REVIEW. St. Thomas Aquinas. By RALPH MCINERNY. The University of Notre Dame Press 1982 (reprint of Twayne Publishers 1977). Pp $5.95.

Similar documents
Wisdom in Aristotle and Aquinas From Metaphysics to Mysticism Edmond Eh University of Saint Joseph, Macau

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

On Being and Essence (DE ENTE Et ESSENTIA)

P. Weingartner, God s existence. Can it be proven? A logical commentary on the five ways of Thomas Aquinas, Ontos, Frankfurt Pp. 116.

Peter L.P. Simpson December, 2012

by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB

PL 407 HISTORY OF MEDIEVAL PHILOSOPHY Spring 2012

William Hasker s discussion of the Thomistic doctrine of the soul

PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE LET THOMAS AQUINAS TEACH IT. Joseph Kenny, O.P. St. Thomas Aquinas Priory Ibadan, Nigeria

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

John Duns Scotus. 1. His Life and Works. Handout 24. called The Subtle Doctor. born in 1265 (or 1266) in Scotland; died in Cologne in 1308

270 Now that we have settled these issues, we should answer the first question [n.

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

Questions on Book III of the De anima 1

The Divine Nature. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 3-11) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian J.

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

On the Relation of Philosophy to the Theology Conference Seward 11/24/98

Robert Kiely Office Hours: Monday 4:15 6:00; Wednesday 1-3; Thursday 2-3

WHAT ARISTOTLE TAUGHT

Henry of Ghent on Divine Illumination

Thomas Aquinas on the World s Duration. Summa Theologiae Ia Q46: The Beginning of the Duration of Created Things

William Ockham on Universals

general development of both renaissance and post renaissance philosophy up till today. It would

ACTA PHILOSOPHICA, vol. 8 (1999), fasc. 1/recensioni

Anthony P. Andres. The Place of Conversion in Aristotelian Logic. Anthony P. Andres

Summer Preparation Work

PHILOSOPHY AS THE HANDMAID OF RELIGION LECTURE 2/ PHI. OF THEO.

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Philosophy of Nature, Philosophy of the Soul, Metaphysics

Spinoza s Modal-Ontological Argument for Monism

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Ethical non-naturalism

Descartes: A Guide for the Perplexed

Medieval Thought February Medieval Thought

Christian Evidences. The Verification of Biblical Christianity, Part 2. CA312 LESSON 06 of 12

Syllabus Medieval Philosophy PHL 262--Spring 2010 Michael R. Baumer, Course Instructor MW 4:00 to 5:50 Main Campus, Main Classroom Building, Room 326

Summula philosophiae naturalis (Summary of Natural Philosophy)

PHILOSOPHY ESSAY ADVICE

The question is concerning truth and it is inquired first what truth is. Now

Syllabus Medieval Philosophy PHL 262--Spring 2011 Michael R. Baumer, Course Instructor MWF 1:30-2:35 Main Campus, Main Classroom Building, Room 305

The Darkness and the Light: Aquinas in Conversation

Contextualizing Aquina's Ontology of Soul: An Analysis of His Arabic and Neoplatonic Sources

Aquinas on the Beginning and End of Human Life

A Review of Norm Geisler's Prolegomena

FOLLOWING CHRIST IN THE WORLD

Other Recommended Books (on reserve at library):

Building Systematic Theology

Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII. Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS. Book VII

Faith and Reason Thomas Aquinas

What We Are: Our Metaphysical Nature & Moral Implications

ever read the whole of the Summa. College graduates, especially students of religion and philosophy, may have studied a few selections, but somehow th

DOMINICAN UNIVERSITY COLLEGE

Thomas Aquinas The Treatise on the Divine Nature

St. Thomas Aquinas Excerpt from Summa Theologica

QUESTION 58. The Mode of an Angel s Cognition

PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY

Robert Kiely Office Hours: Tuesday 1-3, Wednesday 1-3, and by appointment

QUESTION 54. An Angel s Cognition

Metaphysical Problems and Methods

McKenzie Study Center, an Institute of Gutenberg College. Handout 5 The Bible and the History of Ideas Teacher: John A. Jack Crabtree.

Thomism The Philosophy of Thomas Aquinas

Aquinas' Principle of Individuation. Patrick W. Hughes Denison University

Self-Evidence in Finnis Natural Law Theory: A Reply to Sayers

QUESTION 3. God s Simplicity

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Chapter Six. Aristotle s Theory of Causation and the Ideas of Potentiality and Actuality

X/$ c Akadémiai Kiadó, Budapest, 2004 AQUINAS S VIEWS ON MIND AND SOUL: ECHOES OF PLATONISM. Patrick Quinn

Philosophy is dead. Thus speaks Stephen Hawking, the bestknown

Department of Philosophy. Module descriptions 2017/18. Level C (i.e. normally 1 st Yr.) Modules

Qué es la filosofía? What is philosophy? Philosophy

Divine command theory

TRUTH IN MATHEMATICS. H.G. Dales and G. Oliveri (eds.) (Clarendon: Oxford. 1998, pp. xv, 376, ISBN X) Reviewed by Mark Colyvan

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

An Analysis of the Proofs for the Principality of the Creation of Existence in the Transcendent Philosophy of Mulla Sadra

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Syllabus PHIL 1000 Philosophy of Human Nature Summer 2017, Tues/Wed/Thurs 9:00-12:00pm Location: TBD

QUESTION 55. The Medium of Angelic Cognition

St. Thomas quotes the opening lines of Avicenna s Metaphysics: ens and essentia are what is first conceived by the intellect. 2

ZAGZEBSKI ON RATIONALITY

On The Existence of God Thomas Aquinas

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011

GCE Religious Studies

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

A Christian Philosophy of Education

The thought of St. Thomas Aquinas continues to exercise and fascinate. Aquinas Medalist s Address. Anthony Kenny

THE PRINCIPLE OF ANALOGY IN PROTESTANT AND CATHOLIC THEOLOGY

PART TWO EXISTENCE AND THE EXISTENT. D. The Existent

Introduction: Paradigms, Theism, and the Parity Thesis

A CRITIQUE OF THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. A Paper. Presented to. Dr. Douglas Blount. Southwestern Baptist Theological Seminary. In Partial Fulfillment

Accessing the Moral Law through Feeling

The Names of God. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 12-13) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian Shanley (2006)

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Introduction to Philosophy

Are There Moral Facts

Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke,

The Summa Lamberti on the Properties of Terms

Proof of the Necessary of Existence

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Intro Viewed from a certain angle, philosophy is about what, if anything, we ought to believe.

Transcription:

REVIEW St. Thomas Aquinas. By RALPH MCINERNY. The University of Notre Dame Press 1982 (reprint of Twayne Publishers 1977). Pp. 172. $5.95. McInerny has succeeded at a demanding task: he has written a compact and lucid introduction to the philosophy of Aquinas that manages to be philosophical at the same time. By a liberal use of quotation and paraphrase McInerny presents Aquinas s own arguments for evaluation, drawing us into the inner works of his philosophy. This method, coupled with McInerny s sure touch, makes Aquinas speak directly and forcefully as a philosopher. McInerny s style remains cogent while ranging across a wide variety of topics; those unfamiliar with mediæval philosophy will find it an invaluable introduction. The seasoned scholar too will find plenty of interest here, such as McInerny s striking analysis of the praeambula fidei and his exquisite explanation of participated perfection. McInerny s format is unusual but effective. After a brief chapter in which he sketches the life of St. Thomas, McInerny presents Aquinas s philosophy in close connection with its various sources, devoting a chapter apiece to Aristotle, Boethius, and the platonism of Augustine and Pseudo- Dionysius. Such an approach allows McInerny to discuss many differing topics in a natural and coherent manner. The book concludes with a chapter on Aquinas s view of theology and its relation to both faith and philosophy. Certain themes are developed throughout, in particular the nature of metaphysics. Aristotle was not immediately accepted in the thirteenth century; in the eyes of many he seemed to teach doctrines inimical to the Christian faith. First, Aristotle seems to argue for the eternity of the world, a view incompatible with the doctrine of creation. McInerny gracefully presents Aquinas s well-known view that the eternity of the world can be neither proven nor disproven. Second, the so-called Latin Averroists read Aristotle as denying personal immortality in De anima 3.5. McInerny carefully proceeds through Aquinas s painstaking analysis and rejection of this as a tenable philosophical interpretation of Aristotle, based on the immaterial reception of forms in the intellect and the qualitative distinction of the sensitive and intellective faculties of the soul. Although McInerny mentions Aquinas s belief in immortality and the resurrection of the body, disappointingly he 1

2 Review does not give these reasons (for immortality see Summa theologiae Ia.75.6; the need for resurrection is grounded in the theory of the soul as an incomplete substance given in Ia.76.2 ad 2 and Ia.76.5). Aristotle s moral philosophy is distinctively non-christian; Aquinas adapted it for the faith by distinguishing natural and supernatural ends, thereby amplifying the Aristotelian framework. Here McInerny weaves several different texts together into a single presentation of the main tenets of Aquinas s ethics. What is distinctive about man as man is that he has free will and may choose his actions. By the doctrine of natural law certain selfevident moral principles are known to us, e. g. the first principle of practical reason, that the good should be pursued and evil avoided (Summa theologiae IaIIae.94.2). This leads to one of McInerny s more striking points, that theoretical moral knowledge moral science is generally useless, for the precepts of natural law and their consequences are too abstract to guide us in concrete situations. Rather, we require practical, not speculative, wisdom in knowing which course of action to adopt by means of the practical syllogism. McInerny also sees this as providing scope for free will: although we necessarily will the good, as the formal object of the will, we are not determined to any particular course of action. But here I must register my disagreement with McInerny; if we must choose the good then we will always choose the course of action which is best, and this is hardly free will. Duns Scotus recognized this point in his Opus Oxoniense IV d. 49 q. 10, and some have observed a change in St. Thomas himself (see Karl Riesenhuber, Die Transcendenz der Freiheit zum Guten, Munich 1971)., to seeing the will as the efficient rather that the material cause and the intellect as the final rather than the formal cause. McInerny does not take account of this. Nevertheless, he reviews Aquinas s argument that the good is single and identifies the ultimate final end as God and beatitude, thus christianizing Aristotle. McInerny next turns to St. Thomas s debt to Boethius, beginning with his early commentary on Boethius s De Trinitate, and in an extended discussion tries to specify the exact nature of metaphysics. The standard view of Aquinas takes metaphysics to be defined by degrees of abstraction, citing Aristotle (Metaphysics 6.1.8 10): physics deals only with matter and motion; mathematics with only matter; metaphysics with only being qua being. But McInerny notes that Aquinas only allows two forms of abstraction, namely the abstraction of a whole (proper to physics) and the abstraction

Review 3 of a form (proper to mathematics). Metaphysics, then, is not arrived at through either kind of abstraction. To resolve this dilemma, McInerny notes that abstractive judgements are one form of separatio (judgements of separation). He then suggests that, for Aquinas, metaphysics is characterized by the separative judgement that there are incorporeal items which exist, such as God and angels. If he is correct, then this can also serve as a polemical answer to those who see no need for a discipline beyond physics and mathematics. There is not much textual evidence, but McInerny makes a plausible case. To make his case, however, McInerny gives short shrift to the view that the separative judgement in question is that there is a real distinction between essence and existence. This view deserves a better hearing. McInerny does go on, though, to discuss this distinction, and to his credit not only gives the classic phoenix-argument from the De ente et essentia to establish the difference between essence and existence, but also gives the full technical argument from Aquinas s commentary on Boethius s De hebdomadibus, too often ignored by scholars. McInerny ends this chapter with some brief remarks about free will and determinism. McInerny then takes up the Platonism of Augustine and the Pseudo- Dionysius, separating such platonism into two components: the role of Ideas, and the nature of participation. When discussing the Ideas, McInerny first treats their ontological role in the problem of universals, and gives a concise outline of Aquinas s solution by the so-called doctrine of the three-fold universal. Here again I must say that platonic Ideas could not have solved the problem of universals as the problem was understood by Boethius, for the universal was meant to enter into the metaphysical constitution of the particular, which Ideas notoriously cannot do. Ideas are therefore irrelevant to the mediæval problem of universals. McInerny then treats of the epistemological role of Ideas in connection with the theories of abstraction and illumination. Finally, McInerny discusses participation in connection with the names of God and the distinction between essential and participated perfection. His discussion of these points is the finest I have ever read, and clearly states how the platonism St. Thomas rejected in most cases had to be employed when reasoning about God. This discussion alone is worth the price of the book. In the last chapter McInerny takes up Aquinas s views on theology. He starts by outlining the argument of Werner Jaeger that the Metaphysics

4 Review vacillates between two irreconcilable conceptions of metaphysics as the study of being qua being and as the study of God and so is not a unified work but rather a patchwork quilt of essays composed at different times. While acknowledging the useful results of the philological research that Jaeger inspired, McInerny gracefully illustrates Aquinas s view that metaphysics is in one sense theology and equally is the study of being qua being. Aquinas reconciles Jaeger s irreconcilable conceptions by denying the possibility of a science which alone studied God (preface to his commentary on Aristotle s Metaphysics). There is theology as metaphysics, which investigates the world according to the canons of philosophy, and there is theology as the study of revealed truths, but there is no philosophical science of God. With that, McInerny takes up several questions about theology and faith. He analyzes several senses of belief and knowledge, attending particularly to the analogical character of religious language, and then asks whether it is rational to believe the doctrines of the Christian faith. Here McInerny is excellent: he introduces St. Thomas s notion of the praeambula fidei, and notes that some propositions which are to be believed may also be known to the theologian. This has always seemed peculiar, but McInerny uses his earlier analysis of knowledge and belief to show how these propositions can be both known and believed, and then suggests that such propositions illustrate the rationality of faith: we can come to know in some instances that what is taught in Scripture is true we never discover that it teaches what is false; thus Scripture is known to be a reliable guide to truth. Therefore it is only rational to believe other propositions found in Scripture, even those which are in principle unverifiable in this life, just as it is rational to believe any reliable source. This discussion is clear, cogent, and remarkably persuasive. McInerny concludes by hoping that his book will cause the reader to turn to the works of Aquinas directly. He should have every confidence, for his presentation invites the reader to think through each issue and problem as it is raised. This work is a sine qua non for all those interested in mediæval philosophy. Some final words of caution. McInerny s translations are rarely wrong but they are sometimes misleading, for instance the translation of secundum quid as broadly speaking on p. 37, or the phrase on p. 50 which his power voluntarily produces according to his image, which should be translated

Review 5 as which proceeds from Divine Power according to his will. Second, there are several minor errors a more careful job of proofreading would have caught, the most serious of which is that Augustine is incorrectly said on p. 107 to have been born in 345 AD rather than 354 AD. And finally, there are many classical Thomistic theses about which McInerny says little or nothing: the unity of substantial form; the a posteriori proofs of God s existence in the Five Ways; the potential nature of prime matter; the primacy of the intellect over the will; matter as the principle of individuation. But McInerny s choice of theme is careful and judicious, and there is no reason to favour these theses over McInerny s selection. He has written, quite simply, the best short book on Aquinas available.