Religion is Not Totally Irrelevant to Legal Ethics

Similar documents
Legal Ethics and the Suffering Client

The Lawyer's Moral Obligation of Justification

FURTHER REFLECTIONS ON THE ROLE OF RELIGION IN LAWYERING AND IN LIFE

The Ethical Lawyer Contradiction in Terms or Reality?

Marc James Asay v. Michael W. Moore

PHIL 202: IV:

An Introduction to Ethics / Moral Philosophy

24.00: Problems of Philosophy Prof. Sally Haslanger November 16, 2005 Moral Relativism

Two Approaches to Natural Law;Note

SPRING 2014 UNDERGRADUATE COURSE OFFERINGS

Chapter 2 Reasoning about Ethics

Aspects of Deconstruction: Thought Control in Xanadu

In his book Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong, J. L. Mackie agues against

90 South Cascade Avenue, Suite 1500, Colorado Springs, Colorado Telephone: Fax:

What are you studying? What is ethics? Why study ethics in PR?

Short Answers: Answer the following questions in one paragraph (each is worth 5 points).

"Who Are You To Judge Me?" John 20:19-31 April 11, Quasimodogeniti Good Shepherd Lutheran Church Boise, Idaho Pastor Tim Pauls

A Framework for Thinking Ethically

THE ETHICS OF STRATEGIC COMMUNICATION: WINTER 2009

Divine command theory

Keeping Faith in Community: A Pastoral Response and Ethical Argument

Aristotle's Theory of Friendship Tested. Syra Mehdi

UNITED STATES DISTRICT COURT

If a man is characteristically and temperamentally an irritable, ill-tempered and notoriously given to uncontrolled outbursts of passionate anger,

VATICAN II COUNCIL PRESENTATION 6C DIGNITATIS HUMANAE ON RELIGIOUS LIBERTY

University of New Hampshire Spring Semester 2016 Philosophy : Ethics (Writing Intensive) Prof. Ruth Sample SYLLABUS

Suppose... Kant. The Good Will. Kant Three Propositions

Christian Worldview and Ethics CRU Institute of Biblical Studies February 25 March 1, 2019 Instructor: Mark Liederbach

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

Any More from Heaven? [1]

Ethics (ETHC) JHU-CTY Course Syllabus

INTRODUCTION TO GUIDELINES FOR CHURCH DISCIPLINE

(i) Morality is a system; and (ii) It is a system comprised of moral rules and principles.

INTRODUCTORY HANDOUT PHILOSOPHY 13 FALL, 2004 INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY---ETHICS Professor: Richard Arneson. TAs: Eric Campbell and Adam Streed.

What Kind of Freedom Does Religion Need?

Legal Ethics Advisors and the Interests of Justice: Is an Ethics Advisor a Conscience or a Co- Conspirator?

MR. NELSON: Mr. Chief Justice, may it please the Court, counsel: I m somewhat caught up in where to begin. I think perhaps the first and most

Comment on Rule, Story, and Commitment in the Teaching of Legal Ethics, by Roger C. Cramton and Susan P. Koniak

I. Plato s Republic. II. Descartes Meditations. The Criterion of Clarity and Distinctness and the Existence of God (Third Meditation)

DISTRICT COURT OF APPEAL OF THE STATE OF FLORIDA FOURTH DISTRICT January Term 2006

The Literature of Civil Disobedience Response Sheet. Ralph Waldo Emerson is a significant American essayist, poet, and philosopher. He lived from 1803

A Word of Caution: Consequences of Confession

Consider... Ethical Egoism. Rachels. Consider... Theories about Human Motivations

Kant, Deontology, & Respect for Persons

Henry Lord Brougham, Written by Himself

Law and Authority. An unjust law is not a law

Ethical Theory. Ethical Theory. Consequentialism in practice. How do we get the numbers? Must Choose Best Possible Act

Ethical Theory for Catholic Professionals

Deontology: Duty-Based Ethics IMMANUEL KANT

Lecture 2: What Ethics is Not. Jim Pryor Guidelines on Reading Philosophy Peter Singer What Ethics is Not

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

HUME AND HIS CRITICS: Reid and Kames

Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule

Happiness and Personal Growth: Dial.

CAN WE BE HELD RESPONSIBLE FOR THE SINS OF OTHERS INCLUDING CHURCHES?, part 2 quotes

We begin our discussion, however, more than 400 years before Christ with the Athenian philosopher Socrates. Socrates asks the question:

Other Recommended Books (on reserve at library):

AMERICAN CENTER FOR LAW AND JUSTICE S MEMORANDUM OF LAW REGARDING THE CRIMINAL TRIAL OF ABDUL RAHMAN FOR CONVERTING FROM ISLAM TO CHRISTIANITY

Be not deceived. God is not mocked; for whatsoever a man soweth that shall he also reap. Galatians 6 v 7. THE TERRORIST. What does God have to say?

PHIL%13:%Ethics;%Fall%2012% David%O.%Brink;%UCSD% Syllabus% Part%I:%Challenges%to%Moral%Theory 1.%Relativism%and%Tolerance.

Critical Inquiries for a New American Century. Poisonous "Pieties" Serve The Enemies Of The People

SANDEL ON RELIGION IN THE PUBLIC SQUARE

The King s Trial, pt. 1 Matthew 26:57 68

Bishop s Report To The Judicial Council Of The United Methodist Church

The Colorado report: beyond the cheerleading

Adult Sunday School Lesson Summary for February 14, 2010 Released on Wednesday, February 10, "Declared by Peter"

Class 23 - April 20 Plato, What is Right Conduct?

HARE S PRESCRIPTIVISM

GENERAL DEPOSITION GUIDELINES

Ethical Relativism 1. Ethical Relativism: Ethical Relativism: subjective objective ethical nihilism Ice cream is good subjective

Criticizing Arguments

Definitions: Values and Moral Values

A primer of major ethical theories

Louisiana Law Review. Cheney C. Joseph Jr. Louisiana State University Law Center. Volume 35 Number 5 Special Issue Repository Citation

Huntingdon College W. James Samford, Jr. School of Business and Professional Studies

Religious Charities in Guardianship. A White Paper by Americans Against Abusive Probate Guardianship

George Bundy Smith - A Good Lawyer

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

WITNESSING. Discipleship 1 - Chapter 6

Faith-N-Focus : E-quip Your Faith

Philosophy 2: Introduction to Philosophy Section 4170 Online Course El Camino College Spring, 2015

Positivism, Natural Law, and Disestablishment: Some Questions Raised by MacCormick's Moralistic Amoralism

Introduction to Ethics MWF 2:30-3:20pm BRNG 1230

Interpreting Scripture/Interpreting Law

Conscientious Objectors--Religious Training and Belief--New Test [Umted States v'. Seeger, 380 U.S. 163 (1965) ]

Judaism without Ordinary Law: Toward a Broader View of Sanctification. In the second chapter of Judaism as a Civilization, Rabbi Mordecai M.

White Paper: Innocent or Inconclusive? Analyzing Abolitionists Claims About the Death

Lecture 12 Deontology. Onora O Neill A Simplified Account of Kant s Ethics

Originalism, the Why and the What

This Morals and Society course is all about ethics. What is ethics?

Making God a Liar. by Charles Grandison Finney The Penny Pulpit, May 26, 1850*

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

FAITH IN HUMAN RIGHTS

Effective Closing Arguments

STATE OF MICHIGAN COURT OF APPEALS

Ethics is subjective.

IN COURT OF APPEALS DECISION DATED AND RELEASED NOTICE. August 19, No STAN SMITH, INC., PLAINTIFF-APPELLANT,

The Limits of Civil Authority

The Pleasure Imperative

The Role of Inconsistency in the Death of Socrates 1

Transcription:

Maurice A. Deane School of Law at Hofstra University Scholarly Commons at Hofstra Law Hofstra Law Faculty Scholarship 3-1998 Religion is Not Totally Irrelevant to Legal Ethics Monroe H. Freedman Maurice A. Deane School of Law at Hofstra University Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarlycommons.law.hofstra.edu/faculty_scholarship Recommended Citation Monroe H. Freedman, Religion is Not Totally Irrelevant to Legal Ethics, 66 Fordham L. Rev. 1299 (1998) Available at: https://scholarlycommons.law.hofstra.edu/faculty_scholarship/42 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarly Commons at Hofstra Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Hofstra Law Faculty Scholarship by an authorized administrator of Scholarly Commons at Hofstra Law. For more information, please contact lawcls@hofstra.edu.

RELIGION IS NOT TOTALLY IRRELEVANT TO LEGAL ETHICS Monroe H. Freedman* rrhere is a familiar story about three stonemasons, each of whom Xis asked what he is doing. The first replies, "I am making a wall." The second says, "I am helping to construct a building." The third answers, "I am helping to build a great cathedral to celebrate the glory of God." What if we asked the same question of three lawyers, "What are you doing?" The first might reply, "I am trying a case." The second, "I am serving my client." And the third, "I am participating in the administration of justice." I think we would all agree that there is a significant progression in the self-defining responses of the stonemasons. But how about the lawyers' answers? Is it clear that there is a progression-in religious terms-in the way the lawyers see themselves? The Bible tells us: "Justice, justice shalt thou follow...."i The third lawyer, then, is fulfilling a religious precept by participating in the pursuit of justice. But what about the second lawyer? Is his function any less significant, religiously? If we take seriously the injunction, "[L]ove thy neighbor as thyself," 2 then it seems to me that the simple service of one's client is the essence of religion, as well as of justice. Professor Leslie Griffin has written, "If too much emphasis is given to the lawyer's theological beliefs, the lawyer may lose sight of her client's interests." ' 3 I would rephrase that to say, "If a lawyer loses sight of her client's interests, she has almost certainly lost sight of her theological beliefs as wel." '4 My first point, then, is that even people who share the same or similar religious traditions can disagree over which religious precepts are more important. And it can matter. For example, if you needed a lawyer, would you rather be represented by the third lawyer or the second? 5 * Lichtenstein Distinguished Professor of Legal Ethics, Hofstra University Law School. Author, Understanding Lawyers' Ethics (1990). 1. Deuteuronomy 16:20 (The Holy Scriptures, Jewish Publication Society of America 1955). Biblical citations are to The Holy Scriptures (Jewish Publication Society of America 1955) unless otherwise indicated. 2. Leviticus 19:18. 3. Leslie H. Griffin, The Relevance of Religion to a Lawyer's Work: Legal Ethics, 66 Fordham L. Rev. 1261 (1998). 4. See Monroe H. Freedman, Legal Ethics and the Suffering Client, 36 Cath. U. L Rev. 331 (1987). 5. Or consider a variation suggested by Professor Russell G. Pearce: The third lawyer says, "I am celebrating the glory of God by aiding in the administration of justice." Would that make you feel more sanguine about being represented by the third lawyer? 1299

1300 FORDHAM LAW REVIEW [Vol. 66 My next point can be illustrated through a true story. Several years ago, a friend expressed his disappointment that he could never serve on a jury. At that time, the jury commission where we lived used a questionnaire that asked, among other things, whether the potential juror had moral objections to the death penalty. Anyone answering yes to that question was automatically disqualified from serving. Because my friend believed, as a matter of religious conviction, that human life is sacred and that its preservation is paramount to all other moral values, he responded in the affirmative and was disqualified each time he submitted the questionnaire. I suggested to my friend that his conduct was inconsistent with his asserted moral priorities. The preservation of human life was not paramount for him-telling the truth to the jury commission was. Because of his scruples about answering the questionnaire truthfully, he had been making it impossible for himself to serve on a jury and, as a juror, to vote against death. After reflection, my friend decided to lie on the next jury questionnaire. It happens that my friend was a reform rabbi, and his religious beliefs helped him to reach his decision. But not all religious people-in fact, not all religious Jews-would make the same decision. Indeed, I imagine that there are Jews, Protestants, and Catholics (to say nothing of Kantians) who would find lying to a court to be a shocking matter, regardless of the consequentialist justification. 6 My point is that religion doesn't "answer" such dilemmas-not, at any rate, in a predictable or consistent way. Moreover, conflicting religious precepts can create dilemmas of conscience' as readily as can conflicting precepts of legal ethics. I recently spoke at a gathering of lawyers and others interested in law and religion. Most of those present were shocked at my argument that a criminal defense lawyer could ethically present perjured testimony. 8 Their shocked response is hardly surprising: False swearing is condemned by religion as well as by law, lawyers' ethics, and philosophy. Yet, as Professor Griffin notes, all religions also "condemn... the breaking of solemn promises." 9 What, then, is my obligation regarding my client's perjury when I have given him my solemn promise not to divulge what he tells me in confidence? When my client admits to 6. After lying to the jury commission, it would be necessary to lie again in court during voir dire. 7. Professor Griffin refers to "dilemmas of the individual attorney's conscience," but I understand her to mean dilemmas between religious morality and legal ethics. See Griffin, supra note 3, at 1256. 8. See, e.g., Monroe H. Freedman, Understanding Lawyers' Ethics 108-42 (1990) (explaining why it is ethical for a criminal defense lawyer to present perjured testimony) [hereinafter Freedman, Understanding Lawyers' Ethics]. 9. Griffin, supra note 3, at 1279 n.83 and accompanying text (quoting Ronald M. Green, Religion and Moral Reason: A New Method for Comparative Study 11 (1988)).

1998] LEGAL ETHICS 1301 me that he intends to testify falsely about his involvement in the crime, should I present my client's perjury to the court as truthful testimony, or should I tell the judge that my client is lying and thereby break my promise to my client? Religion, like legal ethics, presents the moral dilemma. And, like legal ethics, religion gives no clear answer to that dilemma. 10 Another point: Professor Griffin should be more careful about what she wishes for. "I think," she says, "that philosophical and religious ethics should have equal status in the legal profession."" That thought conjures up an image of Oliver Twist asking, please, sir, for some more porridge. True, the occasional moral philosopher wanders into the literature of legal ethics, but I challenge anyone to demonstrate a single significant effect that any such moral philosopher has had on any particular issue of legal ethics. Reluctantly, I have pretty much given up the effort of trying to teach moral philosophy (including discussion of God and of Natural Law) in my legal ethics course. The students' lack of interest is matched only by their almost universal and invincible commitment to cultural relativism. I once spent the better part of a class session trying to identify a single moral precept that the students could agree was universally true, a single horrific act or practice that they could agree was wrong regardless of time and place. Slavery and genocide, sadly enough, are too familiar to jolt them into responding. So, at a time when most people had not yet heard about the horrors of clitoridectomy and infibulation, I described those practices. The students were indeed shocked, but not a single one would condemn the practice as wrong on the part of those people who accept it as part of their custom or religion. As one student explained, "You have to be tolerant." "At last," I exclaimed in genuine excitement, "a universal principle: One must be tolerant!" And the students readily agreed on that one. So I said to a bright student (the one who had first posited the principle), "Okay, over there in that comer is a man who is about to perform the ritual torture and murder of a baby. And over there, in that corner, is a man who is about to be extremely intolerant of the first man's act. You can stop one of them, but not both. Quick! Which one do you stop?" When she hesitated and then avoided a direct answer, I realized just how hopeless the whole discussion was. Professor Griffin elaborates her wish by adding, "If utilitarianism and Kantianism, consequentialism and deontology, are becoming 10. The possible ways of dealing with the problem are analyzed in Understanding Lawyers' Ethics. Freedman, Understanding Lawyer's Ethics, supra note 8, at 109-22. 11. Remarks of Professor Leslie Griffin at the Conference, The Relevance of Religion to a Lawyer's Work, Fordham University, June 1-3, 1997; cf Griffin, supra note 3, at 1254 ("In this essay I argue that the academic discipline of religious studies at least should have equal status in legal ethics with philosophy.").

1302 FORDHAM LAW REVIEW [Vol. 66 standard ethical terms for lawyers, then lawyers should learn that the religious ethical traditions are also comprehensible, not merely personal or private accounts of morality." 2 In fact, those terms of moral philosophy are no more "standard ethical terms for lawyers" than they are for health-care managers or professional wrestlers. It is undoubtedly true that for a lawyer who takes both her profession and her religion seriously (in the sense of expressing or fulfilling what is at the core of her self), then, for that lawyer, her religious ethical tradition will inform her professional life and her decisions about legal ethics. But her religious ethical tradition will do so only in what Professor Griffin disparages as a "merely personal or private" account of morality. That is, the lawyer will be applying, in a personal or private way, her understanding of her religious tradition to resolve issues of legal ethics. The alternative-to use religious ethical traditions to decide issues of legal ethics in a public and communal way-seems to me to be neither practical nor desirable. Part of the problem, of course, is the use of the treacherous term "traditions" in this context. Whose traditions and whose formulations and interpretations of those traditions are we to use? For example, Professors Sanford Levinson and Russell Pearce have succeeded in persuading Professor Griffin that there is a serious question whether an observant Jew could be a criminal defense lawyer, or any other kind of lawyer, in the American legal system.' 3 They do this by manipulating the word "tradition," as in "[t]he Jewish tradition's general hostility to an adversarial role." 14 Thus, Professors Levinson and Pearce factitiously establish a Jewish tradition hostile to adversarial lawyering through critical remarks about legal practice by a medieval Jewish scholar and a seventeenth century rabbi,' 5 and by the fact that "only in 1960 did the Israeli rabbinate formally accept[ ] practices permitting legal counsel to argue on behalf of either litigant."' 6 Indeed, Professor Pearce asserts this Jewish tradition hostile to adversarial lawyers even while acknowledging that "Jewish courts have permitted lawyers since the 12. Id. at 1271. 13. Id. at 1256 & n.9. 14. Id. (quoting Russell G. Pearce, The Jewish Lawyer's Question, 27 Tex. Tech L. Rev. 1259, 1265 (1996)); see also Sanford Levinson, Identifying the Jewish Lawyer: Reflections on the Construction of Professional Identity, 14 Cardozo L. Rev. 1577, 1607 (1993). 15. Not surprisingly, the quotations are similar to modem criticisms of lawyers, for example: A lawyer is a "legal manipulator... concerned less with absolute fidelity to the law than with crafting ostensibly legal arguments that would enable the client to prevail against an adversary." Pearce, supra note 14, at 1265 (quoting Levinson, supra note 14, at 1598-99). If such quotes prove anything about traditional legal practice, of course, it is that legal practice at the time-which the scholar described as well as decried-was in fact highly adversarial. 16. Pearce, supra note 14, at 1265 (internal quotations omitted).

1998] LEGAL ETHICS 1303 middle ages."' 7 Note also the point-ambiguous at best-that the Jewish rabbinate in Israel formally accepted legal counsel to argue in 1960. That was, after all, only twelve years after the founding of Israel, and before the Supreme Court of the United States recognized a right to appointed counsel in criminal cases involving imprisonment. 8 By similar reasoning, of course, we can question whether Christian tradition permits an observant Protestant or Catholic to be a lawyer. Who could be a lawyer in the face of the condemnation: "Woe unto you also, ye lawyers! for ye lade men with burdens grievous to be borne, and ye yourselves touch not the burdens with one of your fingers," 19 and "Woe unto you, lawyers! for ye have taken away the key of knowledge...." 0 Thus, religious tradition would make non-lawyers of us all. Finally, I want to correct Professor Griffin's misrepresentation of my position on morality in lawyering. She makes this error in an earlier article in the Georgetown Journal of Legal Ethics.?' In her present paper, Professor Griffin refers to David Luban for "the dominant view" or "standard conception" of lawyering, in which the lawyer bears no moral responsibility for her representation of a client. 2 As 17. Id. 18. Argersinger v. Hamlin, 407 U.S. 25 (1972); Gideon v. Wainwright, 372 U.S. 335 (1963). 19. Luke 11:46 (King James). 20. Luke 11:52 (King James). 21. Leslie Griffin, The Lawyer's Dirty Hands, 8 Geo. J. Legal Ethics 219, 225-27 (1995). There are other errors of scholarship in that article. For example, referring to my defense of the adversary system, Professor Griffin primarily cites Monroe H. Freedman, Lawyers' Ethics in an Adversary System (1975). That book, however, simply describes, rather than defends, the adversary system. Professor Griffin makes no reference to my more recent book, Understanding Lawyers' Ethics, which includes a thirty-page chapter that explains and defends the adversary system. Freedman, Understanding Lawyers' Ethics, supra note 8, at 13-42. Also, Professor Griffin discusses an article that I originally published in 1966. See Griffin, supra, at n.36. The article she discusses is Professional Responsibility of the Criminal Defense Lawyer: The Three Hardest Questions, 64 Mich. L Rev. 1469 (1966). Her only cited source for that article, however, is an anthology published twenty years thereafter. Thus, when she says (correctly) that my analysis in the article is based in part on the ABA's 1908 Canons of Professional Ethics, she makes it appear that I neglected the ABA's 1969 Model Code of Professional Responsibility, which actually was not promulgated until three years after my article had been written. Again, she makes no reference to Understanding Lawyers' Ethics, in which I analyzed the same issues in the context of both the Model Code and the Model Rules. 22. Griffin, supra note 3, at 1254 & n.2. Professor Griffin relies on David Luban, Lawyers and Justice: An Ethical Study (1988), which incorrectly asserts that I support the "dominant picture." Luban's discussion, however, and even his bibliography, omits any reference to the principal article I have written on that subject. See Monroe H. Freedman, Personal Responsibility in a Professional System, 27 Cath. U. L Rev. 191 (1978). Ironically, that article originated as the Pope John XXIII Lecture, and is one of the few law review articles that includes citations to religious sources.

1304 FORDHAM LAW REVIEW [Vol. 66 stated by Professor Murray Schwartz, who originated the analysis, 23 under the Principles of Professionalism and Nonaccountability, the lawyer is "beyond reproof for acting on behalf of the client" and is totally "immun[e] from [moral] accountability." 24 I, however, have repeatedly rejected that view, for example: Because my own position has been misunderstood in the past, let me reiterate it. Lawyers are morally accountable. A lawyer can be "called to account" and is not "beyond reproof" for the decision to accept a particular client or cause. Also, while representing a client, the lawyer should counsel the client regarding the moral aspects of the representation. If a lawyer chooses to represent a client, however, it would be immoral as well as unprofessional for the lawyer, either by concealment or coercion, to deprive the client of lawful rights that the client elects to pursue after appropriate counseling. 25 Some readers may be surprised to learn that the position expressed in that paragraph-that lawyers are morally accountable for the decision to accept a particular client or cause-is highly controversial. That position has been denounced as "worse than absurd," "dangerous," and "pernicious." A law professor who specializes in ethics (and is deeply committed to his religion) wrote to inform me that "Joe Mc- Carthy would be proud of you." 26 Right or wrong, at least those critics are objecting to what I have said, rather than presenting and criticizing a position that I do not hold. CONCLUSION Professor Griffin pleads that religious ethics be given equal status with moral philosophy in the legal profession. 7 In fact, religious eth- Also, I have expanded and updated that analysis in chapter three of Understanding Lawyers' Ethics ("The Lawyer's Virtue and the Client's Autonomy"), which was published seven years ago. See Freedman, Understanding Lawyers' Ethics, supra note 8, ch. 3; see also Monroe H. Freedman, The Lawyer's Moral Obligation of Justification, 74 Tex. L. Rev. 111 (1995) [hereinafter Freedman, Moral Obligation]; Monroe H. Freedman, Legal Ethics and the Suffering Client, 36 Cath. U. L. Rev. 331 (1987). All but the last of these were published before Professor Griffin's article in the Georgetown Journal of Legal Ethics. See Leslie Griffin, The Lawyer's Dirty Hands, 8 Geo. J. Legal Ethics 219 (1995). 23. Murray L. Schwartz, The Professionalism and Accountability of Lawyers, 66 Cal. L. Rev. 669 (1978); Murray L. Schwartz, The Zeal of the Civil Advocate, in The Good Lawyer 151 (David Luban ed., 1984) [hereinafter Schwartz, Zeal of the Civil Advocate]. 24. Schwartz, Zeal of the Civil Advocate, supra note 23, at 151. 25. Freedman, Understanding Lawyers' Ethics, supra note 8, at 71 (citing David Luban, Lawyers and Justice (1988)); see also citations supra note 22. 26. See Freedman, Moral Obligation, supra note 22, at 115 n.20; Monroe Freedman, The Morality of Lawyering, Legal Times, Sept. 20, 1993, at 22; see also Monroe Freedman, Must You Be the Devil's Advocate?, Legal Times, Aug. 23, 1993, at 19 (discussing whether a lawyer should represent a client or position that the lawyer finds morally objectionable). 27. Running through Professor Griffin's paper is the assumption that legal ethics needs religion because the legal profession is in serious and unprecedented trouble.

1998] LEGAL ETHICS 1305 ics already has equal status with philosophy, which is to say, virtually none. And that is probably a good thing. Yes, I like to think that my religion informs and enriches my professional life,' just as it informs and enriches my life in general. Also, I accept the possibility-but only the possibility-that people who are religious are better people than they would otherwise be. 29 But among Jews-just as among Christians-there is so much disagreement about what constitutes "tradition" and "ethics" that I am skeptical about how useful it would be for the organized Bar to attempt to apply anything called "religious ethics" to the essentially public endeavor of fashioning and enforcing rules of professional conduct for lawyers. Better, I think, for religion to remain what Professor Griffin denigratingly calls "merely personal or private accounts of morality.1 30 Griffin, supra note 3, at 1264 & n.27, 1267. She apparently gets that idea from such fatuous works as Anthony T. Kronman, The Lost Lawyer Failing Ideals of the Legal Profession (1993). But see Roger C. Cramton & Susan P. Koniak, Rule, Story, and Commitment in the Teaching of Legal Ethics, 38 Wm. & Mary L Rev. 145, 184-85, 193-97 (1996) (providing devastating commentary on Dean Kronman's book); Monroe Freedman, The Good Old Days, for Good Old Boys, Legal Tunes, Feb. 28, 1994, at 31 (arguing that the legal profession's idealized past, to which some commentators yearn to return, was not all that ideal). 28. See Monroe H. Freedman, Legal Ethics from a Jewish Perspective, 27 Tex. Tech L. Rev. 1131 (1996) (N.B. the indefinite article in the title). 29. Professor Griffin assumes that religious commitment can only make a positive contribution. Griffin, supra note 3, at 1257-58. The unhappy fact is that deep religious commitment is also a characteristic of Ayatollahs, Grand Inquisitors, and a prophet who hacked a chained prisoner into pieces. 30. Id. at 1271.

Notes & Observations