Deduction. Of all the modes of reasoning, deductive arguments have the strongest relationship between the premises

Similar documents
Logic Appendix: More detailed instruction in deductive logic

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 1. Background Material for the Exercise on Validity

MCQ IN TRADITIONAL LOGIC. 1. Logic is the science of A) Thought. B) Beauty. C) Mind. D) Goodness

Complications for Categorical Syllogisms. PHIL 121: Methods of Reasoning February 27, 2013 Instructor:Karin Howe Binghamton University

5.3 The Four Kinds of Categorical Propositions

Pastor-teacher Don Hargrove Faith Bible Church September 8, 2011

Venn Diagrams and Categorical Syllogisms. Unit 5

Part 2 Module 4: Categorical Syllogisms

Argument Basics. When an argument shows that its conclusion is worth accepting we say that the argument is good.

To better understand VALIDITY, we now turn to the topic of logical form.

ELEMENTS OF LOGIC. 1.1 What is Logic? Arguments and Propositions

Baronett, Logic (4th ed.) Chapter Guide

SYLLOGISTIC LOGIC CATEGORICAL PROPOSITIONS

SHORT ANSWER. Write the word or phrase that best completes each statement or answers the question.

Intro Viewed from a certain angle, philosophy is about what, if anything, we ought to believe.

What is a logical argument? What is deductive reasoning? Fundamentals of Academic Writing

Philosophy 1100: Ethics

Unit 4. Reason as a way of knowing. Tuesday, March 4, 14

Unit. Categorical Syllogism. What is a syllogism? Types of Syllogism

PHI Introduction Lecture 4. An Overview of the Two Branches of Logic

Logic Book Part 1! by Skylar Ruloff!

A Primer on Logic Part 1: Preliminaries and Vocabulary. Jason Zarri. 1. An Easy $10.00? a 3 c 2. (i) (ii) (iii) (iv)

Lecture 3 Arguments Jim Pryor What is an Argument? Jim Pryor Vocabulary Describing Arguments

Part II: How to Evaluate Deductive Arguments

Selections from Aristotle s Prior Analytics 41a21 41b5

7.1. Unit. Terms and Propositions. Nature of propositions. Types of proposition. Classification of propositions

Introduction to Philosophy

John Buridan. Summulae de Dialectica IX Sophismata

EXERCISES: (from

6.5 Exposition of the Fifteen Valid Forms of the Categorical Syllogism

Section 3.5. Symbolic Arguments. Copyright 2013, 2010, 2007, Pearson, Education, Inc.

1.5. Argument Forms: Proving Invalidity

Recall. Validity: If the premises are true the conclusion must be true. Soundness. Valid; and. Premises are true

Study Guides. Chapter 1 - Basic Training

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER IX CHAPTER IX FORMAL CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE

Anthony P. Andres. The Place of Conversion in Aristotelian Logic. Anthony P. Andres

The Appeal to Reason. Introductory Logic pt. 1

Dr. Carlo Alvaro Reasoning and Argumentation Distribution & Opposition DISTRIBUTION

A s a contracts professional, from

L4: Reasoning. Dani Navarro

Section 3.5. Symbolic Arguments. Copyright 2013, 2010, 2007, Pearson, Education, Inc.

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

A short introduction to formal logic

BASIC CONCEPTS OF LOGIC

Lecture 1: Validity & Soundness

In this section you will learn three basic aspects of logic. When you are done, you will understand the following:

1. To arrive at the truth we have to reason correctly. 2. Logic is the study of correct reasoning. B. DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE ARGUMENTS

PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy

5.6.1 Formal validity in categorical deductive arguments

The Problem of Major Premise in Buddhist Logic

9.1 Intro to Predicate Logic Practice with symbolizations. Today s Lecture 3/30/10

Critical Thinking is:

LOGIC ANTHONY KAPOLKA FYF 101-9/3/2010

13.6 Euler Diagrams and Syllogistic Arguments

Introduction to Philosophy

REASONING SYLLOGISM. Subject Predicate Distributed Not Distributed Distributed Distributed

Topics and Posterior Analytics. Philosophy 21 Fall, 2004 G. J. Mattey

CHAPTER 10 VENN DIAGRAMS

Transition to Quantified Predicate Logic

7. Some recent rulings of the Supreme Court were politically motivated decisions that flouted the entire history of U.S. legal practice.

Introduction to Philosophy Crito. Instructor: Jason Sheley

Unit 4. Reason as a way of knowing

PRACTICE EXAM The state of Israel was in a state of mourning today because of the assassination of Yztzak Rabin.

Categorical Logic Handout Logic: Spring Sound: Any valid argument with true premises.

Chapter 1. Introduction. 1.1 Deductive and Plausible Reasoning Strong Syllogism

BASIC CONCEPTS OF LOGIC

Instructor s Manual 1

Argument and Persuasion. Stating Opinions and Proposals

PHILOSOPHY 102 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC PRACTICE EXAM 1. W# Section (10 or 11) 4. T F The statements that compose a disjunction are called conjuncts.

Three Kinds of Arguments

What would count as Ibn Sīnā (11th century Persia) having first order logic?

Geometry TEST Review Chapter 2 - Logic

Geometry 2.3.notebook October 02, 2015

Relevance. Premises are relevant to the conclusion when the truth of the premises provide some evidence that the conclusion is true

Criticizing Arguments

Basic Concepts and Skills!

The Development of Laws of Formal Logic of Aristotle

The antecendent always a expresses a sufficient condition for the consequent

Proofs of Non-existence

CRITICAL THINKING (CT) MODEL PART 1 GENERAL CONCEPTS

Identify the subject and predicate terms in, and name the form of, each of the following propositions.

1.5 Deductive and Inductive Arguments

Aristotle ( ) His scientific thinking, his physics.

The Sea-Fight Tomorrow by Aristotle

Ethics and Science. Obstacles to search for truth. Ethics: Basic Concepts 1

LOGICAL THINKING CHAPTER DEDUCTIVE THINKING: THE SYLLOGISM. If we reason it is not because we like to, but because we must.

1.6 Validity and Truth

1. Immediate inferences embodied in the square of opposition 2. Obversion 3. Conversion

Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak.

What is an argument? PHIL 110. Is this an argument? Is this an argument? What about this? And what about this?

Introduction to Analyzing and Evaluating Arguments

1 Clarion Logic Notes Chapter 4

Logic & Philosophy. SSB Syllabus

Epistemology. Diogenes: Master Cynic. The Ancient Greek Skeptics 4/6/2011. But is it really possible to claim knowledge of anything?

Lecture 4: Deductive Validity

Moon s Day, March 23: Elementary Reasoning

Critical Thinking 5.7 Validity in inductive, conductive, and abductive arguments

What we want to know is: why might one adopt this fatalistic attitude in response to reflection on the existence of truths about the future?

Phil 3304 Introduction to Logic Dr. David Naugle. Identifying Arguments i

A R G U M E N T S I N A C T I O N

Transcription:

Deduction Deductive arguments, deduction, deductive logic all means the same thing. They are different ways of referring to the same style of reasoning Deduction is just one mode of reasoning, but it is a formidable form of reasoning. Deductive reasoning is common in the imperial disciplines. Deductive reasoning is prized because deductive arguments have the highest standards of cogency. Of all the modes of reasoning, deductive arguments have the strongest relationship between the premises Recall: we reserve the term sound to describe good deductive arguments.

Recall: Validity In day-to-day life, we talk about a valid driver s license, or the validation of software serial number. Validity is a technical term in deductive logic. If an argument has an appropriate deductive form, then we say that the argument is valid. Recall: deductive logic is just one mode of reasoning, though it is a very powerful form of reasoning. A deductive argument is either valid or invalid. When we say that an argument is invalid we mean that we are rejecting the argument because it doesn t have the right deductive form. When we say this, we don t care about the content of the premises. That is, we don t care what the premises are about.

Recall: Validity (more) If an argument has a valid form and the premises are true, then the conclusion of the argument must be true. The conclusion is deductively entailed. But, an argument may be valid (have the right form or structure) but not be true. It s premises could be false. Important: Committing to the validity of an argument, does not necessarily commit you to the truth conclusion. Likewise, asserting the invalidity of an argument, does not necessarily commit you to rejecting the conclusion. (You might accept the conclusion, but reject the form of the argument given for the conclusion.)

Validity Illustrated P1: If it s whirly-gig then smack-gurgle. P2: This is a whirly-gig. C1: This is also a smack-gurgle. This is a valid argument. We recognize the form as being valid. All arguments of this form are valid: P1: If P then Q. P2: P C1: Therefore, Q But, not all arguments of this form necessarily produce true conclusions. In this case, we don t know if the premises are true or false. We only know that argument is valid. We know nothing about its truth!

An example of validity Premise: All apples are fruit. Premise: All fruit contain antioxidants. Conclusion: All apples contain antioxidants. Premise: All aardvarks have long noses. Premise: Anything with a long nose has an acute sense of smell. Conclusion: All aardvarks have an acute sense of smell. Logical form: All As are Bs. All Bs are Cs. Therefore, all As are Cs.

A Valid But Untrue Syllogism Consider this syllogism again: P1: All men are purple. P2: Socrates is a man. C1: Socrates is purple. This syllogism also has the form: P1: All S are P P2: M is S C1: M is P Recall: Truth and Validity are different things. Validity guarantees (and only guarantees) that if the premises are true the conclusion will be true. In this case, P1 is false. So, the conclusion is false. Nonetheless, the form of the syllogism is valid.

Important! Validity and Truth are Different. Example 1: P1: All men are mortal. P2: Socrates is a man. C1: Socrates is mortal. (Valid and True) Example 2: P1: All men are purple. P2: Socrates is a man. C1: Socrates is purple. (Valid but false) Note: Example 1 and Example 2 have exactly the same form or structure of argument. This is one valid form of deductive argument. Common Form: All S are P M is an S. Therefore, M is P

Valid Deductive Arguments are Truth Preserving Look at Example 2 again: P1: All men are purple. P2: Socrates is a man. C1: Socrates is purple. (Valid but false) What went wrong? Clearly, P1 is false. It is not true that All men are purple. Hypothetically, if P1 were true, then C1 would be true too! Valid deductive arguments are truth preserving. That s a fancy way of saying that: in valid deductive arguments are machines the gobble up true premises and split out true conclusions.

Why we deduction In deductive arguments, the premises entail the conclusion. This is because valid deductive arguments are truth preserving. And so, it is not possible for the premises of a deductive argument to be true and the conclusion false. In more detail: If (1) the premises are true, And (2) the form of the deductive argument is valid, Then (3) the conclusion must be true always and forever which is why imperial disciplines love deduction!

Deductive Logic Often when people say logic they mean deductive logic There are other logics, notably, inductive logic. Deductive logic is studies the valid forms of deductive argument. It looks at the forms of argument that preserve truth. It looks at ways of testing arguments to see if they are valid (truth preserving). Important: Form NOT Content! Deductive logic is concerned purely with forms of argument, not the content. It is not concerned with truth. It is only concerned with figuring out the arguments that preserve truth.

Scope of Course Concern There are many types of deductive logic. We will be looking briefly at one: categorical logic The aim is to understand what deductive arguments look likes so you know when you are dealing with a situation involving deductive entailment. Shameless advertisement: If you want deductive logic, take PHIL2210 and then PHIL3110.

Categorical Logic Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good arguments have common shapes, forms or patterns. Aristotle thought of logic as a tool or organon for inquiry. We call Aristotle s tool categorical logic, or syllogistic logic, or simply syllogism.

Four Categorical Statements 1) Universal Affirmative All S is P All men are mortal Every man is an island 2) Universal Negative No S is P No conservatives are fiscally responsible. No penguins are flying birds. 3) Particular Affirmative Some S is P Some guinea pigs have long hair. Some Tories are good people 4) Particular Negative Some S is not P Some people are not generous Some rocks are not sedimentary.

Variables The four forms of the syllogism are: All S are P; No S are P; Some S are P; Some S are not P. We use S and P to stand for the specific content of the statements. We do this because we are only interested in the form of the statements. The use of variables helps us achieve generality. We say that S and P are variables. The specific content of S and P may change or vary.

Categories We use S to stand for the subject of the statement (what the statement is about) and P to stand for the predicate of the statement (what is begin said about the subject.) The choice of S and P as variables is entirely conventional. We could use any letter or other symbol Categorical logic is the logic of categories. The subject and predicate will always be categories. Any category can include only one thing, five things, or everything. Likewise, a category can exclude only one thing, five things, or everything.

Examples All robins are birds. Every thing in the category robin is a member of the category birds. No elephants are reptiles. Everything in the category elephant is not a member of the category reptile. Some mammals are marsupials. Some of the things in the category of mammals are members of the category or marsuplials. Some animals are not viviparous. Some of the things that are animals are not things that are viviparous.

Categorical Form We make many assertions about categories, but most of the time the sentences that we utter are not exactly in categorical form. Nevertheless, it is still plausible to represent their content in the categorical form. That is, we can translate many different kinds of sentences into sentences with one of the four categorical forms.

Everyday sentences can be translated into categorical sentences and categorical sentences can be translated into standard form Every robin is a bird. All robins are birds. All S are P Every elephant is not a reptile. No elephants are reptiles. No S are P There are a few mammals that are marsupials Some mammals are marsupials. Some S are P You can find animals that are not viviparous. Some animals are not viviparous. Some S are not P

Translation into Categorical Form (1) Stylistic variants: many different sentences can assert exactly the same categorical relation. All Texans are ornery, Every single Texan is ornery, Any Texan is ornery, There is no Texan who is not ornery. (2) A and The are ambiguous between a particular and a universal (or generic) sense. A lion is a mammal makes a different claim that A lion just escaped from the zoo (3) Any is generally universal, but is particular when inside the scope of a not. Compare Amy can solve any problem and Amy cannot solve any problem. (4) Only : Like all, only asserts a universal affirmative, but it asserts the opposite inclusion relation. Only Ss are P translates into Categorical form as All Ps are S.

Syllogism Syllogisms are a basic form of argument. Syllogisms have three lines; two premises and one conclusion. You see lots of syllogisms. Here are two you have seen in the course: P1: All men are mortal. P2: Socrates is a man. C1: Socrates is mortal. P1: All three-sided figures are triangles. P2: This figure has three sides. C1: This figure is a triangle.

Anatomy of a Syllogism A syllogism consists of three sentences. Two premises and one conclusion. Each sentence is made up of two terms. Every term occurs twice in a syllogism. Count the terms in the following syllogism P1: All S are M P2: No M are P C1: No S are P Each unique term that makes up the syllogism has a particular name. The predicate, P, of the conclusion is the major term. The subject, S, of the conclusion is the minor term. The term that appears in both premises but not the conclusion is the middle term.

Translating Syllogisms into Categorical Form P1: All men are mortal. P2: Socrates is a man. C1: Socrates is mortal. P1: All S are P P2: M is S C1: M is P P1: All three-sided figures are triangles. P2: This figure has three sides. C1: This figure is a triangle. P1: All S are P P2: M is S C1: M is P These syllogisms have different contents but the same logical form! They are valid for the same reason.

Translate Syllogism into Categorical Form No lawyers are golfers, but some golfers are doctors. Therefore, no lawyers are doctors. No L are G. Some G are D. Therefore, no L are D.

Translation Only doctors are golfers, and any golfer has good turf shoes. So, all doctors have good turf shoes. All G are D. All G are S. Therefore, all D are S.

Venn Diagrams In Symbolic Logic (1881), English mathematician John Venn (1834-1923) invented a way to pictorially represent categorical statements, and to test syllogisms for validity. Every category is represented by a circle. We overlap the circles, so that we can represent inclusion and exclusion relations between categories.

One Category

One Category

Two Categories Lawyers Golfers

Two Categories Golfers only Lawyers Golfers Lawyers only Lawyers who are also golfers.

Picturing Categorical Statements We can use Venn diagrams to picture categorical statements and syllogisms. We use Venn diagrams to picture logical space. [In Venn diagrams] logical space is represented in circles and parts of circles. To indicate that there is nothing in an area of logical space, we shade in the area. To indicate that there is something, we put an x in the space. [216]

Universal Affirmative All lawyers are golfers. All S are P. S lawyers P golfers

Universal Negative No lawyers are golfers. No S are P. S lawyers P golfers

Particular Affirmative Some lawyers are golfers. Some S are P. S lawyers P golfers X

Particular Negative Some lawyers are not golfers. Some S are not P. S lawyers P golfers X

Venn Diagrams and Syllogisms We can use Venn diagrams to picture syllogisms, AND to check whether or not the syllogism is valid or invalid. Consider the syllogism: All S are P No P is M Therefore, no S is M. Every categorical statement has two terms, and so we pictured categorical statements with two circles, one for each term. Since a syllogism has three terms, we will need three circles to picture the syllogism, again one for each term.

Venn Diagram for a Syllogism S P M

An Example Consider the syllogism: All liberals are Keynesians. No Keynesians are monetarists. Therefore, no liberal is a monetarist. The syllogism has the form: All S are M No M are P Therefore, no S are P. We can picture this syllogism in a Venn diagram.

P1: All S are M P2: No M are P C1: No S are P S P M

** P1: All S are M ** P2: No M are P C1: No S are P S P M

** P1: All S are M ** P2: No M are P C1: No S are P S P M

P1: All S are M ** P2: No M is P ** C1: No S is P S P M

Validity and Invalidity In valid deductions, the conclusion states no more information than has already been stated in the premises. This is why valid deductive arguments are truth preserving. They simply preserve whatever truth happens to have been stated in the premises. If the conclusion states more than has been stated in the premises, then the conclusion is invalid. To see if a conclusion is valid or invalid, we simply check to see if the information in the conclusion is already pictured in the Venn diagram. If the information is already on the diagram, then the syllogism is valid. If the information is not already on the diagram if something new has been stated in the conclusion then the syllogism is invalid.

P1: All S are M P2: No M is P ** C1: No S is P ** S P Valid! The area in green picturing No S is P was already shaded black and red. So, all the information in the conclusion is information already in the premises. M

Another Example P1: Some people who smoke also drink. P2: Some people who drink take risks. C1: Some people who smoke take risks. P1: Some S are M P2: Some M are P C1: Some S are P

** P1: Some S are M ** P2: Some M are P C1: Some S are P S P X M

** P1: Some S are M ** P2: Some M are P C1: Some S are P S P X X M

P1: Some S are M ** P2: Some M are P ** C1: Some S are P S P X X X M

P1: Some S are M P2: Some M are P ** C1: Some S are P ** S P X (!) X X X Invalid! Note that the X marked with an exclamation point was not information included in either of the premises. M

Like forms have like properties of validity and invalidity We began with examples that included content. We replaced the content with variables. This allows us to achieve generality. The specific content of an argument does not affect its validity or invalidity. From the first example, all syllogisms are valid if they have the form: P1: All S are M P2: No M are P P3: No S are P. From the second example, all syllogisms are invalid if they have the form: P1: Some S are M P2: Some M are P C1: Some S are P Keep in mind, these are just specific examples. There are, of course, many other valid syllogism forms. We will need to test each to see if it is a valid or invalid form.

Last Example P1: All fuzzies are dolittles. P2: Some dolittles are mugwumps. C1: No fuzzies are mugwumps. P1: All S are M P2: Some M are P C1: No S are P We are going to do this example in a single diagram.

P1: All S are M P2: Some M are P C1: No S are P S P X X Invalid! Note the shading and the X in the very center section indicates a contradiction. M

Summary of Some Key Points All categorical statements have one of four forms. Each has a unique Venn diagram with two circles. We can use a Venn diagram with three circles to represent a syllogism and test whether the syllogism is valid or invalid. Remember that validity and invalidity has nothing to do with truth and falsity. Valid arguments preserve truth. In a valid argument, if the premises are true, then the conclusion will be true. Valid deductive arguments provide the strongest relationship between premises and conclusion. Such arguments are sound; i.e., possess the highest standard of cogency.