humanity

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2015

2. A Roman Catholic Commentary

Reclaiming the mystical interpretation of the Resurrection

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

Inquiry, Knowledge, and Truth: Pragmatic Conceptions. Pragmatism is a philosophical position characterized by its specific mode of inquiry, and

Revelations of Understanding: The Great Return of Essence-Me to Immanent I am

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system

John Haugeland. Dasein Disclosed: John Haugeland s Heidegger. Edited by Joseph Rouse. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2013.

Philosophical Review.

A Brief History of Thinking about Thinking Thomas Lombardo

Can Christianity be Reduced to Morality? Ted Di Maria, Philosophy, Gonzaga University Gonzaga Socratic Club, April 18, 2008

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Transcription:

Word & World Volume XXI, Number 3 Summer 2001 Word, World, and a Postmodern Theology of Law PAUL J. LOKKEN OW SHALL WE THINK OF GOD S LAW IN POSTMODERNITY? HOW DOES GOD S law come to be in a postmodern world, how does it manifest itself, what is its character, and how do we come to know it? Here we shall develop the claim that Word and world come together to issue in a law that is uniquely postmodern in nature and discernment. First, however, we must examine how these questions arise at all by understanding the unique difficulty postmodernism poses for law in general. I. THE POSTMODERN ETHOS Modernity, with its classic hallmarks of an autonomous thinking subject, objective reason, an independent external reality, and foundational and universal knowledge, has been under attack for a long time. One can exhaustively trace this development going back at least as far as Nietzsche. Today, however, as we enter the new millennium, postmodernism stands for the general intuition that life has somehow fundamentally changed as compared with the modern era. This is evident in most every facet of our existence but is perhaps most obvious in our public art, popular culture, and electronic mass media, which constantly expose us to an explosion of volatile, incompatible, and bizarre images that blur truth and fiction, reality and fantasy. These images inevitably force us to seek and invent meaning beyond the parameters of modern rationality by choosing from an indeterminate In a postmodern world, it is not we who discover the truth of the law, but we are instead grasped by it, just as we are grasped by the truth of the gospel in proclamation. Copyright 2001 by Word & World, Luther Seminary, Saint Paul, Minnesota. All rights reserved. 289

Lokken range of possible interpretative responses. Thus, while most postmodern thinkers would concede that the modern worldview ostensibly continues to shape our thinking at all levels, from the mundane to the sophisticated (perhaps especially there), few moderns would disagree that there has been a gradual paradigm shift toward a new way of understanding such concepts as self, reason, universality, language, knowledge, and truth that is today recognized as distinctly postmodern in nature. What are some of the primary tenets of this new postmodern ethos? First, to modernity s concept of the autonomous self, postmodernity opposes a self that is decentered and situated, in that self and world are truly mutually constitutive. Second, to modernity s strong conception of reason, postmodernity opposes a reason that is contingent, fallible, and local, in that its rules and criteria for what qualifies as rational at any given time are products of the historical, cultural, and linguistic conventions then in place. Third, to modernity s notion of reality as governed by universal structures, discerned methodologically and applied deductively, postmodernity opposes the empirical, the provisional, the practical, the pragmatic, and the unmasking of all totalizing perspectives as merely conventional and selfreferential. Fourth, to modernity s common sense view of language as a neutral medium that reflects the structure of the mind by which it is able to represent accurately what it objectively perceives, postmodernity opposes language as the medium in which self and world are mutually constituted. Finally, to modernity s conception of knowledge and truth as that which is immediately available to an autonomous self with respect to an independent external reality transparent to perception through direct intuition and the impartial exercise of reason, postmodernity opposes language games, lifeworlds, practices, and conventions, again emphasizing the inherently local (rather than universal) character of all claims of truth and knowledge. II. THE NECESSITY FOR A POSTMODERN CONCEPTION OF GOD S LAW If we do, indeed, live in a postmodern age of such seeming instability and fragmentation, how can it be said that we come to know God s will for us as law? If we give ourselves over to the most radical forms of philosophical postmodernism, it is hard to be optimistic that we can come to such knowledge. For the French deconstuctionist Jacques Derrida, for example, our present reality originates and subsists, not by means of any transcendental source (e.g., God), but through the imposition of systems of exclusion and repression. Accordingly, justice is itself the exposing and deconstructing of those systems and the equally repressive ones that inevitably replace them. Of course, from a theological point of view such nihilism is unacceptable. As Christians we assume in faith that God exists and is a source of law. Therefore, the question for us is how to discern God s will in whatever type of world we inhabit. However, before we retreat pell-mell from postmodernity back into modernity, let 290

Word, World, and a Postmodern Theology of Law us remember that the modern concept of law, though it certainly saw law as founded in the transcendent, nevertheless was also theologically troublesome. The modern concept of law succeeded a premodern view that saw God as the sole stable source of meaning and value. God s law, of course, could be known from Scripture. But the law to be found there was basically a reminder of the law that had already been inscribed by God in nature. That law, the natural law, could be known because of the metaphysical unity that was seen to exist between humans and nature, between mind and body. With modernity the premodern metaphysical unity between humanity and nature broke down. Thus, philosophically, at least, there came to be a split between subject and object, and correlatively in law between fact and value. The world could tell us what is, but it could not tell us what ought to be. Hence positivism came to reign in the modern view of the law. Theologically, God s law came to be viewed, particularly for Protestants, not necessarily as immanent in creation, but as directly revealed, for example, in Scripture. To be sure, there continued to be natural law theologians, particularly in Catholicism, but their work also took on a modern positivistic twist that saw creation as a book of rules from which the law can be read with some particularity (even though already with Augustine, and particularly with Thomas Aquinas, natural law came to be limited to the most general abstractions). In both cases law tended to be seen as consisting of universal, eternal, and unchanging principles from which a single correct answer to every legal dilemma could be methodologically deduced according to the modern scientific ethos. Today, however, this modern concept of law, while it meets our understandable desire for certainty in the law, seems contrary to our postmodern lived experience. How can even God s law be considered unaffected by time and context when the law as we have interpreted and applied it in the past sometimes no longer seems right and just under the changed circumstances of the present, and when Christians themselves have sometimes changed their minds about what the law is (for example, as they did with respect to slavery)? How can we be confident of modernity s right-answer thesis when often even after the most painstaking analysis we simply do not know what it is that God wants us to do and think, and when in many cases we see no single right answer, but several more or less correct possible answers which must be mediated in a setting of profound disagreement? If we cannot give ourselves wholly over to modernity, where shall we turn in our quest to understand the nature of God s law and how we come to know it? Some say that we should simply return to premodernity. This would offer us the opportunity to see God s law once again as immanent and discernable in and through creation, something largely denied to us by modernity. It is not likely, however, that we could ever return to a premodern view of the law. The premodern worldview is simply no longer our worldview. In any event, while modern rationalism may not be capable of yielding ultimate truth in law, we would not want to surrender its gains so long as its theoretical, methodological, and scientific viewpoint 291

Lokken is kept in proper perspective. Thus, since we can neither remain in modernity nor return to premodernity, can we somehow bravely move forward to find a theology of law that again will allow us to see God s will as somehow immanent and discernable in creation (without an unrealistic return to a premodern world view), that makes use of modern rationalism (without limiting truth to that yielded by theory and method), and that is distinctly postmodern (without surrendering to nihilism and relativism)? As we have already said, our specific claim is that Word and world come together to issue in a law that is uniquely postmodern in nature and discernment. In making this claim we shall take as our point of departure Hans-Georg Gadamer, whose hermeneutic philosophy represents the thoroughly postmodern, yet non-nihilistic, point of view for which we have been looking.* III. GOD S LAW IN THE WORLD AS DIVINE WORD How can it be said (contrary to modernity s fact-value split) that God s law is immanent in creation? Here we shall draw upon Augustine s reflections (via Gadamer) upon the verbum Dei. Reading the prologue to the Gospel of John, Augustine was perplexed how the Son could be seen as the Word without coming to the undesirable conclusion that the Son is merely an external and perceptible utterance of the Father, thus subordinating the Son to the Father in an anti-trinitarian way. Augustine approached this problem by making a distinction between an inner and an outer divine Word. He concluded that the outer Word (the Son) embodies the full self-knowledge of the inner Word (the Father), thus preserving the unity of the Father and the Son. As a result, God the Father is fully present in God s historical utterance of the Son. But the outer expressions of the inner Word do not consist solely of the historical Jesus Christ. Indeed the whole of creation itself is to be seen as having been spoken into being and continually sustained by means of the inner Word. In fact, Gadamer sees it as a natural extension of Augustine s view to say that the inner Word is fully realized and perfected only by means of the incarnation, by becoming flesh, by becoming world. Thus, Augustine has provided a way of thinking of God as being present in the world (by means of Word) as its truth in general (as God has intended it to be), and specifically as the truth of the law (as God wills for us to be and act). IV. GOD S LAW IN THE WORLD AS HUMAN WORD But how does the truth of the world and God s law with respect to it come to be expressed in our understanding? Gadamer answers that it does so through the medium of language. Thought belongs to language, and language belongs to the world in such a way that language is the place of disclosure where subject, object, thought, and world meet. Thus, language is capable of bearing and reflecting being *In discussing Gadamer s hermeneutic philosophy and its theological implications we have relied principally upon Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, 2d rev. ed., trans. Joel C. Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall (New York: Continuum, 1989). 292

Word, World, and a Postmodern Theology of Law and its truth truthfully. Gadamer, citing Thomas Aquinas and Nicholas of Cusa, demonstrates this capacity by paralleling Augustine s distinction between inner and outer divine Word with a distinction between inner and outer human word. Outer word, held Thomas, is capable of bearing the truth of the inner word in the same way that a truthful conclusion is already present in the premises from the beginning. Nicholas of Cusa affirms Thomas s analysis by insisting that outer word is in no way a weakened manifestation of the inner word, its multiplicity being but a prismatic reflection of the inner word s original unity. This last insight by Nicholas of Cusa, however, signals a fundamental distinction between Word and word that had been previously drawn by Thomas. While God by means of Word creates the world in the unity of a single intuition, from the human point of view of word, the world unfolds in the multiplicity of temporality. Although this difference emphasizes the finitude of word, it need not wholly detract from word s truth-bearing capacity, since God s eternal unity can nevertheless be seen as constantly bearing upon external creation and its components as an assertion of their truth as they play themselves out in the finitude of temporality. This claim again is supported by Nicholas of Cusa, who held that the single Word of God is reflected in (or shines through) every created thing. Thus, there is a dialectical relationship between the one Word and the multiplicity of creation as we experience it. Gadamer sees as the perfect example of this duality the proclamation of the gospel. Here the unity of the divine Word comes to be expressed truthfully in the multiplicity of human words. The one Word comes to be proclaimed ever anew in the multiplicity of its proclamation. Hence, just as the unity of the divine Word asserts itself as the truth of the gospel in external worldly proclamation, so, too, it asserts itself as the true nature for us of all else, and in particular of God s law with respect to it, for there is nothing in the multiplicity of temporal being the truth of which does not have its origin in that unity. V. HOW GOD S LAW AS W(W)ORD IS MANIFESTED IN A POSTMODERN WORLD Thus, the Word shines through or asserts itself in word as the truth of external creation. And it does so, not only in the sphere of science (as the exaggerated claims of modernity seems to contend), but also in such non-methodological and non-theoretical human spheres as history, art, philosophy, religion, and law. But exactly how does this truth shine through as word? The non-nihilistic but yet postmodern answer, according to Gadamer, is that it asserts itself and we are grasped by it hermeneutically. What does Gadamer mean by this? For Gadamer, the world and its aspects, and specifically the truth of the law, emerge through a merging of horizons. One such horizon in legal analysis is the law as received in tradition (e.g., the United States Constitution or the Ten Commandments). The law so received as artifact is far from a self-evident object, as modernity contends, but in a postmodern way is open in that it constantly presents itself ever anew and productively in a multiplic- 293

Lokken ity of ways, lending itself to a fecundity of interpretations, all of them potentially truthful from the standpoint of the wholeness of some legitimate perspective. Thus, the truth of a law is never finished. Further, we as interpreters of the law, as a second horizon, are also never finished. As the law is constantly presenting itself under new aspects, we are constantly questioned anew and our expectations based upon past interpretation constantly disappointed. Thus, we are continually presenting or reconstituting ourselves anew through meaningful interpretation, by means of which we become co-creators of our own present and future experience. A third horizon is a context of application. Law (even such cherished axioms as love your neighbor as yourself ) as conceived in the absence of a situation of application is simply an empty generality. Consequently, the law is to be found in the facts. Literally, there is no law until it is revealed experientially in them. Each of these horizons is primordially historical. Accordingly, we can approach the law only as we are enabled from the standpoint of our past experiences and prejudices. So, also, the law itself can be known only as it has been previously interpreted. Even the context of application, although wholly contemporary, can present itself only as it has developed historically. Thus, these horizons form the perspective from which the law appears and is of interest to us, just as we cannot, for example, view the Mona Lisa except from the visual perspective da Vinci incorporated into the painting itself. Yet, though restrictive in this way, these historical givens (or prejudices) are not to be viewed negatively, since they are the only means by which further experiences and interpretations are enabled. In any event, since reality is constantly presenting itself under new aspects, all horizons as they are interactively brought into play are burst open and brought into a state of indeterminacy. Thus, for example, the horizon of the interpreting subject, like the prodigal son in the biblical parable, is in a constant progression of coming into being through a primordial process of alienation and return, a process in which other horizons, now seen as foreign and perhaps threatening, are integrated into a consciousness that is newly augmented and unified. In the same way, the horizons of law and the context of application are transformed just as they are about to be further placed in play in the context of future experiences, where they will be further transformed again. Gadamer claims that the merging of these horizons in play results in an event of being in which the truth for us of the law ever asserts itself anew for the present. Thus, we as interpreting subjects have no ultimate control over the manifestation of truth as modernity tends to suggest with its theories and methods. Rather, this truth happens to us as it asserts itself. Accordingly, we do not discover the truth of the law, but are instead grasped by it, just as in an event of proclamation we are grasped by the truth of the gospel. VI. THE POSTMODERN CHARACTER OF LAW AND ITS TRUTH What is the character of this law that is constantly happening or asserting itself? Because the truth of the law results from a constant mediation of past and 294

Word, World, and a Postmodern Theology of Law present, it, although always thoroughly contemporary, also has a timeless quality by means of which something of enduring significance, namely the Word as it reflects God s will for us, is constantly proving itself. It is finite in that the law as we have received it in the past runs out and is broken open as it addresses the new demands of the present, requiring us to remain receptive to the new possibilities and orientations that God s will for the future may require of it. It is productive in that God s law always exceeds our understanding of it at any given time so that its truth keeps happening and is always on the way. It is rhetorical in that it arises more from conversation and praxis than deductive logic, convincing and persuading us as we go without necessarily being able to prove. Finally, it is plural in that both the relativistic idea that every interpretation is equally truthful and the dogmatic idea that only one necessarily is so must be rejected. There may be equally well-justified interpretations of what God s law requires in a given context. In such cases we as moral actors must choose between multiple ways of proceeding that appear equally more or less just, being called upon in this way to be co-creators of the law. VII. THE ISSUE OF CRITERIA But how do we test whether we truly have become grasped by God s Word as it asserts itself as the truth of the law? We cannot step outside these events of hermeneutic fusion of horizons in order to identify transcendent means and methods of doing so. Specifically, we cannot rely on the enlightenment s strong concept of autonomous, disinterested, and unbiased reason, since, as we have already seen, reason is always to some degree the captive of some outside agenda. Nor can we rely overly on pre-established criteria, since, although we shall always apply criteria, in postmodernity no criterion can be taken as foundational. Modernity s framing of the question of truth, based upon criteria of scientific reason and method, admitted answers compatible only with its restricted point of view, thus robbing Shakespeare and Bach (not to mention the claims of faith) of any meaningful claim to truth. On the other hand, if there are no definitive criteria, neither are we left totally at sea. Gadamer s postmodern hermeneutical approach suggests its own signposts of recognition. One such signpost is tradition. Any disagreement we may have in the present presupposes a more profound common agreement based in tradition. Thus, for us Christians there is inevitably brought into play in ethical deliberation the horizon of the Christian narrative as it has found expression in legal and moral convictions. Of course, tradition is not followed blindly. The Word, since it is always flowering in a new parousia, is genuinely deconstructive, refusing to be bound to the cross of any aspect of tradition that has become unjust and oppressive. A second such signpost is what Gadamer calls the sensus communis. God s law is assuredly not the result of a popularity contest or the dictate of fashion. It does, however, include a common sense recognition of what has already come into being and cannot be changed, a sensitivity to the community s present needs, aims, 295

Lokken and hopes for the future, and a sense of proportion and relationship that is governed by the requirements of humanity as a whole, but always subject, of course, to a postmodern prophetic vigilance against the suppression of new meaning. VIII. AN INTERSECTION OF FAITH, WORD, WORLD, AND LAW If our discussion of tradition and sensus communis has given us some sense of confidence in law s stability and continuity, we nevertheless still have not solved the problem whether we can discern the law with certainty. In many situations we simply may not know what God would have us do. In such cases we may ultimately not know whether what we have chosen to do is obedient or disobedient to God s law. Thus, any certainty we now have in the law must ultimately rest in faith. It is a faith that constantly asserts as against nihilism that there is truth in this postmodern world, and indeed truth in law. As Word bears on the world, law comes thereby to be expressed in the multiplicity of human word. And while we make full use of reason, criteria, and signposts, in the end we recognize God s law in the blessed mode of light and beauty that is uniquely the Word s, however it may be obscured in this world of finitude. Thus, when we are able to see meaningful bases of distinction, so that not all opinions and proposals appear equally good, it is by means of God s Word. When we begin in the course of theoretical argument to recognize the reasons, based in the traditional, the pragmatic, or the contextual, why one solution begins to take on greater weight and truth than another, it is by means of God s Word. The unity that shines through all terrestrial things (including the law) self-evidently as their beauty is the Word. And so, while we can and should continually seek the law, we do not discover it, nor can we control it with our modern quest for certainty and right answers. Rather, as the Word has its way with us, we are grasped by it, captivated and claimed by it however imperfectly, and brought home by it even as we continue as sojourners in our postmodern world. PAUL LOKKEN is associate dean for graduate theological education at Luther Seminary, St. Paul, Minnesota. 296