Studies in Buddhist Philosophy by Mark Siderits (review)

Similar documents
NEW BOOK> The Golden Age of Indian Buddhist Philosophy

Empty Words: Buddhist Philosophy and Cross-Cultural Interpretation (review)

Philosophy East and West, Volume 65, Number 3, July 2015, pp (Review) DOI: /pew

Against a Hindu God: Buddhist Philosophy of Religion in India (review)

PHILOSOPHY 191: PHILOSOPHY WITHOUT BORDERS: INDIA AND EUROPE Spring 2014 Emerson 310, Thursdays 2-4. Office Hours: TBA Office Hours: M 3-4, W 2-3

PHIL 445 / PHIL 510B / AAAS 482P: Buddhist Metaphysics Fall 2017

Skepticism and Internalism

Defending the Semantic Interpretation: A Reply to Ferraro

Perceiving Particulars-as-such Is Incoherent--A Reply to Mark Siderits

4/30/2010 cforum :: Moderator Control Panel

A (Very) Brief Introduction to Epistemology Lecture 2. Palash Sarkar

Emptiness Appraised: A Critical Study of Nagarjuna's Philosophy (review)

Is Klein an infinitist about doxastic justification?


Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

6AANA016 Indian Philosophy: The Orthodox Schools Syllabus Academic year 2012/3

The Truth of Nagarjuna: Something Beyond Nirvana

The Background of Indian Philosophy

PH 1000 Introduction to Philosophy, or PH 1001 Practical Reasoning

Elements of Mind (EM) has two themes, one major and one minor. The major theme is

Epistemology: A Contemporary Introduction to The Theory of Knowledge, by Robert Audi. New York: Routledge, 2011.

Philosophy Courses-1

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

BUDDHIST PHILOSOPHY. Office hours: I will be delighted to talk with you outside of class. Make an appointment or drop by during my office hours:

ROUGH OUTLINE FOR EMPTINESS, BUDDHISM, NAGARJUNA

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

Experience and Foundationalism in Audi s The Architecture of Reason

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece

McDowell and the New Evil Genius

Review of Aristotle on Knowledge and Learning: The Posterior Analytics by David Bronstein

Nāgārjuna and the Philosophy of Upāya by John Schroeder

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

Semantic Externalism, by Jesper Kallestrup. London: Routledge, 2012, x+271 pages, ISBN (pbk).

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27)

The form of relativism that says that whether an agent s actions are right or wrong depends on the moral principles accepted in her own society.

The Ethics of Śaṅkara and Śāntideva: A Selfless Response to an Illusory World

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

All philosophical debates not due to ignorance of base truths or our imperfect rationality are indeterminate.

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

Qualified Realism: From Constructive Empiricism to Metaphysical Realism.

What Should We Believe?

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

Access provided by National Taiwan University (10 Aug :00 GMT)

Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science

Courses providing assessment data PHL 202. Semester/Year

proper construal of Davidson s principle of rationality will show the objection to be misguided. Andrew Wong Washington University, St.

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

Examining the Bodhisattva s Brain

On Nāgārjuna s Ontological and Semantic Paradox

Epistemic Reduction: The Case of Arthāpatti

Let us begin by first locating our fields in relation to other fields that study ethics. Consider the following taxonomy: Kinds of ethical inquiries

5AANA009 Epistemology II 2014 to 2015

THE POSSIBILITY OF AN ALL-KNOWING GOD


David Copp, ed., The Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory, Oxford: Oxford University

1/8. Reid on Common Sense

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

REVIEW THE DOOR TO SELLARS

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Robert Audi, The Architecture of Reason: The Structure and. Substance of Rationality. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xvi, 286.

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

Review of Steven D. Hales Book: Relativism and the Foundations of Philosophy

SWINBURNE ON THE EUTHYPHRO DILEMMA. CAN SUPERVENIENCE SAVE HIM?

Transcript of teachings by Khen Rinpoche Geshe Chonyi

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

THE CHALLENGES FOR EARLY MODERN PHILOSOPHY: EDITORIAL INTRODUCTION 1. Steffen Ducheyne

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

PRELIMINARY. Asian Mahayana (Great Vehicle) traditions of Buddhism, Nagarjuna. easily resorted to in our attempt to understand the world.

From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Cory Juhl, Eric Loomis, Analyticity (New York: Routledge, 2010).

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Stout s teleological theory of action

Buddhism s Engagement with the World. April 21-22, University of Utah

Brandom s five-step program for modal health

Varieties of Apriority

Department of Philosophy. Module descriptions 2017/18. Level C (i.e. normally 1 st Yr.) Modules

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

Reply to Lorne Falkenstein RAE LANGTON. Edinburgh University

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999):

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Realism and the success of science argument. Leplin:

Course Intended Learning Outcomes (ILOs) Course ILOs

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

Transcription:

Studies in Buddhist Philosophy by Mark Siderits (review) Roy W. Perrett Philosophy East and West, Volume 68, Number 1, January 2018, pp. 1-5 (Review) Published by University of Hawai'i Press DOI: https://doi.org/10.1353/pew.2018.0032 For additional information about this article https://muse.jhu.edu/article/682224 Access provided by National Taiwan University (12 Apr 2018 09:14 GMT)

BOOK REVIEW Studies in Buddhist Philosophy. By Mark Siderits. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016. Pp. viii + 313. Hardcover $75.00, ISBN 978-0-19-875486-2. Reviewed by Roy W. Perrett Ashoka University roy.perrett@ashoka.edu.in Over the last few decades Mark Siderits has established himself as a leading philosophical interpreter of Indian Buddhist philosophy. He has published widely in this field, but three of his books are particularly well known: his Personal Identity and Buddhist Philosophy (2003), a self-styled essay in fusion philosophy ; his introductory textbook Buddhism as Philosophy (2007); and with Shōryū Katsura his translation and commentary, Nāgārjuna s Middle Way: Mūlamadhyamakakārikā (2013). Taken together, these three books offer a fuller sense of Siderits philosophical concerns with Buddhism. The concern with fusion philosophy is focused primarily on philosophical problem-solving and energetically quarries Buddhist philosophy for possible solutions to these universal problems. But Siderits is equally concerned with getting right the details of the classical Indian texts and making them accessible to non- Sanskritist philosophers through his translations, for successful fusion philosophy needs to be sensitive to the details of what was going on in the Indian philosophical tradition. The nineteen essays collected in Studies in Buddhist Philosophy are more directly concerned with Siderits second kind of concern than his first, insofar as they are usually focused on interpretive matters. But these interpretive endeavors are always motivated by larger systematic issues about how best to make progress on solving cross-cultural philosophical problems in epistemology, metaphysics and ethics. That the primary focus of most of the essays is interpretive, however, ensures that this book is not one for beginners in Indian Buddhist philosophy (Siderits own Buddhism as Philosophy is much better suited for that purpose). On the other hand, for those with some prior knowledge of the field this book offers an engaging and consistently thoughtprovoking set of essays. Of course, all of the essays here have been previously published. But Siderits has also provided new postscripts to connect the pieces together by showing thematic interrelations, and has frequently indicated with admirable intellectual honesty where he presently holds different views from those he originally expressed. Hence there is not only the usual convenience value of having all the old essays now available in one volume, there is also the opportunity to grasp better the architectonic of Siderits distinctive take on 1

Indian Buddhist philosophy. Finally, Jan Westerhoff s excellent editorial introduction to the volume very successfully sets the stage for all of this. The nineteen essays are divided into six groups. Part 1 of the book contains four essays on Madhyamaka and Anti-Realism, a theme that Siderits has devoted much attention to over the years. There he expounds his semantic interpretation of emptiness, according to which Madhyamaka is best understood as a form of anti-realism. On Siderits view, Mādhyamikas like Nāgārjuna do not intend to deny the effability of ultimate reality, but rather the intelligibility of the notion of a mind-independent nature of the world. This means that Madhyamaka is a kind of conventionalism, but one uncommitted to relativism a point that (in essay 1.2) Siderits argues was very well understood by Bhāviveka and the often devalued Svātantrika tradition. Moreover, this semantic interpretation of emptiness (signaled by Siderits slogan the ultimate truth is that there is no ultimate truth ) has soteriological implications: emptiness properly understood is supposed to free us from that most subtle form of grasping, our attachment to the idea of a final theory of the world. In contrast to the broadly empiricist strand in early Buddhism that is committed to a correspondence theory of truth, Madhyamaka instead draws inspiration from the spirit of the early Buddhist category error approach to the indeterminate (avyākata) questions. Part 2 consists of five essays on Logical and Metaphysical Problems. The first of these extends the discussion beyond Madhyamaka to address the Yogācāra-Sautrāntika school s tenet that the object of perception is a bare particular and hence all perception is non-conceptual. Replying to the objection that this would mean that (incoherently) there is nothing that it is like to perceive an object, Siderits argues that the Buddhists commitment to externalism about mental content allows them to evade this charge. Essay 2.2 discusses the Pudgalavādins, an early school of Buddhist thinkers who asserted the existence of a person (pudgala), who is neither reducible to the psycho-physical aggregates, nor entirely distinct from them. One modern interpretation of this notorious claim is that it might be effectively equivalent to the claim that such a person might supervene on the aggregates, but not be reducible to them. Siderits, however, rejects this as failing to provide the Pudgalavādins with the middle way they sought for between Abhidharma reductionism and non-buddhist self-theory though in a postscript he indicates he thinks that it would be more charitable to interpret the Pudgalavādins as espousing a emergentism about persons. Essay 2.3 is on causation and emptiness in early Madhyamaka, arguing that Nāgārjuna is right to suppose that nothing that arises in dependence on causes and conditions can possess intrinsic nature and thus be ultimately real. In a postscript, however, Siderits acknowledges that the viability of a Humean account of causation might allow for the possibility of causal relations between ultimately real entities. 2

Essay 2.4 addresses the case advanced by Jay Garfield and Graham Priest for a dialetheist interpretation of Nāgārjuna, i.e. one that takes him to be committed to the existence of true contradictions. Siderits view is that such an interpretation is both historically problematic and philosophically undesirable, insofar as it threatens to undermine Mādhyamikas extensive use of prasaṅga or reductio arguments. Essay 2.5 is also about the role of logic in Buddhist philosophy, but this time about the nature of inference (anumāna) and the old worry about whether the Indian syllogism is deductive or inductive. Siderits argues for there being two different perspectives on a standard Indian inference: one concerns what the facts might be, and the other concerns the cognizer s epistemic position. Appreciating this distinction will enable us to understand better what is going on in an Indian inferential situation. Part 3 focuses on philosophy of language, particularly the Buddhist nominalists doctrine of exclusion (apoha): roughly, the idea that the meaning of a kind term like cow is the exclusion of its exclusion class non-cow. A standard Indian objection to this theory is that it is circular, since we can only understand the meaning of non-cow if we already understand the meaning of cow. In reply Siderits appeals to the distinction between choice and term negation and in two essays explores in some detail how a combination of these two types of negation might allow the construction of ersatz universals from a base of pure particulars. Essay 3.3 explores a related, but different issue: the apparent absence of a sense-reference distinction in Indian philosophy of language. Siderits presents two counterexamples to this general claim: the way in which the Buddhist philosopher Dharmakīrti effectively distinguishes between the sense and reference of a predicative expression in his development of apoha theory, and the Prābhākara Mīmāṃsā theory of related designation, which holds that what is designated by a word in a sentence is already related. Part 4 of the book is concerned with epistemology. The first two essays in this section are on the Madhyamaka critique of epistemology, with 4.1 and 4.2 focusing, respectively, on Nāgārjuna s critique of pramāṇavāda epistemology in the Vigrahavyāvartanī and Candrakīrti s extension of this in the Prasannapadā. Essay 4.3 argues that classical Indian epistemology is externalist and denies the internalist thesis that to have knowledge one must know that one knows. Siderits believes that this suggestion coheres well with Nāgārjuna s critique of epistemological foundationalism. Part 5 is devoted to ethics. Essay 5.1 is on the problem of free will and moral responsibility and argues for a position Siderits calls Buddhist paleocompatiblism. The leading idea here is that, given the Buddhist doctrine of two truths, the form of determinism said to be incompatible with moral responsibility could only be true ultimately, whereas the claim that persons are 3

morally responsible can only be true conventionally. Hence nothing about responsibility can follow from the thesis of determinism. Essay 5.2 considers whether the structure of Buddhist ethics is better described as consequentalist or virtue theoretic. Siderits suggestion is that it is best described as a form of aretaic consequentialism, where the cultivation of the virtues is to be justified on consequentialist grounds as promoting the Buddhist end of reducing suffering and, ultimately, the attainment of liberation. Finally, Part 6 consists of two essays that discuss the relations between Buddhist and non-buddhist Indian philosophy. Essay 6.1 is concerned with the debate between the Nyāya realists and the Buddhist anti-realists, arguing once more that Indian epistemologies should be seen as externalist, rather than internalist. A consequence of this common feature is then claimed to be that (notwithstanding their other differences) both Naiyāyikas and Buddhists believe we can justifiably hold our beliefs without knowing that the justification obtains. Accordingly, the Madhyamaka thesis that the pramāṇas and prameyas are mutually interdependent cannot provide a master argument for emptiness. Essay 6.2 addresses the difference between Madhyamaka and Advaita Vedānta, two systems sometimes seen as closely aligned. Siderits argues, however, that while Advaita is a realist view with a theory of what is ultimately true, Madhyamika is an anti-realism that rejects any final theory of what is foundationally true. As I have already indicated, this is an admirable book: lucidly written, carefully argued, and philosophically inventive. Moreover, although philosophers in both India and the West are notoriously contrary creatures, I personally find much of it to be very persuasive. Predictably enough, however, I do not find all of Siderits claims equally compelling. For instance, while I agree that Indian epistemology can very broadly speaking be represented as externalist about justification, I think it also exhibits significant internalist features (particularly in later Nyāya). I also find Siderits explication (in Chs. 1.3 and 5.2) of the key Buddhist notion of suffering (duḥkha) to be implausibly intellectualistic. A different sort of reservation I have, though, is about what is left out of Indian Buddhist philosophy in Siderits account of it. Of course, any book on Indian Buddhist philosophy is going to have to be selective and there is nothing that an author has to apologize for in that. But it is also important to try to reconstruct the author s principles of selection. There is no discussion in Siderits writings, for example, of the extensive Buddhist debates about the nature of path (marga) and its attendant philosophical psychology that we find in both Abhidharma and in the bodhisattva manuals by Candrakīrti and Śantideva, notwithstanding that he refers frequently to those texts. Nor is there any attention paid to the metaphysical speculations about Buddhahood and its attributes to be found in Dharmakīrti and other Yogācāra authors. Nor is there even much philosophical concern shown for the problematic notions of karma 4

and rebirth. Indeed, readers from a traditional Buddhist background coming to Siderits work are likely to experience his vision of Indian Buddhist philosophy as a somewhat religiously desiccated one. This is not to suggest that Siderits simply ignores Buddhist soteriological concerns: on the contrary, he is frequently quite explicit about them. But usually only when they can be safely subsumed under the rubric of Buddhist ethics, which he views as a variety of ethical naturalism. Siderits brings to his fusion philosophy project his dual training in classical Indian philosophy and Western analytic philosophy. In recent years analytic philosophy (particularly in America) has often taken a naturalistic turn, insisting on philosophy s continuity with the methods of science and exhibiting a corresponding bias towards physicalism. In contrast, there is also much recent analytic work on the metaphysics of identity, change and material being, and on normative non-naturalism, for instance that is uncommitted to naturalism. But it is an (undefended) general commitment to philosophical naturalism that apparently determines Siderits vision of what is to be included in Indian Buddhist philosophy proper. This is clearly a disputable stand and any fusion philosopher of Siderits naturalistic persuasion who also wants to get the historical Indian texts right eventually has to address the following two questions. First, the exegetical question: just how naturalistic was Indian Buddhist philosophy? Second, the philosophical question: is naturalism philosophically adequate to addressing the issues central to Buddhist philosophy? With respect to the exegetical question, I take it to be relatively uncontroversial that there were both naturalistic and non-naturalistic strands of thought present in Indian Buddhist philosophy. But the full details of the relative weight of these surely remains open to debate. With respect to the philosophical question, those less impressed with the naturalistic turn in analytic philosophy will presumably be more sceptical about an affirmative answer than is Siderits. Whatever stand one takes on these crucial issues, however, Siderits fine work remains an important resource for anyone interested in engaging philosophically with Indian Buddhist philosophy. 5