Authority Beyond the Bounds of Mere Reason in the Schmitt-Strauss Exchange

Similar documents
Leo Strauss lettore di Hermann Cohen (Leo Strauss Reads Hermann

POLI 342: MODERN WESTERN POLITICAL THOUGHT

The Need for Metanormativity: A Response to Christmas

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

A CONCEPTUAL ANALYSIS OF SECULARISM AND ITS LEGITIMACY IN THE CONSTITUTIONAL DEMOCRATIC STATE

Process Thought and Bridge Building: A Response to Stephen K. White. Kevin Schilbrack

A Brief History of Thinking about Thinking Thomas Lombardo

The dangers of the sovereign being the judge of rationality

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Reading Questions for Phil , Fall 2016 (Daniel)

The Holy See APOSTOLIC JOURNEY TO THE UNITED KINGDOM (SEPTEMBER 16-19, 2010)

4 Liberty, Rationality, and Agency in Hobbes s Leviathan

PROVOCATION EVERYONE IS A PHILOSOPHER! T.M. Scanlon

Taoist and Confucian Contributions to Harmony in East Asia: Christians in dialogue with Confucian Thought and Taoist Spirituality.

Who Has the Burden of Proof? Must the Christian Provide Adequate Reasons for Christian Beliefs?

Secularization in Western territory has another background, namely modernity. Modernity is evaluated from the following philosophical point of view.

What is the "Social" in "Social Coherence?" Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious Freedom in an Egalitarian Age

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

INTRODUCTION. Human knowledge has been classified into different disciplines. Each

PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY

SEMINAR ON NINETEENTH CENTURY THEOLOGY

Religious Studies. Name: Institution: Course: Date:

COMITÉ SUR LES AFFAIRES RELIGIEUSES A NEW APPROACH TO RELIGIOUS EDUCATION IN SCHOOL: A CHOICE REGARDING TODAY S CHALLENGES

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

On the Origins and Normative Status of the Impartial Spectator

PREFERENCES AND VALUE ASSESSMENTS IN CASES OF DECISION UNDER RISK

Descartes and Schopenhauer on Voluntary Movement:

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

Response to Gregory Floyd s Where Does Hermeneutics Lead? Brad Elliott Stone, Loyola Marymount University ACPA 2017

Tuesday, September 2, Idealism


Summary of Chapters. Chapter 1: Introduction and Overview

Resolutio of Idealism into Atheism in Fichte

Teachur Philosophy Degree 2018

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Philosophical Review.

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Postmodernism. Issue Christianity Post-Modernism. Theology Trinitarian Atheism. Philosophy Supernaturalism Anti-Realism

Philosophy Courses-1

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Principles of a Regnum Christi School

Lecture 18: Rationalism

Christian scholars would all agree that their Christian faith ought to shape how

Introduction to SUNY Series in Constructive Postmodern Thought 1

Rorty on the Priority of Democracy to Philosophy

Consciousness might be defined as the perceiver of mental phenomena. We might say that there are no differences between one perceiver and another, as

A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES

Evidence and Transcendence

Forum on Public Policy

Legal and Religious Dimension of Morality in Christian Literature

PART FOUR: CATHOLIC HERMENEUTICS

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

4/30/2010 cforum :: Moderator Control Panel

The University of Texas at Austin Government 382M Unique # The Political Thought of Leo Strauss Fall 2011

GOD'S SILENCE IN THE DIALOGUE ACCORDING TO MARTIN BUBER

William Meehan Essay on Spinoza s psychology.

Remarks by Bani Dugal

Templates for Research Paper

1.3 Target Group 1. One Main Target Group 2. Two Secondary Target Groups 1.4 Objectives 1. Short-Term objectives

Templeton Fellowships at the NDIAS

CHAPTER 2 Test Bank MULTIPLE CHOICE

Kant and his Successors

Care of the Soul: Service-Learning and the Value of the Humanities

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

Legal Positivism: the Separation and Identification theses are true.

ntroduction to Socialist Humanism: An International Symposium by Eri...

Practical Wisdom and Politics

Qué es la filosofía? What is philosophy? Philosophy

BCC Papers 5/2, May

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

What s God got to do with it?

Philosophy Courses-1

REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET. Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary

The Human Deficit according to Immanuel Kant: The Gap between the Moral Law and Human Inability to Live by It. Pieter Vos 1

1/9. The Second Analogy (1)

I, for my part, have tried to bear in mind the very aims Dante set himself in writing this work, that is:

Jesus Alone. Session 6 1 JOHN 5:1-12

Preface. amalgam of "invented and imagined events", but as "the story" which is. narrative of Luke's Gospel has made of it. The emphasis is on the

Florida State University Libraries

The Role of Faith in the Progressive Movement. Part Six of the Progressive Tradition Series. Marta Cook and John Halpin October 2010

The Making of a Modern Zoroastrianism. Zoroaster, also known as Zarathustra, is credited as the founder of the religion that eventually became

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

erscheint in G. Motzkin u.a. (Hg.): Religion and Democracy in a Globalizing Europe (2009) Civil Religion and Secular Religion

Kierkegaard s The Sickness Unto Death is one of the great philosophical works of the 19th

131 seventeenth-century news

Discussion of McCool, From Unity to Pluralism

Multi-faith Statement - University of Salford

SOVEREIGN MILITARY ORDER OF MALTA

EVIL, SIN, FALSITY AND THE DYNAMICS OF FAITH. Masao Abe

Of Skepticism with Regard to the Senses. David Hume

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

REFORM ZIONISM. Excerpts From: Section 6 - Reform Zionist Youth Movement in Israel MICHAEL LIVNI (LANGER) AN EDUCATOR'S PERSPECTIVE

Animal Farm. Teaching Unit. Advanced Placement in English Literature and Composition. Individual Learning Packet. by George Orwell

Towards Guidelines on International Standards of Quality in Theological Education A WCC/ETE-Project

PHD THESIS SUMMARY: Rational choice theory: its merits and limits in explaining and predicting cultural behaviour

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt

Help! Muslims Everywhere Ton van den Beld 1

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

Transcription:

Authority Beyond the Bounds of Mere Reason in the Schmitt-Strauss Exchange John P. McCormick Political Science, University of Chicago; and Radcliffe Institute, Harvard University Outline This essay reevaluates the Weimar writings of Carl Schmitt and Leo Strauss, specifically, their intellectual efforts to replace, as a ground of political authority, Enlightenment rationality with, respectively, political theology and Biblical atheism. These efforts originate in the respective authors idiosyncratically Catholic and Jewish writings from the early twenties, culminate in the their engagement over Schmitt s Concept of the Political in 1932, and continue, with certain changes in orientation, into the early to mid-thirties, after the Weimar Republic had been usurped by the National Socialist Party state. Both authors were deeply affected by the early twentieth century crisis of neo-kantian thought in Germany, a crisis exacerbated by Nietzsche s assault on moral philosophy and by the palpable horrors of the Great War. This crisis is perhaps best characterized as a widespread perception that Enlightenment rationality could not ground itself; in response, supporters scrambled to buttress Enlightenment thought by embedding it in various historical narratives, and detractors reveled in the fact that such a rationality was clearly susceptible to an unprecedented kind of dogmatism that was in fact fundamentally antithetical to reason, substantively understood. Schmitt and Strauss each insisted that Enlightenment rationality was unraveling into a way of thinking that violently rejected form of any kind, fixated myopically on human things

2 and lacked any conception of the external constraints that condition the possibilities of philosophy, morality and politics. Consequently, Enlightenment reason obfuscates genuine expressions of rationality and obscures the necessity of political order as such. For Schmitt, specifically, Enlightenment rationality s failure to ground itself philosophically revealed modern political thought s parasitic reliance on premodern, transcendental forms of authority. Because the Enlightenment did not, as promised, deliver universal truths on which peaceful agreement could be based, mankind in the twentieth century was once again, after a brief hiatus of three or four centuries, searching for the substantive, extrarational, or rather prerational, foundations of political life. Whether superficially linguistic, ethnic, cultural, or economic, the post-enlightenment basis of political existence would be, according to Schmitt, fundamentally theological. While liberals promote parliamentary deliberations, or a gapless system of positive legal norms, or universal principles enshrined in written constitutions, Schmitt insisted that nonrational leaps of faith were required to establish the irreducible bases of political authority. For Strauss, while Orthodox Judaism, with which he expresses great affinity, was, as such, no longer available as a political resource, the historical-cultural notion of the nation prevalent in contemporary Zionism was too dependent on late Enlightenment, German-Christian categories to serve as a singularly Jewish ground of politics. Neither the religious belief associated with orthodoxy, nor the timid doubt exhibited by modern philosophic skeptics from Descartes to Cassirer, nor, for that matter, some characteristically German sublation or synthesis of the two, could, according to Strauss, provide a suitable political grounding in a post- Enlightenment epoch. On the contrary, he would assign this role to the Biblical atheism

3 exhibited by the great state theorists of the seventeenth century and recently revised by Nietzsche and Heidegger, an orientation that is reducible to neither belief nor atheism, moreover, one that can be characterized as neither modern nor traditional. Even though, on Strauss s understanding, early Enlightenment figures, such as Hobbes and Spinoza, were atheistic enemies of orthodox religion and progenitors of the later unrealistically pacific and intellectually self-devouring forms of rationality associated with Kantian liberalism, Strauss admired their harsh and courageous attitude toward the prerational origins of authority, even if the early modern figures would attempt to legitimate this authority, after the fact, on rational grounds. Strauss attributes to their attitude of moral and philosophic probity the basis of an authority that could serve as an alternative to the politically soft and philosophically untenable love thy neighbor at the core of Enlightenment and liberal understanding of human sociality. The phrases political theology and Biblical atheism each imply something religious that is qualified by association with something else; something that either renders religion more concrete or draws out of that which is apparently antireligious elements that were once associated with religiosity. On the one hand, politics and atheism make religion more concrete. Once the Enlightenment eventually banished religion to the interior of human conscience, both Schmitt and Strauss suggest, it essentially abolished the necessary foundation of all political order. Theology had been, before the German Enlightenment, simultaneously religious and political, although the authors will disagree on the extent to which Christianity could be, like, Islam and Judaism, political. The biblical in Strauss s formulation of Biblical atheism recalls the authoritative and authoritative role of the Biblical prophet who imposes law upon unruly human

4 nature and who cultivates the fundamental psychological disposition of awe or fear necessary to makes this founding possible. While God can no longer be the source of such fear or awe, a prophetic figure might still manipulate the fear inherent in the inherently fragile human psyche and necessary for stable human interactions. Whereas traditional atheisms associated with Epicureanism and Averoism was fundamentally soft, rejecting the harsh rigors of religious observance and diminishing the necessity for fear of the divine, modern atheism as expressed by a Hobbes or a Heidegger confronts the harshness of human existence, accentuates the necessarily fearful state this puts human being in fundamentally, and emphasizes the inescapable fact that human beings are in need of rule. The political in Schmitt s political theology accords with the divine-like sovereign power that executive actors must impose upon secular reality so as to save and reaffirm political order and provide the intellectual structures required for the elaboration and realization of morality in human affairs. Politics was fundamentally theological in at least three ways for Schmitt: (1) Political phenomena are not systematically predictable. Unforeseeable exceptions, which he compares to miracles, inevitably confound and threaten all rationalist political frameworks. An unrestrained political actor must be authorized to identify and confront them. (2) Legitimate authority requires requires a transcendent source. Divine command, or something like it, rather than the fundamentally groundless rational-legal norms generated by Kantian thought, is the only worthy and stable justification for political rule. In addition: (3) A polity is constituted by people who believe in it, not by persons for whom it provides a framework for the pursuit of rational self-interest. Human beings identify with, and often kill and die for, political communities on extrarational grounds; they do not, nor

5 should not, calculate costs and benefits for their own economic advancement or personal selfpreservation. Thus, while the idées générales governing European political thought and practice since the seventeenth century were justified in individualist terms, the return of concrete politics portends the preeminence of groups organized around specific ways of life, a point on which Strauss is in complete agreement. In his Zionist writings, Strauss associates individualism with assimilation, not with the life of a people properly understood. In the paper, I will also highlight important differences in the ways that Schmitt and Strauss draw upon theological resources: Strauss searches for the functional equivalent of a transcendent, universe-creating God, who, by existing absolutely apart from humanity, makes truly rational philosophizing possible and who can stand as the source of a politically appropriate, profound form of fear and reverence in ordinary people. On the contrary, Schmitt often upholds the incarnation, in his words, the fact that God became man in historical reality, as the phenomenon that sets humanity apart from mere physical matter, provides guidance on the contents of morality and presents a model for the personal form, in a very substantive sense, that political authority should take. Ultimately the two thinkers may diverge most on the question of conscience and its relationship to the human need for being ruled. Conscience, as such, is a target for Strauss; unlike the Law, conscience is an irredeemable source of philosophical degradation and political anarchy. For Schmitt, conscience can and should maintain a place of prominence in moral philosophy, so long as it remains subservient to the authority of transcendental divinity (made flesh in political form). Thus, unlike Heinrich Meier in his celebrated accounts of the two thinkers, I do not understand their differences in terms of a distinction between philosophy and theology, but rather

6 I understand them, more as Miguel Vatter and Nicholas Xenos do, as exhibiting two different forms of theologically influenced political philosophy, even if my assessment of the content and implications of their respective political theologies differ from those of these authors.