Moore on External Relations

Similar documents
Early Russell on Philosophical Grammar

2.3. Failed proofs and counterexamples

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Pastor-teacher Don Hargrove Faith Bible Church September 8, 2011

Intro Viewed from a certain angle, philosophy is about what, if anything, we ought to believe.

Philosophy of Mind. Introduction to the Mind-Body Problem

15. Russell on definite descriptions

Logic clearly dictates that the needs of the many outweigh the needs of the few or the needs of the one (Spock and Captain Kirk).

Lecture 3 Arguments Jim Pryor What is an Argument? Jim Pryor Vocabulary Describing Arguments

10.3 Universal and Existential Quantifiers

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Lecture 25 Hume on Causation

A Solution to the Gettier Problem Keota Fields. the three traditional conditions for knowledge, have been discussed extensively in the

Can logical consequence be deflated?

10 CERTAINTY G.E. MOORE: SELECTED WRITINGS

Informalizing Formal Logic

Philosophy of Mind. Introduction to the Mind-Body Problem

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

PART III - Symbolic Logic Chapter 7 - Sentential Propositions

A Primer on Logic Part 1: Preliminaries and Vocabulary. Jason Zarri. 1. An Easy $10.00? a 3 c 2. (i) (ii) (iii) (iv)

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Logic: A Brief Introduction

Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions. David Braun. University of Rochester

What is a logical argument? What is deductive reasoning? Fundamentals of Academic Writing

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC FOR METAPHYSICIANS

Logic for Computer Science - Week 1 Introduction to Informal Logic

Prior, Berkeley, and the Barcan Formula. James Levine Trinity College, Dublin

ELEMENTS OF LOGIC. 1.1 What is Logic? Arguments and Propositions

PHILOSOPHY ESSAY ADVICE

Introduction to Philosophy

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

INTERMEDIATE LOGIC Glossary of key terms

CHAPTER 1 A PROPOSITIONAL THEORY OF ASSERTIVE ILLOCUTIONARY ARGUMENTS OCTOBER 2017

God of the gaps: a neglected reply to God s stone problem

A Problem for a Direct-Reference Theory of Belief Reports. Stephen Schiffer New York University

How Gödelian Ontological Arguments Fail

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

From Grounding to Truth-Making: Some Thoughts

Keynes s probability An introduction to the theory of logical groups

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling

A Note on a Remark of Evans *

Tools for Logical Analysis. Roger Bishop Jones

Semantic Entailment and Natural Deduction

10. Presuppositions Introduction The Phenomenon Tests for presuppositions

[3.] Bertrand Russell. 1

Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments

Klein on the Unity of Cartesian and Contemporary Skepticism

Logic. If and only if / Si et seulement si / Genau dann, wenn

Dynamics of change in logic

The Problem of Major Premise in Buddhist Logic

Figure 1 Figure 2 U S S. non-p P P

What is Physicalism? Meet Mary the Omniscient Scientist

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant

Exercise Sets. KS Philosophical Logic: Modality, Conditionals Vagueness. Dirk Kindermann University of Graz July 2014

Subjective Logic: Logic as Rational Belief Dynamics. Richard Johns Department of Philosophy, UBC

Primitive Thisness and Primitive Identity Robert Merrihew Adams

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Possibility and Necessity

Avicenna, Proof of the Necessary of Existence

2. Refutations can be stronger or weaker.

Philosophy 125 Day 12: Overview

Artificial Intelligence: Valid Arguments and Proof Systems. Prof. Deepak Khemani. Department of Computer Science and Engineering

C. Exam #1 comments on difficult spots; if you have questions about this, please let me know. D. Discussion of extra credit opportunities

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

DESCARTES ON THE OBJECTIVE REALITY OF MATERIALLY FALSE IDEAS

Selections from Aristotle s Prior Analytics 41a21 41b5

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

WHY PLANTINGA FAILS TO RECONCILE DIVINE FOREKNOWLEDGE

What is an argument? PHIL 110. Is this an argument? Is this an argument? What about this? And what about this?

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

A Note on Straight-Thinking

Evaluating Classical Identity and Its Alternatives by Tamoghna Sarkar

2016 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

Externalism and a priori knowledge of the world: Why privileged access is not the issue Maria Lasonen-Aarnio

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER IX CHAPTER IX FORMAL CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE

Logic Appendix: More detailed instruction in deductive logic

Reply to Robert Koons

HANDBOOK. IV. Argument Construction Determine the Ultimate Conclusion Construct the Chain of Reasoning Communicate the Argument 13

Divisibility, Logic, Radical Empiricism, and Metaphysics

Imprint THE RELATION BETWEEN CONCEPTION AND CAUSATION IN SPINOZA S METAPHYSICS. John Morrison. volume 13, no. 3. february 2013

Aquinas' Third Way Modalized

PHI Introduction Lecture 4. An Overview of the Two Branches of Logic

Puzzles for Divine Omnipotence & Divine Freedom

To better understand VALIDITY, we now turn to the topic of logical form.

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

Russell: On Denoting

PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE

Theories of propositions

MCQ IN TRADITIONAL LOGIC. 1. Logic is the science of A) Thought. B) Beauty. C) Mind. D) Goodness

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Transition to Quantified Predicate Logic

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011

The Cosmological Argument: A Defense

TRUTH-MAKERS AND CONVENTION T

Transcription:

Moore on External Relations G. J. Mattey Fall, 2005 / Philosophy 156 The Dogma of Internal Relations Moore claims that there is a dogma held by philosophers such as Bradley and Joachim, that all relations are internal. Joachim: All relations qualify or modify or make a difference to the terms between which they hold (The Nature of Truth, p. 12). Moore claims further that the dogma is difficult to understand. He will provide a clear proposition which it implies and which is certainly false. And he will argue that given the meaning of internal in the proposition, there are some relations which are purely external. A Weak Version of the Dogma The kind of fact that is expressed by stating that a relation obtains involves more than just the terms and the relations themselves. Edward VII was the father of George V. The fact consists of more than just Edward, George, and fatherhood. The relation must relate the terms. Those who claim that all relations are internal seem to be claiming something stronger than this. A Strong Version of the Dogma When entering into a relation brings about a change in a thing, we say that the thing is modified by the relation. By putting wax into a flame, we make it melt. The dogma might be that all relations modify, in the sense of bringing about a change it, the terms which stand in it. 1

If so, the dogma is clearly false, since some terms stand in relations but do not change at all. Moore concludes that modify must be understood in a analogous sense. Relational Properties The dogma seems to be that when a thing stands in a relation to a thing, it is the standing in the relation which modifies it. The claim, then, is not strictly that the relation itself modifies the thing. So Moore introduces the notion of a relational property A single relation, e.g. fatherhood, may be the source of more than one relational property, being the father of someone. Edward VII has the relational property of being the father of Edward Duke of Clarence. Edward VII has the relational property of being the father of George V. If we can understand what it is for a relational property to be external, we can easily derive a sense in which a relation is external. An Analogous Sense of Modify If A s possession of a relation Φ modifies A in the sense of literally modifying (changing) A, then standing in relation Φ to A would make A different from what it was if it not have Φ. If the being held in the flame causes the sealing-wax to melt, we can truly say (in some sense) that the sealing-wax would not have been in a melted state if it had not been in the flame. The condition that standing in relation Φ to A would make A different from what it was if it not have Φ seems applicable as well to cases which do not involve literal modification. So this will be taken to be the analogical sense of modifies that powers the dogma. It can always be truly asserted of any term x which has that property, that any term which had not had it would necessarily have been different from x. 2

Necessity The proposition in question can be clarified further by explanation of the use of would necessarily have been. If any x which had Φ would necessarily have Ψ (here, being different from x), then it follows from the fact that x has Φ that it has Ψ. Moore gives to examples to illustrate his use of follows from. Difference It follows from the fact that something is a right-angled triangle that it is a triangle. It follows from the fact that something is red that it is colored. It remains to clarify the use of different from. Difference may be of two types: Numerical difference, non-identity, Qualitative difference, difference in some respect. If A is qualitatively different from B, then A and B are numerically different. If ball A is red in color and ball B is green in color, they are two different balls. The dogma seems to apply most clearly to qualitative difference. And so it applies to numerical difference as well. Internal Relations in the Qualitative Sense Φ is an internal relation if and only if any x which has Φ is such that it follows from the fact that y lacks Φ that it is qualitatively different from x. Moore thinks that it is difficult to find a plausible example of an internal relation of this sort. One possibility is to make x itself a quality which has relations to other qualities. The quality orange has the relational property of being intermediate between the qualities yellow and red. The quality orange which is intermediate between yellow and red is such that it follows from the fact that a quality is not intermediate between yellow and red that it is qualitatively different from orange. It seems that most relational properties are not internal in this sense. But a more compelling case against the dogma can be made if weaker version involving numerical identity is false. 3

Internal Relations in the Numerical Sense Φ is an internal relation if and only if any x which has Φ is such that it follows from the fact that y lacks Φ that it is numerically different from x. A case of a relation which is internal in this sense is that of a whole to its parts. A visual sense-datum which is half red and half yellow would be a different sense-datum if it lacked the relation to the two colored patches that make it up. On the other hand, the relation of parts to a whole seems external. The red patch in a visual sense-datum would be numerically the same red patch even if it did not compose a whole with the yellow patch. To deny this obviously flies in the face of common sense. Standing in the relation is a mere matter of fact, and this seems to me to be the most important thing that can be meant by saying that some relations are purely external. Motivation for the Dogma Moore wonders how any philosopher could deny that standing in some relations is a mere matter of fact. His diagnosis is that a true proposition is confused with a false one. True: (1) If A has Φ and x lacks Φ, then it follows that A is not identical to x. If George V s father is Edward VII, and some person s father is not Edward VII, it follows that the person is not George V. False: (2) If A has Φ, then from the fact that x lacks Φ, it follows that A is not identical to x. If George V s father is Edward VII, then from the fact that some person s father is not Edward VII, it follows that the person is not identical to George V. The difference may be so clear that nothing more needs to be said, but it conflicts with a common view in logic. 4

Some Logical Notation Moore tries to formulate his objection to the move from (1) to (2) in the language of Russell s Principia Mathematica. So we will need to introduce a bit of notation in order to follow his moves. Universal quantifiers, (x), (x, y), (x, y, z), etc. express (in the terminology of On Denoting ) for all values of x, for all values of x and y, etc. Negation,, expresses that it is not the case that. Material implication,, expresses that it is not the case that what is on the left side is true and what is on the right side is false. We will dispense with Russell s dot grouping punctuation in favor of parentheses. Entailment If q follows from p (as in the examples given above), we can say that p entails q. Russell had no special notation for entailment, so Moore supplies the expression ent. He gives as an example the conjunction of premises in a syllogism of the form Barbara entailing its conclusion. All whales are mammals and all mammals are warm-blooded entails All whales are warm-blooded : p ent q. He also gives an example of a non-entailment a connection which is not logical. Socrates was a man does not entail Socrates was mortal : not p ent q. Formal Representation of the Two Propositions True proposition (1): (x, y)(φx ent ( Φx y x)). False proposition (2): (x, y)(φx ( Φx ent y x)). It can be easily seen that the move from (1) to (2) involves exchanging places between and ent. In terms of propositional logic, the move is as follows: From p ent (q r), To p (q ent r). This is the move that Moore finds to be invalid. 5

A Counter-Example True: All men are mortal entails it is not the case that Socrates is a man and Socrates is not mortal. False: It is not the case that all men are mortal and Socrates is a man does not entail Socrates is mortal. In fact, it is the case that all men are mortal and that Socrates is a man does not entail Socrates is mortal. The Source of the Confusion The reason one might be tempted to hold (2) is due to Bertrand Russell s interpretation of the connective. He thought (at least at one time) that it expresses a form of implication, material implication. Then implication is thought of as expressing entailment, and there is no distinction between: p q implies p ent q, or (x)(φx Ψx) implies (x)(φx ent Ψx). In either case (2) would follow from (1). A Counter-Example True: It is not the case that both I am in this room and I am not more than five years old. False: I am in this room entails I am more than five years old. Being a person in this room does not bear the relation to being more than five years old that being a right angle bears to being an angle. Other interpretations of ent involving also fail to sanction the move from (1) to (2). 6

Some Relational Properties are Not External Having dispensed with the only argument he could find in favor of the thesis that all relational properties are internal, Moore turns to the question of whether some are not internal (in his sense). All Moore can say is that it seems evident in many cases that a term which has a certain relational property might quite well not have had it. That this is this does not entail that this has to other things all the relations which it in fact has. That Edward VII was father of George V does not entail that Edward VII would not be Edward VII were he not father of George V. The Identity of Indiscernibles In a very strong sense, relations are internal when anything not having a relation Φ that x has is necessarily qualitatively distinct from x Two ping-pong balls in different locations (hence differing in a relational property) necessarily differ in some quality. The identity of indiscernibles follows from the strong sense of internal relations. Two ping-pong balls that are different necessarily differ in some quality. Moore accepts the claim that if two (say) ping-pong balls are different, then they necessarily differ in some relational property. He also claims that the identity of indiscernibles is obviously false, which would make the proposition that relations are internal (in the strong sense) false as well. Grounding Russell understands the dogma as asserting that Every relation is grounded in the natures of its related terms. But he is puzzled about what the natures are. If the natures are the terms (things) themselves, then it follows from the weak, numerical, version of the dogma that every relational property follows from the thing s just being the thing it is. If the natures are non-relational qualities, then it follows from the strong, qualitative, version of the dogma that every relational property follows from a thing s having all its qualities, since things differing in relational properties are qualitatively different. There is a sense in which a relation is grounded in the nature of its related terms: the thing has some non-relational property without which it could not have the relational property. 7